This paper was converted on www.awesomepapers.org from LaTeX by an anonymous user.
Want to know more? Visit the Converter page.

A Crystal Analysis of PP-Arrays

Henry Ehrhard
Abstract.

Gasharov introduced the combinatorial objects known as PP-arrays to prove ss-positivity for the chromatic symmetric functions of incomparability graphs of (3+1)-free posets. We define a crystal, a directed colored graph with some additional axioms, on the set of PP-arrays. The components of the crystal have ss-positive characters, thereby refining the ss-positivity theorems of Gasharov, as well as Shareshian and Wachs. The crystal hints at a possible generalization of the Robinson-Schensted correspondence applied to PP-arrays.

1. Introduction

The chromatic symmetric function generalizes the chromatic polynomial of a graph [Sta95]. The Stanley-Stembridge Conjecture [SS93, Conjecture 5.5] states that the chromatic symmetric function of the incomparability graph of a (3+1)-free poset is a positive sum of elementary symmetric functions. The conjecture has long motivated research into the chromatic symmetric functions of these graphs.

In particular, Gasharov showed the weaker result that these symmetric functions are a positive sum of Schur functions, or are “ss-positive” [Gas96]. This was accomplished by reinterpreting the chromatic symmetric functions as generating functions for PP-arrays, a combinatorial object corresponding to proper colorings. Moreover, the coefficients of the expansion into Schur functions can be stated in terms of PP-arrays.

Stanley expressed the desire for a direct bijective proof of Gasharov’s result, which would generalize the Robinson-Schensted correspondence [Sta98]. A better understanding of Gasharov’s result could help in addressing the natural suspicion that it holds for the larger class of claw-free graphs [Sta98, Conjecture 1.4]. Some thought has gone towards finding such a Robinson-Schensted correspondence for PP-arrays [Mag92],[SWW97],[Cho99],[KP21] but the problem in its full generality remains open. Among the immediate consequences of this hypothetical correspondence would be a way to interpret each Schur function in the chromatic symmetric function as an explicit generating function for PP-arrays in its own right.

In this paper we similarly aim to refine the chromatic symmetric function as a sum of smaller ss-positive generating functions. Crystals where introduced by Kashiwara [Kas90] and have often served as a paradigm for interpreting and achieving ss-positivity results, in part due to their connection with the representation theory of Lie groups. We thus construct a crystal on the set of PP-arrays. The crystal determines a sign-reversing involution, similar to the one in Gasharov’s proof, which we use to show that the crystal components have ss-positive character. This refines the ss-positivity theorem of Gasharov.

Guay-Paquet reduced the Stanley-Stembridge Conjecture to the case of unit interval orders [GP13]. More recently, Shareshian and Wachs’ defined a quasisymmetric generalization of the chromatic symmetric function which, when applied to incomparability graphs of natural unit interval orders, suggests a strengthened version of the conjecture and yields an analogously refined ss-positivity theorem [SW16]. We show that our crystal is also applicable to this quasisymmetric setting, further refining the ss-positivity theorem. Shareshian and Wachs use an involution similar to Gasharov’s, but more efficient in some sense. By the same measure, our involution is optimal.

Our goals are similar to [KP21] which, subject to additional poset avoidance conditions that are conjectured to be unnecessary, refines ss-positivity of chromatic quasisymmetric functions for natural unit interval orders. The paper also presents a Robinson-Schensted correspondence in this case. In comparison, our work more generally deals with underlying (3+1)-free posets without additional constraints.

We begin in Section 2 by reviewing the necessary context around PP-arrays and the chromatic symmetric function. In Section 3 we will explain what we mean by a crystal and discuss the diagram crystal defined in [Ass22]. In Section 4 we will define the rr alignment of a PP-array which is a sort of “pairing rule” that will allows us to define the crystal on PP-arrays in Section 5. The ss-positivity property of this crystal will be proved in Section 6, and its applicability to the chromatic quasisymmetric function for natural unit interval orders demonstrated in Section 7. Finally, in Section 8 we will attempt to push our construction further by writing individual Schur functions in the expansion as generating functions when they correspond to partitions of length 1 or 2, even when our PP-array crystal does not tell us how to do so.

This last development relies heavily on the diagram crystal in [Ass22], and the proof is fundamentally bijective which means it can be viewed as a sort of partial Robinson-Schensted correspondence. We are interested to see if the bijection can be extended to partitions of greater lengths. There is also the question of whether a crystal like ours can be defined on the proper colorings of an arbitrary claw-free graph, which would prove ss-positivity of their chromatic symmetric functions.

2. Chromatic Symmetric Functions

A proper coloring of a graph G=(V,E)G=(V,E) is a map κ:V+\kappa:V\to{\mathbb{Z}}_{+} such that κ(v)κ(w)\kappa(v)\neq\kappa(w) whenever (v,w)E(v,w)\in E. An independent subset of VV contains no two elements that form an edge. Proper colorings κ:V+\kappa:V\to{\mathbb{Z}}_{+} are then equivalently defined by requiring that κ1(i)\kappa^{-1}(i) is an independent subset for all i+i\in{\mathbb{Z}}_{+}.

Definition 2.1.

[Sta95] The chromatic symmetric function of a finite graph GG is given by

XG(x)=κvVxκ(v)X_{G}(x)=\sum_{\kappa}\prod_{v\in V}x_{\kappa(v)}

where the sum is over all proper colorings of GG.

It is evident that these functions are indeed symmetric.

Given a poset (P,P)(P,\leq_{P}), its incomparability graph, denoted inc(P)\operatorname{inc}(P), has vertex set PP and edges (u,v)(u,v) whenever uu and vv are incomparable in PP, henceforth denoted by uvu\parallel v. See Fig. 1 for an example of a poset and its incomparability graph. Notice that independent subsets of inc(P)\operatorname{inc}(P) are precisely the chains in PP. That is, there is a canonical ordering on any independent subset. This observation motivates the following definition of objects that correspond to proper colorings of the incomparability graph.

aabbccddeeffgghh
aabbccddeeffgghh
Figure 1. The Hasse diagram (left) and incomparability graph (right) of a (3+1)-free poset.
Definition 2.2.

[Gas96] Let (P,P)(P,\leq_{P}) be a finite poset. A PP-array is an indexing {Ai,j}\{A_{i,j}\} of the elements of PP such that if Ai,jA_{i,j} is defined with j>1j>1 then Ai,j1A_{i,j-1} is also defined and Ai,j1<PAi,jA_{i,j-1}<_{P}A_{i,j}. We let 𝒜P\mathcal{A}_{P} denote the set of PP-arrays.

We visualize a PP-array {Ai,j}\{A_{i,j}\} as the placement of the elements of PP on a grid indexed by matrix convention, where Ai,jA_{i,j} is placed in position (i,j)(i,j). Fig. 2 shows two PP-arrays for the poset in Fig. 1.

\ytableausetupcentertableaux{ytableau}h&d\noneafegbc\ytableausetupcentertableaux{ytableau}a&bcdfghe\none\none\none\vline\ytableausetup{centertableaux}\ytableau h&d\\ \none\\ af\\ e\\ gbc\\ \hskip 100.0pt\vline\ytableausetup{centertableaux}\ytableau a&bcdf\\ ghe\\ \none\\ \none\\ \none\\
Figure 2. Two PP-arrays with the one on the right being a PP-tableau.

Given a PP-array {Ai,j}\{A_{i,j}\}, the corresponding proper coloring of κ:P+\kappa:P\to{\mathbb{Z}}_{+} of inc(P)\operatorname{inc}(P) is defined by κ(Ai,j)=i\kappa(A_{i,j})=i. Given a proper coloring κ:P+\kappa:P\to{\mathbb{Z}}_{+}, the corresponding PP-array is obtained by letting Ai,1,Ai,2,,Ai,kA_{i,1},A_{i,2},\ldots,A_{i,k} be the elements of κ1(i)\kappa^{-1}(i) in increasing order. The weight of a PP-array AA is the weak composition 𝐰𝐭(A)\mathbf{wt}(A) whose iith part is the number of elements in row ii. If κ\kappa is the corresponding proper coloring then 𝐰𝐭(A)i=#κ1(i)\mathbf{wt}(A)_{i}=\#\kappa^{-1}(i) so we realize that

Xinc(P)=A𝒜Pi1xi𝐰𝐭(A)i.X_{\operatorname{inc}(P)}=\sum_{A\in\mathcal{A}_{P}}\prod_{i\geq 1}x_{i}^{\mathbf{wt}(A)_{i}}.

Developing these combinatorial objects further, we have the following definition.

Definition 2.3.

[Gas96] Let (P,P)(P,\leq_{P}) be a poset. A PP-tableau is a PP-array with the additional constraint that whenever Ai,jA_{i,j} is defined with i>1i>1, then Ai1,jA_{i-1,j} is also defined and Ai1,jPAi,jA_{i-1,j}\not>_{P}A_{i,j}.

The second PP-array in Fig. 2 is a PP-tableau. We see that the weight of a PP-tableau is a partition in general, i.e. if TT is a PP-tableau then 𝐰𝐭(T)i𝐰𝐭(T)i+1\mathbf{wt}(T)_{i}\geq\mathbf{wt}(T)_{i+1} for all i1i\geq 1.

A poset is (aa+bb)-free, for natural numbers aa and bb, if it does not contain as an induced subposet the disjoint union of a aa-chain with a bb-chain. The poset in Fig. 1 is (3+1)-free for instance.

Let sλs_{\lambda} denote the Schur function indexed by a partition λ\lambda. We say a symmetric function is ss-positive if it is a sum of Schur functions. A graph is said to be ss-positive if its chromatic symmetric function is. The following theorem by Gasharov now reveals the motivation behind the definition of PP-tableaux.

Theorem 2.4.

[Gas96] Let (P,P)(P,\leq_{P}) be a (3+1)-free poset. Then Xinc(P)=λcλsλX_{\operatorname{inc}(P)}=\sum_{\lambda}c_{\lambda}s_{\lambda} where cλc_{\lambda} is the number of PP-tableaux of weight λ\lambda. In particular, inc(P)\operatorname{inc}(P) is ss-positive.

The theorem and its proof don’t give us an idea of which monomials (PP-arrays) “contribute” to which Schur functions (PP-tableaux) in any canonical way. Our primary goal in this paper is then to refine this result by developing a finer structure on PP-arrays for a more localized explanation of ss-positivity.

3. Crystals

A crystal is a colored directed graph consisting of the data (,er,fr,𝐰𝐭)(\mathcal{B},e_{r},f_{r},\mathbf{wt}). Here \mathcal{B} is a vertex set. For all r1r\geq 1 the functions er,fr:{0}e_{r},f_{r}:\mathcal{B}\to\mathcal{B}\cup\{0\} called the crystal raising and lowering operators respectively, must satisfy er(u)=ve_{r}(u)=v if and only if fr(v)=uf_{r}(v)=u. The map 𝐰𝐭:\mathbf{wt}:\mathcal{B}\to{\mathbb{Z}}^{\ast} is the weight map where {\mathbb{Z}}^{\ast} is the set of {\mathbb{Z}}-valued sequences with finitely many nonzero entries. Letting αr=(0,,0,1,1,0,)\alpha_{r}=(0,\ldots,0,1,-1,0,\ldots) with the 1 as the rrth entry, whenever ei(u)=ve_{i}(u)=v we also require that 𝐰𝐭(v)=𝐰𝐭(u)+αr\mathbf{wt}(v)=\mathbf{wt}(u)+\alpha_{r}. The character of a crystal with vertex set \mathcal{B} is

char()=vi1xi𝐰𝐭(v)i.\mathrm{char}(\mathcal{B})=\sum_{v\in\mathcal{B}}\prod_{i\geq 1}x_{i}^{\mathbf{wt}(v)_{i}}.

Finally, a highest weight element of a crystal with vertex set \mathcal{B} is some vv\in\mathcal{B} such that er(v)=0e_{r}(v)=0 for all r1r\geq 1. A more comprehensive description of crystals can be found in [BS17].

Be warned that we will overload the symbols er,fre_{r},f_{r} and 𝐰𝐭\mathbf{wt} to be used on multiple vertex sets. However, there should be no ambiguity as it will be clear to which vertex set the maps are being applied.

In the following sections we will define a crystal (𝒜P,er,fr,𝐰𝐭)(\mathcal{A}_{P},e_{r},f_{r},\mathbf{wt}) for any (3+1)-free poset (P,P)(P,\leq_{P}), with 𝐰𝐭:𝒜P\mathbf{wt}:\mathcal{A}_{P}\to{\mathbb{Z}}^{\ast} as already defined. We see that char(𝒜P)\mathrm{char}(\mathcal{A}_{P}) coincides with Xinc(P)X_{\operatorname{inc}(P)} and is therefore ss-positive by Theorem 2.4. Showing that the character of any connected component of the crystal is ss-positive therefore generalizes this result, which is exactly what we intend to do. It will take us until Section 5 to define the operators ere_{r} and frf_{r} for this crystal, and until Section 6 to prove the refined ss-positivity result.

3.1. The Diagram Crystal

For the remainder of this section we will discuss Assaf’s diagram crystal [Ass22]. This is not a prerequisite for understanding anything up through Section 7. However, it may be a helpful example of a crystal with nice properties, and it is necessary for Section 8 where we partially succeed in pushing our refinement of Theorem 2.4 even further.

By a diagram we mean a finite subset of +×+{\mathbb{Z}}_{+}\times{\mathbb{Z}}_{+} which we will interpret as positions in a grid using matrix convention. The elements of a diagram are referred to as its cells. We let 𝒟\mathcal{D} denote the set of diagrams. The weight map on 𝒟\mathcal{D} is defined so that 𝐰𝐭(D)i\mathbf{wt}(D)_{i} is the number of cells in row ii of DD.

Definition 3.1.

[Ass22] Let DD be a diagram and r+r\in{\mathbb{Z}}_{+}. The set of rr-pairs of DD is a set of disjoint pairs of cells between rows rr and r+1r+1 defined iteratively as follows. We say that two unpaired cells xx and yy in rows rr and r+1r+1 respectively with xx weakly left of yy form an rr-pair whenever every other cell in rows rr and r+1r+1 in a column weakly between xx and yy is already part of an rr-pair.

Definition 3.2.

[Ass22] We define er:𝒟𝒟{0}e_{r}:\mathcal{D}\to\mathcal{D}\cup\{0\} on D𝒟D\in\mathcal{D} as follows. If every cell in row r+1r+1 of DD is rr-paired then er(D)=0e_{r}(D)=0. Otherwise, take (r+1,c)(r+1,c) to be the rightmost cell in row r+1r+1 of DD that is not rr-paired and set er(D)=(D{(r+1,c)}){(r,c)}e_{r}(D)=(D\setminus\{(r+1,c)\})\cup\{(r,c)\}. That is, we “move” the cell (r+1,c)(r+1,c) to row rr.

Definition 3.3.

[Ass22] Given the above definition, the crystal lowering operator fr:𝒟𝒟{0}f_{r}:\mathcal{D}\to\mathcal{D}\cup\{0\} is implicitly defined as follows. Let D𝒟D\in\mathcal{D}. If every cell in row rr of DD is rr-paired then fr(D)=0f_{r}(D)=0. Otherwise, take (r,c)(r,c) to be the leftmost cell in row rr of DD that is not rr-paired and set fr(D)=(D{(r,c)}){(r+1,c)}f_{r}(D)=(D\setminus\{(r,c)\})\cup\{(r+1,c)\}.

Fig. 3 shows the diagrams reachable from {(1,1),(1,2),(2,2),(2,3)}𝒟\{(1,1),(1,2),(2,2),(2,3)\}\in\mathcal{D} using only edges colored 1 and 2.

{}_{~{}} {}_{~{}} {}_{~{}} {}_{~{}}
{}_{~{}} {}_{~{}} {}_{~{}} {}_{~{}}
{}_{~{}} {}_{~{}} {}_{~{}} {}_{~{}}
{}_{~{}} {}_{~{}} {}_{~{}} {}_{~{}}
{}_{~{}} {}_{~{}} {}_{~{}} {}_{~{}}
{}_{~{}} {}_{~{}} {}_{~{}} {}_{~{}}
222211112211
Figure 3. A portion of the diagram crystal.

We will also find useful the notion of column cc-pairing which is defined similarly to rr-pairing.

Definition 3.4.

[Ass22] Let DD be a diagram and c+c\in{\mathbb{Z}}_{+}. The column cc-pairing of DD is an iterative construction where we say that two cells xx and yy in columns cc and c+1c+1 respectively with xx in a row weakly below that of yy are column cc-paired whenever every other cell in columns cc and c+1c+1 in a row weakly between xx and yy is already column cc-paired.

The following is a consequence of [Ass22, Theorem 4.2.5].

Proposition 3.5.

The diagram crystal raising and lowering operators do not change the number of column cc-pairs.

We will find this proposition applicable when a diagram DD shares a connected component in the crystal with a diagram DD^{\prime} that is “top-justified”, i.e. such that when (r,c)D(r,c)\in D with r>1r>1 we have (r1,c)D(r-1,c)\in D as well. In this case, Proposition 3.5 implies every cell in the shorter of the two columns cc and c+1c+1 is column cc-paired.

A second invariant of components in the diagram crystal that we will find useful is given by the next lemma.

Lemma 3.6.

Let DD be a diagram and consider sequences of cells (r1,c1),,(rk,ck)(r_{1},c_{1}),\ldots,(r_{k},c_{k}) in DD such that ri<ri+1r_{i}<r_{i+1} and cici+1c_{i}\leq c_{i+1}. The maximal length of such a sequence is unchanged by the crystal raising and lowering operators.

Proof.

Suppose (r1,c1),,(rk,ck)D(r_{1},c_{1}),\ldots,(r_{k},c_{k})\in D is a sequence of cells in a diagram DD with ri<ri+1r_{i}<r_{i+1} and cici+1c_{i}\leq c_{i+1} of maximal length. We will show that there is such a sequence of cells of length kk in er(D)e_{r}(D) if er(D)0e_{r}(D)\neq 0.

The only way this might not be the case is if r+1=rir+1=r_{i} for some 1ik1\leq i\leq k and ere_{r} were to remove (ri,ci)(r_{i},c_{i}) from DD. In this case, we have (ri1,ci)er(D)(r_{i}-1,c_{i})\in e_{r}(D). Unless i>1i>1 and ri1=ri1r_{i-1}=r_{i}-1, we get another sequence of cells in er(D)e_{r}(D) with the desired properties by simply replacing (ri,ci)(r_{i},c_{i}) in the sequence with (ri1,ci)(r_{i}-1,c_{i}). So assume i>1i>1 and ri1=ri1r_{i-1}=r_{i}-1.

We know (ri,ci)(r_{i},c_{i}) is not rr-paired in DD. Then (ri1,ci1)(r_{i-1},c_{i-1}) must be rr-paired with some (ri,d)(r_{i},d) with ci1d<cic_{i-1}\leq d<c_{i}. Replacing (ri,ci)(r_{i},c_{i}) in the sequence (r1,c1),,(rk,ck)(r_{1},c_{1}),\ldots,(r_{k},c_{k}) with (ri,d)(r_{i},d) then gives us a sequence in er(D)e_{r}(D) of length kk with the desired properties.

It is similar to show that if fr(D)0f_{r}(D)\neq 0 then fr(D)f_{r}(D) has such a sequence of cells of length kk. ∎

Once again considering the cases of a component containing a top-justified diagram, the lemma says that the maximal length of a sequence of cells as described above is the maximal number of cells in a column.

Assaf’s Theorem 5.3.4 specializes to the following statement.

Theorem 3.7.

[Ass22] Let DD be a top-justified diagram. Then the character of the component of the diagram crystal containing DD is s𝐰𝐭(D)s_{\mathbf{wt}(D)}. Additionally, DD is the unique highest weight element in its connected component.

Remark 3.8.

The theorem as presented in [Ass22] actually shows that there is a crystal isomorphism between the relevant components of the diagram crystal and a tableaux crystal. The diagrams in a given component are then in weight preserving bijection with semi-standard Young tableaux of shape 𝐰𝐭(D)\mathbf{wt}(D).

4. The rr Alignment

For the remainder of this paper, (P,P)(P,\leq_{P}) is always a finite (3+1)-free poset. In this section we will introduce the rr alignment of a PP-array. The rr alignment will be fundamental for defining the crystal operators on PP-arrays in Section 5. It is a way of horizontally spacing out the elements of rows rr and r+1r+1, and can be thought of as a “pairing rule,” analogous to the idea of rr-pairs for the diagram crystal, which helps us determine how ere_{r} and frf_{r} affect rows rr and r+1r+1.

Definition 4.1.

Let AA be a PP-array and let r1r\geq 1. Let the chains a1<P<Pama_{1}<_{P}\cdots<_{P}a_{m} and b1<P<Pbnb_{1}<_{P}\cdots<_{P}b_{n} be the elements of rows rr and r+1r+1 of AA respectively. Let C:{a1,,am,b1,,bn}+C:\{a_{1},\ldots,a_{m},b_{1},\ldots,b_{n}\}\to{\mathbb{Z}}_{+} be the function inductively defined so that C(bk)=kC(b_{k})=k for each 1kn1\leq k\leq n, and

C(ak)=max({C(bi)bi<Pak}{C(ai)1i<k})+1.C(a_{k})=\max(\{C(b_{i})\mid b_{i}<_{P}a_{k}\}\cup\{C(a_{i})\mid 1\leq i<k\})+1.

Then we define the rr pre-alignment of AA to be the map

{a1,,am,b1,,bn}{r,r+1}×+\{a_{1},\ldots,a_{m},b_{1},\ldots,b_{n}\}\to\{r,r+1\}\times{\mathbb{Z}}_{+}

such that each aka_{k} maps to (r,C(ak))(r,C(a_{k})), and each bkb_{k} to (r+1,C(bk))(r+1,C(b_{k})).

Fig. 4 shows a visualization of the rr pre-alignment for a PP-array AA if PP is as in Fig. 1, row rr of AA contains the elements b,c,db,c,d and row r+1r+1 contains a,ha,h.

\ytableausetup

mathmode, centertableaux,boxsize=1.5em{ytableau} \none[r]&\none\nonebcd
\none[r+1]\noneah

Figure 4. An rr pre-alignment for a PP-array with PP as in Fig. 1.
Definition 4.2.

Let AA be a PP-array and let r1r\geq 1. Let the chains a1<P<Pama_{1}<_{P}\cdots<_{P}a_{m} and b1<P<Pbnb_{1}<_{P}\cdots<_{P}b_{n} be the elements of rows rr and r+1r+1 of AA respectively. Let ϕ0\phi_{0} be the rr pre-alignment. We construct the rr alignment of AA as follows.

Suppose we have some ϕk:{a1,,am,b1,,bn}{r,r+1}×+\phi_{k}:\{a_{1},\ldots,a_{m},b_{1},\ldots,b_{n}\}\to\{r,r+1\}\times{\mathbb{Z}}_{+}. Select the rightmost element xx mapped to some (i,c)(i,c) such that column c+1c+1 of ϕk\phi_{k} is nonempty and contains no y>Pxy>_{P}x, if such an xx exists. Then we define

ϕk+1:{a1,,am,b1,,bn}{r,r+1}×+\phi_{k+1}:\{a_{1},\ldots,a_{m},b_{1},\ldots,b_{n}\}\to\{r,r+1\}\times{\mathbb{Z}}_{+}

so that ϕk+1(x)=(i,c+1)\phi_{k+1}(x)=(i,c+1) and ϕk+1\phi_{k+1} coincides with ϕk\phi_{k} elsewhere. If no such xx exists then the rr alignment of AA is defined to be ϕk\phi_{k}.

Fig. 5 shows the rr alignment for a PP-array with rows rr and r+1r+1 as in Fig. 4.

\ytableausetup

mathmode, centertableaux,boxsize=1.5em{ytableau} \none[r]&\none\nonebcd
\none[r+1]\nonea\noneh

Figure 5. The rr alignment for a PP-array with PP as in Fig. 1.
Proposition 4.3.

The rr alignment of a PP-array AA is well-defined. Additionally, if a1<P<Pama_{1}<_{P}\cdots<_{P}a_{m} and b1<P<Pbnb_{1}<_{P}\cdots<_{P}b_{n} are the elements of rows rr and r+1r+1 of AA respectively, then in the rr alignment each aia_{i} is in a column strictly left of ai+1a_{i+1} and each bib_{i} is in a column strictly left of bi+1b_{i+1}.

Proof.

Our attention is restricted entirely to rows rr and r+1r+1 of AA. That the rr pre-alignment ϕ0\phi_{0} satisfies the condition on a1,,ama_{1},\ldots,a_{m} and b1,,bnb_{1},\ldots,b_{n} is immediate from the definition. Let dd be the rightmost occupied column in the rr pre-alignment. Suppose we have ϕk\phi_{k} as in Definition 4.2 that satisfies the condition on a1,,ama_{1},\ldots,a_{m} and b1,,bnb_{1},\ldots,b_{n}, and the rightmost occupied column of ϕk\phi_{k} is dd.

Should these inductive hypotheses continue to hold, we will have shown that the process to determine the rr alignment must terminate, as we are limited by dd in how far we can shift each element to the right. The other obstacle to well-definiteness is the question of whether xx, as in the definition, is unique when it exists. To this end, consider some column cc in ϕk\phi_{k} which contains two elements, some aia_{i} and bjb_{j}. If column c+1c+1 contains an element in ϕk\phi_{k} then by assumption it is either ai+1a_{i+1} or bj+1b_{j+1}. Thus, there is at most one element in column cc for which there is no greater element in column c+1c+1. This indeed proves that xx is uniquely determined when it exists.

Now suppose xx exists and resides in some column cc of ϕk\phi_{k}. By choice of xx, column c+1c+1 is nonempty in ϕk\phi_{k}, so c<dc<d. In ϕk+1\phi_{k+1} we know xx is mapped to column c+1c+1, so any column right of dd remains unoccupied. Moreover, if x=aix=a_{i} for some 1im1\leq i\leq m, then by the inductive hypothesis ai1a_{i-1} (if it exists) is strictly left of column cc in both ϕk\phi_{k} and ϕk+1\phi_{k+1}. If ai+1>Pxa_{i+1}>_{P}x exists then it is strictly right of column c+1c+1 of ϕk\phi_{k} and ϕk+1\phi_{k+1} using both the inductive hypothesis and the choice of xx. The same argument can be made when x=bix=b_{i} for some 1in1\leq i\leq n. Then the inductive hypothesis on a1,,ama_{1},\ldots,a_{m} and b1,,bnb_{1},\ldots,b_{n} continues to hold. ∎

Lemma 4.4.

In the rr alignment of a PP-array AA, any element in row r+1r+1 that does not share a column with an element in row rr is strictly left of any element in row rr that does not share a column with an element in row r+1r+1.

Proof.

This is clear for the row rr pre-alignment. Prior to moving an element from some column cc to column c+1c+1 while obtaining the rr alignment, column cc must contain an element in each row while column c+1c+1 contains exactly one element. Thus, the property is maintained as we move elements to the right. ∎

In Section 5 we will define our crystal operators on 𝒜P\mathcal{A}_{P} using the rr alignment. To prove that our operators are essentially inverses as required, we will want to see that they act predictably on the rr alignment. This motivates us to write a more static characterization of the rr alignment, as opposed to the procedural definition.

Definition 4.5.

Let AA be a PP-array. Let the chains a1<Pa2<P<Pama_{1}<_{P}a_{2}<_{P}\cdots<_{P}a_{m} and b1<Pb2<P<Pbnb_{1}<_{P}b_{2}<_{P}\cdots<_{P}b_{n} be the elements of rows rr and r+1r+1 of AA respectively. A weak rr alignment of AA is a map ϕ:{a1,,am,b1,,bn}{r,r+1}×+\phi:\{a_{1},\ldots,a_{m},b_{1},\ldots,b_{n}\}\to\{r,r+1\}\times{\mathbb{Z}}_{+} satisfying the following properties:

  1. (1)

    each aia_{i} is mapped to row rr in a column strictly right of ai1a_{i-1} if it exists, and each bib_{i} is mapped to row r+1r+1 in a column strictly right of bi1b_{i-1} if it exists,

  2. (2)

    if ϕ\phi maps an element to some column c>1c>1, then it also maps an element to column c1c-1,

  3. (3)

    if x<Pyx<_{P}y with xx mapped to row r+1r+1 and yy mapped to row rr then xx is mapped to a column strictly left of yy, and

  4. (4)

    if some xx is mapped to some column cc, then either ϕ\phi maps some y>Pxy>_{P}x to column c+1c+1 or it maps no elements to column c+1c+1.

Definition 4.6.

Let AA be a PP-array. Let the chains a1<Pa2<P<Pama_{1}<_{P}a_{2}<_{P}\cdots<_{P}a_{m} and b1<Pb2<P<Pbnb_{1}<_{P}b_{2}<_{P}\cdots<_{P}b_{n} be the elements of rows rr and r+1r+1 of AA respectively. Let ϕ,ψ:{a1,,am,b1,,bn}{r,r+1}×+\phi,\psi:\{a_{1},\ldots,a_{m},b_{1},\ldots,b_{n}\}\to\{r,r+1\}\times{\mathbb{Z}}_{+}. We write ϕψ\phi\preceq^{*}\psi when the position of each element in ϕ\phi is in a column weakly left of its position in ψ\psi. This defines a partial order on such maps. If ϕ\phi and ψ\psi are weak rr alignments of AA we write ϕψ\phi\preceq\psi.

Proposition 4.7.

Let AA be a PP-array and r1r\geq 1. The rr alignment is the unique minimal weak rr alignment according to the partial order \preceq.

Proof.

That the rr alignment satisfies (1) and (4) follows by definition. Property (3) is clear in the pre-alignment, and xx can never be shifted right into a column containing yy. So (3) holds in the alignment as well.

Let ϕ0\phi_{0} denote the rr pre-alignment. For every element in a column c>1c>1 of ϕ0\phi_{0} there is a lesser element in column c1c-1. Therefore there is some chain of elements in consecutive columns x1<P<Pxx_{1}<_{P}\cdots<_{P}x_{\ell} where x1x_{1} is in the first column and xx_{\ell} is in the rightmost nonempty column, call it dd. No element can move right of dd as we construct the rr alignment, and therefore each element in the chain x1<P<Pxx_{1}<_{P}\cdots<_{P}x_{\ell} is in the same position in the rr alignment. This proves that the rr alignment satisfies (2), and is therefore a weak rr alignment.

Now let ψ\psi be a weak rr alignment. For any aka_{k} there is some sequence

b1,,bj,ai,,akb_{1},\ldots,b_{j},a_{i},\ldots,a_{k}

(possibly with j=0j=0) that is increasing in P\leq_{P} and occupy consecutive columns in the rr pre-alignment, similarly to above. By properties (1) and (3), each element in this sequence must be in a column strictly right of the preceding one in ψ\psi. Thus, the position of aka_{k} in ψ\psi is weakly right of its position in the rr pre-alignment. The same is certainly true for each bkb_{k} so ϕ0ψ\phi_{0}\preceq^{\ast}\psi.

Let ϕk\phi_{k} be an intermediate step between the rr pre-alignment and rr alignment as in Definition 4.2, and assume ϕkψ\phi_{k}\preceq^{\ast}\psi. Suppose there exists a rightmost xx in ϕk\phi_{k} such that the adjacent column to its right is nonempty and contains no element greater than xx. We will show xx lies strictly right in ψ\psi of its position in ϕk\phi_{k}. This is true if xx is in the rightmost nonempty column of ψ\psi, which is weakly right of the rightmost nonempty column of ϕk\phi_{k}, which is in turn strictly right of xx in ϕk\phi_{k}. Otherwise, there is some y>Pxy>_{P}x one column right of xx in ψ\psi by (4).

Say xx lies in column cc in ϕk\phi_{k}. If yy lies in a column strictly right of cc in ϕk\phi_{k}, it must be in column c+ic+i for some i2i\geq 2 by choice of xx. Then yy lies strictly right of column c+i1c+i-1 in ψ\psi which means xx lies strictly right of c+i2cc+i-2\geq c in ψ\psi.

Suppose instead yy lies in some column weakly left of cc in ϕk\phi_{k}. Then xx and yy lie in opposite rows. However, this means any element right of xx in ϕk\phi_{k} is greater than xx which contradicts our choice of xx. By induction we can now say that ϕk+1ψ\phi_{k+1}\preceq^{\ast}\psi. Then if ϕk\phi_{k} is the rr alignment we have ϕkψ\phi_{k}\preceq\psi. ∎

Using Proposition 4.7, we end the section with a final useful lemma.

Lemma 4.8.

If the rr alignment of AA maps a unique element xPx\in P to some column cc, then any element strictly left of cc is smaller than any element weakly right of cc in the rr alignment.

Proof.

Let yy be an element strictly left of cc, and zz an element weakly right of cc. If yy and zz share a row, then y<Pzy<_{P}z by (1) in Definition 4.5. We have y<Pxy<_{P}x by (4) in Definition 4.5, so if zz shares a row with xx we have y<Pzy<_{P}z as well. Thus, assume yy shares a row with xx and zz does not.

If zz is in row r+1r+1, let zz^{\prime} be the element in the same column of row rr which exists by Lemma 4.4. We have zPzz\not<_{P}z^{\prime} by (3) in Definition 4.5 so y<Pzy<_{P}z by the (3+1)-free condition.

Otherwise, it suffices to assume zz is the leftmost element in row rr in a column strictly right of cc. If zz does not share a column with any element in row rr then once again we have y<Pzy<_{P}z by (4) in Definition 4.5. So suppose we have some zz^{\prime} in the same column as zz in row r+1r+1. If we had yPzy\not<_{P}z in this circumstance, that would imply z<Pzz<_{P}z^{\prime} by the (3+1)-free condition, and also xPzx\not<_{P}z. Then moving the position of zz one column to the left would still satisfy conditions (1)-(4) in Definition 4.5, contradicting Proposition 4.7. ∎

5. The PP-Array Crystal

We now have the tools to define the crystal operators on 𝒜P\mathcal{A}_{P}.

Definition 5.1.

The crystal lowering operator fr:𝒜P𝒜P{0}f_{r}:\mathcal{A}_{P}\to\mathcal{A}_{P}\cup\{0\} acts on A𝒜PA\in\mathcal{A}_{P} as follows. Let a1<P<Pama_{1}<_{P}\cdots<_{P}a_{m} and b1<P<Pbnb_{1}<_{P}\cdots<_{P}b_{n} be the entries of rows rr and r+1r+1 of AA respectively.

  • If every column of the rr alignment with an entry in row rr also contains an entry in row r+1r+1 then define fr(A)=0f_{r}(A)=0.

  • Otherwise let pp be minimal such that apa_{p} does not share a column with an element in row r+1r+1 in the rr alignment. Let t0t\geq 0 be minimal such that there is no bi>Pap+tb_{i}>_{P}a_{p+t} one column right of ap+ta_{p+t}. Then we move ap,,ap+ta_{p},\ldots,a_{p+t} to row r+1r+1, and any bib_{i} that shares a column with one of these entries to row rr.

Proposition 5.2.

The crystal lowering operator frf_{r} is well-defined, and if we have A𝒜PA\in\mathcal{A}_{P} with fr(A)0f_{r}(A)\neq 0 then 𝐰𝐭(fr(A))=𝐰𝐭(A)αr\mathbf{wt}(f_{r}(A))=\mathbf{wt}(A)-\alpha_{r}.

Proof.

Let A𝒜PA\in\mathcal{A}_{P} and let a1<P<Pama_{1}<_{P}\cdots<_{P}a_{m} and b1<P<Pbnb_{1}<_{P}\cdots<_{P}b_{n} be the entries of rows rr and r+1r+1 of AA respectively. Select apa_{p} as in the definition, assuming it exists. By Lemma 4.4 every nonempty column strictly right of the column containing apa_{p} in the rr alignment must contain an entry in row rr. In particular, there is no bib_{i} in any column strictly right of ama_{m} and it therefore makes sense to select t0t\geq 0 as in the definition. The entries ap,,ap+ta_{p},\ldots,a_{p+t} reside in consecutive columns of the rr alignment by Lemma 4.4 and property (1) of weak rr alignments, and for each 0i<t0\leq i<t there is some bjPap+ib_{j}\not>_{P}a_{p+i} that shares a column with ap+i+1a_{p+i+1} by choice of tt. Let q1q\geq 1 be minimal such that either bqb_{q} lies in a column strictly right of apa_{p} or does not exist. The relevant columns of the rr alignment are then as in Fig. 6 (which degenerates to just the column containing apa_{p} if t=0t=0).

\ytableausetup

mathmode, centertableaux,boxsize=2.5em{ytableau} ap&ap+1ap+2⋯ap+t
\nonebqbq+1⋯bq+t-1

Figure 6. The columns in the alignment of AA whose entries are to be row swapped by frf_{r}.

We must show

  1. (i)

    bq1<Papb_{q-1}<_{P}a_{p}

  2. (ii)

    ap+t<Pbq+ta_{p+t}<_{P}b_{q+t}

  3. (iii)

    ap1<Pbqa_{p-1}<_{P}b_{q}

  4. (iv)

    bq+t1<Pap+t+1b_{q+t-1}<_{P}a_{p+t+1}

whenever these indices are valid. The point being that (i) and (ii) show row r+1r+1 of fr(A)f_{r}(A) is a chain, and (iii) and (iv) show row rr of fr(A)f_{r}(A) is a chain. When t=0t=0 we need not consider (iii) or (iv).

We have (i) immediately from Lemma 4.8. If bq+tb_{q+t} is one column right of ap+ta_{p+t} then (ii) follows by choice of ap+ta_{p+t}. Otherwise, by Lemma 4.4 there is some ap+t+ia_{p+t+i} with i>2i>2 that shares a column with bq+tb_{q+t}. By (3) in Definition 4.5, bq+tPap+t+ib_{q+t}\not<_{P}a_{p+t+i} so we get (ii) by the (3+1)-free condition.

If t0t\neq 0 we know ap+t1Pbq+t1a_{p+t-1}\not<_{P}b_{q+t-1} so (iv) follows from the (3+1)-free condition. By property (3) in Definition 4.5 we have bqPap+1b_{q}\not<_{P}a_{p+1} so (iii) follows from the (3+1)-free condition.

Fig. 6 makes clear that 𝐰𝐭(fr(A))=𝐰𝐭(A)αr\mathbf{wt}(f_{r}(A))=\mathbf{wt}(A)-\alpha_{r}. ∎

Lemma 5.3.

Let AA be a PP-array. Let ap<P<Pap+ta_{p}<_{P}\cdots<_{P}a_{p+t} and bq<P<Pbq+t1b_{q}<_{P}\cdots<_{P}b_{q+t-1} be the elements whose rows are swapped by frf_{r} as in Fig. 6. Then ap+i+1bq+ia_{p+i+1}\parallel b_{q+i} for each 0i<t0\leq i<t.

Proof.

We have ap+iPbq+ia_{p+i}\not<_{P}b_{q+i} by choice of ap+ta_{p+t}, thus ap+i+1Pbq+ia_{p+i+1}\not<_{P}b_{q+i}. Since ap+i+1a_{p+i+1} shares a column with bq+ib_{q+i} in the rr alignment, we have ap+i+1Pbq+ia_{p+i+1}\not>_{P}b_{q+i} by property (3) in Definition 4.5. ∎

As with the crystal lowering operator, we will soon define the crystal raising operator using the rr alignment of a PP-array. To eventually see that these two operations are inverses, we then want to know how frf_{r} affects the rr alignment. The answer is given by the following lemma.

Lemma 5.4.

Applying frf_{r} to a PP-array AA does not change the column of any entry in the rr alignment.

Proof.

Let a1<Pa2<P<Pama_{1}<_{P}a_{2}<_{P}\cdots<_{P}a_{m} and b1<Pb2<P<Pbnb_{1}<_{P}b_{2}<_{P}\cdots<_{P}b_{n} be the entries of rows rr and r+1r+1 of AA respectively. Proposition 5.2 demonstrates that the entries of rows rr and r+1r+1 in fr(A)f_{r}(A) are respectively given by

a1,,ap1,bq,,bq+t1,ap+t+1,,ama_{1},\ldots,a_{p-1},b_{q},\ldots,b_{q+t-1},a_{p+t+1},\ldots,a_{m}

and

b1,,bq1,ap,,ap+t,bq+t,,bnb_{1},\ldots,b_{q-1},a_{p},\ldots,a_{p+t},b_{q+t},\ldots,b_{n}

for pp and tt as in the definition of frf_{r}, and q1q\geq 1 minimal such that bqb_{q} either does not exist or lies in a column strictly right of apa_{p} in the rr alignment of AA. Define

ϕ:{a1,,am,b1,,bn}{r,r+1}×+\phi:\{a_{1},\ldots,a_{m},b_{1},\ldots,b_{n}\}\to\{r,r+1\}\times{\mathbb{Z}}_{+}

so that it agrees with the rr alignment, except on ap,ap+ta_{p},\ldots a_{p+t} which are sent to row r+1r+1, and bq,,bq+t1b_{q},\ldots,b_{q+t-1} which are sent to row rr, without changing column assignments. This amounts to swapping the rows in Fig. 6. We must show that ϕ\phi is the rr alignment of fr(A)f_{r}(A).

We see that ϕ\phi inherits from the rr alignment of AA properties (1), (2), and (4) in Definition 4.5. The only entries in row rr of ϕ\phi weakly left of some bib_{i} with 1i<q1\leq i<q are among a1,,ap1a_{1},\ldots,a_{p-1}. All these entries occupy the same position in the rr alignment of AA so cannot violate (3). For q+tinq+t\leq i\leq n, the only entries in row rr of ϕ\phi left of bib_{i} that do not also occupy row rr in the rr alignment of AA are bjb_{j} for qj<q+tq\leq j<q+t which are less than bib_{i} and therefore do not violate (3) in Definition 4.5. The only elements of row rr left of apa_{p} in ϕ\phi are aia_{i} that are lesser than apa_{p}. Each ap+ia_{p+i} for 1it1\leq i\leq t shares a column with an incomparable element by Lemma 5.3, so cannot violate (3). So ϕ\phi is a weak rr alignment of fr(A)f_{r}(A).

Suppose we have a weak rr alignment ψ\psi of fr(A)f_{r}(A) such that ψϕ\psi\preceq\phi. We will show ψ=ϕ\psi=\phi. Since apa_{p} is the leftmost element in row rr of the rr alignment of AA that does not share a column with an entry in row r+1r+1, we know from Lemma 4.4 that b1,,bq1,ap,,amb_{1},\ldots,b_{q-1},a_{p},\ldots,a_{m} occupy adjacent columns in the rr alignment of AA, hence in ϕ\phi. Properties (1) and (3) of weak rr alignments force each element in this chain to be strictly right of the previous element in ψ\psi, so the elements of this chain occupy the same columns in ψ\psi and ϕ\phi.

Take bib_{i} for q+tinq+t\leq i\leq n and suppose bjb_{j} occupies the same column in ψ\psi and ϕ\phi for any j>ij>i. The only elements greater than bib_{i} are those bjb_{j}, and possibly some aka_{k} for k>p+tk>p+t. We have assumed that each such greater element occupies the same column in ψ\psi and ϕ\phi. Recalling that apa_{p} is the leftmost element in row rr of the rr alignment of AA that does not share a column with an entry in row r+1r+1, Lemma 4.4 precludes bib_{i} from being strictly right of ama_{m} in the rr alignment, hence in ϕ\phi. Then in ϕ\phi, (3) and (4) place bib_{i} one column left of the leftmost entry greater than bib_{i}. Property (4) forces bib_{i} to occupy the same position in ψ\psi.

Since by choice of bqb_{q} we have ap+iPbq+ia_{p+i}\not<_{P}b_{q+i} for each 0i<t0\leq i<t, we know bq+i<Pap+i+2b_{q+i}<_{P}a_{p+i+2} by the (3+1)-free condition (if ap+i+2a_{p+i+2} exists). We also have bq+iap+i+1b_{q+i}\parallel a_{p+i+1} by Lemma 5.3. This means that in ϕ\phi, each such bq+ib_{q+i} is one column left of the leftmost entry greater than bq+ib_{q+i} if such an entry exists. We have already determined that ϕ\phi and ψ\psi agree on the positions of entries greater than any of bq,,bq+t1b_{q},\ldots,b_{q+t-1}, other than these entries themselves. Now properties (1) and (4) of weak rr alignments prohibit ψ\psi from placing any of these bq+ib_{q+i} strictly left of its position in ϕ\phi.

It remains only to show that ϕ\phi and ψ\psi agree on a1,,ap1a_{1},\ldots,a_{p-1}. Define

ξ:{a1,,am,b1,,bn}{r,r+1}×+\xi:\{a_{1},\ldots,a_{m},b_{1},\ldots,b_{n}\}\to\{r,r+1\}\times{\mathbb{Z}}_{+}

to agree with the rr alignment of AA (hence the column assignments of ϕ\phi), except on the positions of a1,,ap1a_{1},\ldots,a_{p-1} where it instead agrees with ψ\psi. We know ξ\xi places each aia_{i} left of ai+1a_{i+1} so it satisfies (1). Column assignments in ψ\psi all agree with ξ\xi which therefore satisfies (2) and (4).

If bj<Paib_{j}<_{P}a_{i} for some pimp\leq i\leq m and 1jn1\leq j\leq n then the positions of these entries in ξ\xi agrees with the rr alignment of AA and therefore they do not violate (3). For 1i<p1\leq i<p we can only have bj<Paib_{j}<_{P}a_{i} for some j<qj<q. The positions of these elements in ξ\xi agree with ψ\psi so cannot violate (3) either. Then ξ\xi is a weak rr alignment that precedes the rr alignment of AA according \preceq. Then ξ\xi is, in fact, the rr alignment of AA by Proposition 4.7. In particular, for i<pi<p we have ψ(ai)=ξ(ai)=ϕ(ai)\psi(a_{i})=\xi(a_{i})=\phi(a_{i}). Therefore ϕ=ψ\phi=\psi so ϕ\phi is the alignment of fr(A)f_{r}(A) by Proposition 4.7. ∎

We next give a series of analogous statements for the crystal raising operator. The proofs are mostly, but not entirely, symmetric.

Definition 5.5.

The crystal raising operator er:𝒜P𝒜P{0}e_{r}:\mathcal{A}_{P}\to\mathcal{A}_{P}\cup\{0\} acts on A𝒜PA\in\mathcal{A}_{P} as follows. Let a1<P<Pama_{1}<_{P}\cdots<_{P}a_{m} and b1<P<Pbnb_{1}<_{P}\cdots<_{P}b_{n} be the entries of rows rr and r+1r+1 of AA respectively.

  • If every column of the rr alignment with an entry in row r+1r+1 also contains an entry in row rr then define er(A)=0e_{r}(A)=0.

  • Otherwise let pp be maximal such that bpb_{p} does not share a column with an entry in row rr in the rr alignment. Let t0t\geq 0 be minimal such that there is no ai>Pbp+ta_{i}>_{P}b_{p+t} one column right of bp+tb_{p+t}. Then we move bp,,bp+tb_{p},\ldots,b_{p+t} to row rr, and any aia_{i} that shares a column with one of these entries to row r+1r+1.

Proposition 5.6.

The crystal raising operator ere_{r} is well-defined, and if we have A𝒜PA\in\mathcal{A}_{P} with er(A)0e_{r}(A)\neq 0 then 𝐰𝐭(er(A))=𝐰𝐭(A)+αr\mathbf{wt}(e_{r}(A))=\mathbf{wt}(A)+\alpha_{r}.

Proof.

Let A𝒜PA\in\mathcal{A}_{P} and let a1<P<Pama_{1}<_{P}\cdots<_{P}a_{m} and b1<P<Pbnb_{1}<_{P}\cdots<_{P}b_{n} be the entries of rows rr and r+1r+1 of AA respectively. Select bpb_{p} as in the definition, assuming it exists. If the column immediately right of bnb_{n} in the rr alignment contains some aia_{i}, then bn<Paib_{n}<_{P}a_{i} by Lemma 4.8, and it therefore makes sense to select t0t\geq 0 as in the definition of ere_{r}. The entries bp,,bp+tb_{p},\ldots,b_{p+t} reside in consecutive columns of the rr alignment by choice of bpb_{p} and property (3) of weak rr alignments, and for each 0i<t0\leq i<t there is some ajPbp+ia_{j}\not>_{P}b_{p+i} that shares a column with bp+i+1b_{p+i+1}. Let q1q\geq 1 be minimal such that either aqa_{q} lies in a column strictly right of bpb_{p} or does not exist. The relevant columns of the rr alignment are then as shown in Fig. 7 (which degenerates to just the column containing bpb_{p} if t=0t=0).

\ytableausetup

mathmode, centertableaux,boxsize=2.5em{ytableau} \none&aqaq+1⋯aq+t-1
bpbp+1bp+2⋯bp+t 

Figure 7. The columns in the alignment of AA whose elements are to be row swapped by ere_{r}.

To show that both rows of er(A)e_{r}(A) are chains, it suffices to show

  1. (i)

    aq1<Pbpa_{q-1}<_{P}b_{p}

  2. (ii)

    bp+t<Paq+tb_{p+t}<_{P}a_{q+t}

  3. (iii)

    bp1<Paqb_{p-1}<_{P}a_{q}

  4. (iv)

    aq+t1<Pbp+t+1a_{q+t-1}<_{P}b_{p+t+1}

whenever these indices are valid. When t=0t=0 we need not consider (iii) or (iv).

We have (i) immediately from Lemma 4.8. By choice of bpb_{p} we know that aq+ta_{q+t}, if it exists, lies one column right bp+tb_{p+t}. Then (ii) follows by choice of bp+tb_{p+t}.

If t0t\neq 0 we have bp+t1Paq+t1b_{p+t-1}\not<_{P}a_{q+t-1} so (iv) follows from the (3+1)-free condition. We also know bpPaqb_{p}\not<_{P}a_{q} so we must have aqPbp+1a_{q}\not<_{P}b_{p+1} or we could violate the characterization of the rr alignment of AA given in Proposition 4.7 by shifting aqa_{q} one position to the left. Thus (iii) follows from the (3+1)-free condition.

Fig. 7 makes clear that 𝐰𝐭(er(A))=𝐰𝐭(A)+αr\mathbf{wt}(e_{r}(A))=\mathbf{wt}(A)+\alpha_{r}. ∎

Lemma 5.7.

Let AA be a PP-array. Let bp<P<Pbp+tb_{p}<_{P}\cdots<_{P}b_{p+t} and aq<P<Paq+t1a_{q}<_{P}\cdots<_{P}a_{q+t-1} be the elements whose rows are swapped by ere_{r} as in Fig. 7. Then bp+i+1aq+ib_{p+i+1}\parallel a_{q+i} for each 0i<t0\leq i<t.

Proof.

We have bp+iPaq+ib_{p+i}\not<_{P}a_{q+i} by choice of bp+tb_{p+t}. Were we to have aq+i<Pbp+i+1a_{q+i}<_{P}b_{p+i+1}, we could shift aq,,aq+ia_{q},\ldots,a_{q+i} left one position in the rr alignment of AA and we would still have a weak rr alignment, contradicting Proposition 4.7.

On the other hand, aq+iPbp+i+1a_{q+i}\not>_{P}b_{p+i+1} by property (3) of weak rr alignments. ∎

Lemma 5.8.

Applying ere_{r} to a PP-array AA does not change the column of any element in the rr alignment.

Proof.

Let a1<Pa2<P<Pama_{1}<_{P}a_{2}<_{P}\cdots<_{P}a_{m} and b1<Pb2<P<Pbnb_{1}<_{P}b_{2}<_{P}\cdots<_{P}b_{n} be the entries of rows rr and r+1r+1 of AA respectively. Proposition 5.6 demonstrates that rows rr and r+1r+1 in er(A)e_{r}(A) are given by

a1,,aq1,bp,,bp+t,aq+t,,ama_{1},\ldots,a_{q-1},b_{p},\ldots,b_{p+t},a_{q+t},\ldots,a_{m}

and

b1,,bp1,aq,,aq+t1,bp+t+1,,bnb_{1},\ldots,b_{p-1},a_{q},\ldots,a_{q+t-1},b_{p+t+1},\ldots,b_{n}

where pp and tt are as in the definition of ere_{r}, and q1q\geq 1 is minimal such that aqa_{q} either does not exist or lies in a column strictly right of bpb_{p} in the rr alignment of AA. Define

ϕ:{a1,,am,b1,,bn}{r,r+1}×+\phi:\{a_{1},\ldots,a_{m},b_{1},\ldots,b_{n}\}\to\{r,r+1\}\times{\mathbb{Z}}_{+}

so that it agrees with the rr alignment of AA, except on bp,,bp+tb_{p},\ldots,b_{p+t} which are sent to row rr, and aq,,aq+t1a_{q},\ldots,a_{q+t-1} which are sent to row r+1r+1. This amounts to swapping the rows in Fig. 7. We must show that ϕ\phi is the rr alignment of er(A)e_{r}(A).

We see that ϕ\phi inherits from the rr alignment of AA properties (1), (2), and (4) in Definition 4.5. Any entry in row rr of ϕ\phi weakly left of bib_{i} for some 1i<p1\leq i<p is also in row rr weakly left of bib_{i} in the rr alignment of AA and therefore cannot violate (3). The only elements in row rr of ϕ\phi weakly left of bib_{i} for p+t<inp+t<i\leq n are either in the same position in the alignment of AA, or are some bj<Pbib_{j}<_{P}b_{i}. Either way, such bib_{i} cannot be part of a violation of (3). Each aq+ia_{q+i} with 0i<t0\leq i<t shares a column in ϕ\phi with an incomparable element by Lemma 5.7 and so cannot violate (3) either. So ϕ\phi is a weak rr alignment.

Suppose we have a weak rr alignment ψ\psi such that ψϕ\psi\preceq\phi. We will show that ψ=ϕ\psi=\phi. Since bpb_{p} is the rightmost entry in row r+1r+1 of the rr alignment of AA that does not share a column with an entry in row rr, we know from Lemma 4.4 that b1,,bp+t,aq+t,,amb_{1},\ldots,b_{p+t},a_{q+t},\ldots,a_{m} occupy adjacent columns in the alignment of AA, hence in ϕ\phi. Properties (1) and (3) of weak rr alignments force each element in this chain to lie strictly right of the previous one in ψ\psi, so the elements of this chain occupy the same columns in ψ\psi and ϕ\phi.

Let xx be some element of the chain aq,,aq+t1,bp+t+1,,bna_{q},\ldots,a_{q+t-1},b_{p+t+1},\ldots,b_{n}, and assume we have determined all elements greater than xx in the chain to occupy the same position in both ϕ\phi and ψ\psi. In this case, we have in fact determined by the previous paragraph that all entries greater than xx, in the chain or otherwise, occupy the same position in both ϕ\phi and ψ\psi. If q=m+1q=m+1, i.e. ama_{m} lies in a column left of bpb_{p} in the rr alignment of AA, then this chain is vacuous as there cannot exist bp+1b_{p+1} in a column strictly right of ama_{m} by choice of bpb_{p}. Assuming qm+1q\neq m+1 we then know xx must lie weakly left of ama_{m} in ϕ\phi, hence in ψ\psi, by choice of bpb_{p}. Then the position of xx is uniquely determined by (3) and (4) in both ϕ\phi and ψ\psi to be one column left of the leftmost greater element yy. Since yy occupies the same position in ϕ\phi and ψ\psi by induction, so to does xx.

It remains to show ϕ\phi and ψ\psi agree on a1,,aq1a_{1},\ldots,a_{q-1}. Define

ξ:{a1,,am,b1,,bn}{r,r+1}×+\xi:\{a_{1},\ldots,a_{m},b_{1},\ldots,b_{n}\}\to\{r,r+1\}\times{\mathbb{Z}}_{+}

to agree with the rr alignment of AA (hence the column assignments of ϕ\phi), except on the positions of a1,,aq1a_{1},\ldots,a_{q-1} where it instead agrees with ψ\psi. We know ξ\xi places each aia_{i} left of ai+1a_{i+1} so it satisfies (1). Column positions of ψ\psi agree with ξ\xi which therefore satisfies (2) and (4).

The positions of each aia_{i} with qimq\leq i\leq m and each bjb_{j} agree between ξ\xi and the rr alignment of AA, so no such aia_{i} can violate (3) in ξ\xi. For 1i<q1\leq i<q, we can only have bj<Paib_{j}<_{P}a_{i} if j<pj<p. The positions of these elements in ξ\xi agree with ψ\psi so cannot violate (3) either. Then ξ\xi is a weak rr alignment that precedes the rr alignment of AA according to \preceq. Then ξ\xi is, in fact, the rr alignment of AA by Proposition 4.7. In particular, for i<qi<q we have ψ(ai)=ξ(ai)=ϕ(ai)\psi(a_{i})=\xi(a_{i})=\phi(a_{i}). Therefore ϕ=ψ\phi=\psi so ϕ\phi is the alignment of er(A)e_{r}(A) by Proposition 4.7. ∎

Proposition 5.9.

Let AA be a PP-array. Consider the induced subgraph GG of inc(P)\operatorname{inc}(P) restricted to vertices in rows rr and r+1r+1 of AA. Applying frf_{r} or ere_{r} to AA swaps the rows of the elements in a single connected component of GG.

Proof.

We will prove this for frf_{r}, with the argument for ere_{r} being symmetric. If frf_{r} swaps the row of some xPx\in P, and if yPy\in P is incomparable to xx, then yy cannot share a row with xx either before or after applying frf_{r} which is to say frf_{r} swaps the row of yy as well. Thus frf_{r} swaps the rows of elements in a union of connected components of GG.

Now we must show that all elements whose rows are swapped by frf_{r} belong to the same connected component. Let a1<P<Pama_{1}<_{P}\cdots<_{P}a_{m} and b1<P<Pbnb_{1}<_{P}\cdots<_{P}b_{n} be the entries of rows rr and r+1r+1 of AA respectively. Let ap,,ap+ta_{p},\ldots,a_{p+t} and bq,,bq+t1b_{q},\ldots,b_{q+t-1} be the entries whose rows will be changed by frf_{r}, as in Fig. 6. We have that ap+i+1bq+ia_{p+i+1}\parallel b_{q+i} for 0i<t0\leq i<t by Lemma 5.3. That is to say each column in Fig. 6 is a subset of a connected component. This also implies bq+iPap+ib_{q+i}\not<_{P}a_{p+i}, and we have bq+iPap+ib_{q+i}\not>_{P}a_{p+i} by definition of frf_{r}. Thus there is an edge in GG between each column in Fig. 6. So all of ap,,ap+ta_{p},\ldots,a_{p+t} and bq,,bq+t1b_{q},\ldots,b_{q+t-1} belong to the same connected component as desired. ∎

We have seen in Propositions 5.2 and 5.6 that ere_{r} and frf_{r} are well-defined and affect the weight map in the correct way. The following theorem then completes the verification that (𝒜P,er,fr,𝐰𝐭)(\mathcal{A}_{P},e_{r},f_{r},\mathbf{wt}) is a crystal.

Theorem 5.10.

For A,A𝒜PA,A^{\prime}\in\mathcal{A}_{P} we have fr(A)=Af_{r}(A)=A^{\prime} if and only if er(A)=Ae_{r}(A^{\prime})=A.

Proof.

If fr(A)=Af_{r}(A)=A^{\prime} then by Lemma 5.4 and Lemma 4.4, the leftmost entry xx in row rr of the rr alignment of AA that does not share a column with an entry in row r+1r+1, is the rightmost element in row r+1r+1 of the alignment of AA^{\prime} that does not share a column with an entry in row rr. By Proposition 5.9, both frf_{r} and ere_{r} operate by swapping the rows of the entries in the connected component of xx of the induced subgraph of inc(P)\operatorname{inc}(P) restricted to vertices in rows rr and r+1r+1 of AA, or equivalently AA^{\prime}. Thus er(A)=Ae_{r}(A^{\prime})=A. The other direction is similar. ∎

Fig. 8 shows an example of a poset PP and a subset of 𝒜P\mathcal{A}_{P} with edges given by the crystal.

aabbccdd
\ytableausetupcentertableaux, boxsize=1em{ytableau} c&a
db
\ytableausetupcentertableaux, boxsize=1em{ytableau} c&a
b
d
\ytableausetupcentertableaux, boxsize=1em{ytableau} c&a
\none
db
\ytableausetupcentertableaux, boxsize=1em{ytableau} a
c
d&b
\ytableausetupcentertableaux, boxsize=1em{ytableau} \none
c&a
db
\ytableausetupcentertableaux, boxsize=1em{ytableau} b
c&a
d
\ytableausetupcentertableaux, boxsize=1em{ytableau} b
c
d&a
\ytableausetupcentertableaux, boxsize=1em{ytableau} a
d&b
c
\ytableausetupcentertableaux, boxsize=1em{ytableau} d&a
b
c
2222112222111111
Figure 8. A segment of the PP-array crystal for the given poset.

In the context of our crystal on 𝒜P\mathcal{A}_{P}, the PP-tableaux now hold crystal-theoretic significance.

Theorem 5.11.

The highest weight elements of 𝒜P\mathcal{A}_{P} are the PP-tableaux.

Proof.

Let T𝒜PT\in\mathcal{A}_{P} and take r1r\geq 1 to be arbitrary. Let a1<Pa2<P<Pama_{1}<_{P}a_{2}<_{P}\cdots<_{P}a_{m} and b1<Pb2<P<Pbnb_{1}<_{P}b_{2}<_{P}\cdots<_{P}b_{n} be the entries of rows rr and r+1r+1 of TT respectively. Suppose er(T)=0e_{r}(T)=0. Then every nonempty column in the rr alignment of TT contains some aia_{i}. By property (2) of weak rr alignments this means each aia_{i} is in column ii of the rr alignment. Each bib_{i} is necessarily in column ii or greater, so biPaib_{i}\not<_{P}a_{i} by property (3). This shows that rows rr and r+1r+1 of TT satisfy the required column condition of PP-tableaux.

Conversely, suppose mnm\geq n and biPaib_{i}\not<_{P}a_{i} for each 1im1\leq i\leq m. Then each aia_{i} gets mapped to column ii in the rr pre-alignment of TT. As entries shift right to obtain the rr-alignment, the chain a1,,ama_{1},\ldots,a_{m} must stay put, and the entries b1,,bnb_{1},\ldots,b_{n} will never move past the rightmost occupied column mm. Thus, every nonempty column in the rr alignment of TT contains some aia_{i} which means er(T)=0e_{r}(T)=0.

We have shown that er(T)=0e_{r}(T)=0 is equivalent to the PP-tableau column condition on elements in rows rr and r+1r+1. Therefore TT is a highest weight element if and only if it is a PP-tableau. ∎

6. ss-Positivity

Note that the crystal on 𝒜P\mathcal{A}_{P} induces a crystal on any subset. In this section we will be studying characters of connected components of 𝒜P\mathcal{A}_{P}. If CC is a connected component, we will use the notation C𝐚C_{\mathbf{a}} to denote the set of PP-arrays in CC with weight 𝐚\mathbf{a}.

Proposition 6.1.

If CC is a connected component of 𝒜P\mathcal{A}_{P} then char(C)\mathrm{char}(C) is a symmetric function.

Proof.

We must show that the cardinalities of C𝐚C_{\mathbf{a}} and C𝐛C_{\mathbf{b}} match when 𝐛\mathbf{b} is a permutation of 𝐚\mathbf{a}. It suffices to assume 𝐛=sr𝐚\mathbf{b}=s_{r}\mathbf{a} for a simple transposition srs_{r}, and 𝐚r>𝐚r+1\mathbf{a}_{r}>\mathbf{a}_{r+1} without loss of generality.

In the rr alignment of any AC𝐚A\in C_{\mathbf{a}}, we must have that there are at least k=𝐚r𝐚r+1k=\mathbf{a}_{r}-\mathbf{a}_{r+1} entries in row rr that do not share columns with entries in row r+1r+1. Therefore frk(A)0f_{r}^{k}(A)\neq 0 and

𝐰𝐭(frk(A))=𝐚kαr=sr𝐚\mathbf{wt}(f_{r}^{k}(A))=\mathbf{a}-k\alpha_{r}=s_{r}\mathbf{a}

by Lemma 5.4. Then frkf_{r}^{k} provides a bijection from C𝐚C_{\mathbf{a}} to Csi𝐚C_{s_{i}\mathbf{a}} with inverse erke_{r}^{k} by Theorem 5.10. ∎

The next result is our awaited refinement of Theorem 2.4. The proof follows in the spirit of Gasharov’s by using the Jacobi-Trudi identity and the usual inner product on symmetric functions to get an alternating formula for the Schur coefficients in terms of the monomial coefficients [Gas96]. However, the involution we use to cancel terms is based on our crystal operators, which allows us to stay within a connected component of the crystal.

Theorem 6.2.

Let CC be a connected component of 𝒜P\mathcal{A}_{P}. Then char(C)=λcλsλ\mathrm{char}(C)=\sum_{\lambda}c_{\lambda}s_{\lambda} where cλc_{\lambda} is the number of PP-tableaux in CC of weight λ\lambda.

Proof.

Let λcλsλ\sum_{\lambda}c_{\lambda}s_{\lambda} be the expansion of char(C)\mathrm{char}(C) into the Schur basis for symmetric functions. Set n=#Pn=\#P and let λ=(λ1,,λ)\lambda=(\lambda_{1},\ldots,\lambda_{\ell}) be a partition of nn. For πS\pi\in S_{\ell} we let π(λ)\pi(\lambda) denote the weak composition with iith component π(λ)i=λπ(i)π(i)+i\pi(\lambda)_{i}=\lambda_{\pi(i)}-\pi(i)+i for 1i1\leq i\leq\ell. Notice that π(λ)σ(λ)\pi(\lambda)\neq\sigma(\lambda) when πσ\pi\neq\sigma, as we have π(i)<σ(i)\pi(i)<\sigma(i) for some ii which yields

π(λ)iσ(λ)i=(λπ(i)λσ(i))+(σ(i)π(i))>0.\pi(\lambda)_{i}-\sigma(\lambda)_{i}=(\lambda_{\pi(i)}-\lambda_{\sigma(i)})+(\sigma(i)-\pi(i))>0.

The Jacobi-Trudi identity says

sλ=det(hλjj+i)i,j=1=πSsgn(π)hπ(λ)s_{\lambda}=\det(h_{\lambda_{j}-j+i})_{i,j=1}^{\ell}=\sum_{\pi\in S_{\ell}}\operatorname{sgn}(\pi)h_{\pi(\lambda)}

where h𝐚h_{\mathbf{a}} here denotes the complete homogeneous symmetric function of the weak composition 𝐚\mathbf{a}. If 𝐚\mathbf{a} is not a weak composition, i.e. it has a negative part, then h𝐚h_{\mathbf{a}} is considered to be zero. Recall that the Schur functions are an orthonormal basis with respect to the inner product on symmetric functions defined by mλ,hμ=δλμ\langle m_{\lambda},h_{\mu}\rangle=\delta_{\lambda\mu} where mλm_{\lambda} stands for the monomial symmetric function indexed by λ\lambda. Therefore

(1) cλ=char(C),sλ=char(C),πSsgn(π)hπ(λ)=AπSCπ(λ)sgn(A)c_{\lambda}=\langle\mathrm{char}(C),s_{\lambda}\rangle=\langle\mathrm{char}(C),\sum_{\pi\in S_{\ell}}\operatorname{sgn}(\pi)h_{\pi(\lambda)}\rangle=\sum_{A\in\bigsqcup_{\pi\in S_{\ell}}C_{\pi(\lambda)}}\operatorname{sgn}(A)

where sgn(A)\operatorname{sgn}(A) takes the value sgn(π)\operatorname{sgn}(\pi) when ACπ(λ)A\in C_{\pi(\lambda)}.

We will define an involution ι:πSCπ(λ)πSCπ(λ)\iota:\bigsqcup_{\pi\in S_{\ell}}C_{\pi(\lambda)}\to\bigsqcup_{\pi\in S_{\ell}}C_{\pi(\lambda)}. Let A={Ai,j}Cπ(λ)A=\{A_{i,j}\}\in C_{\pi(\lambda)} for some πS\pi\in S_{\ell}. If AA is a PP-tableau then set ι(A)=A\iota(A)=A. Otherwise, there is a minimal cc such that some Ai+1,cA_{i+1,c} exists with i>0i>0, but either Ai,cA_{i,c} does not exist or Ai,c>PAi+1,cA_{i,c}>_{P}A_{i+1,c}. With cc so fixed, let rr be maximal among such ii.

For convenience denote rows rr and r+1r+1 of AA by a1<P<Paπ(λ)ra_{1}<_{P}\cdots<_{P}a_{\pi(\lambda)_{r}} and b1<P<Pbπ(λ)r+1b_{1}<_{P}\cdots<_{P}b_{\pi(\lambda)_{r+1}}. For k<ck<c we have akpbka_{k}\not>_{p}b_{k} which puts aka_{k} in column kk of the rr pre-alignment of AA. If bc+1b_{c+1} does not exist, then aca_{c} is placed in column c1c_{1} of the rr pre-alignment. This is to say column c+1c+1 either contains aca_{c} or bc+1b_{c+1} or is emtpy. Since PP is (3+1)-free and akPbka_{k}\not>_{P}b_{k} when k<ck<c, we have that such aka_{k} are less than bc+1b_{c+1}, if it exists. Then every entry in a column strictly left of c+1c+1 in the rr pre-alignment is less than any entry in column c+1c+1. This prohibits any of these lesser entries from occupying column c+1c+1 in the rr alignment, as none of them can enter column c+1c+1 until both aca_{c} and bc+1b_{c+1} have vacated, but neither can an entry be moved into a previously empty column. This is to say that in the rr alignment, the entries weakly left of column cc are exactly a1,,ac1a_{1},\ldots,a_{c-1} and b1,,bcb_{1},\ldots,b_{c}.

The remaining entries ac,,aπ(λ)ra_{c},\ldots,a_{\pi(\lambda)_{r}} and bc+1,,bπ(λ)r+1b_{c+1},\ldots,b_{\pi(\lambda)_{r+1}} now lie strictly right of column cc in the rr alignment. So if π(λ)rπ(λ)r+1\pi(\lambda)_{r}\geq\pi(\lambda)_{r+1} then there are at least

π(λ)rπ(λ)r+1+1=π(λ)r(πsr)(λ)r\pi(\lambda)_{r}-\pi(\lambda)_{r+1}+1=\pi(\lambda)_{r}-(\pi s_{r})(\lambda)_{r}

such aia_{i} that do not share a column with an entry in row r+1r+1. Then it makes sense to define

ι(A)=frπ(λ)r(πsr)(λ)r(A).\iota(A)=f_{r}^{\pi(\lambda)_{r}-(\pi s_{r})(\lambda)_{r}}(A).

If instead π(λ)r<π(λ)r+1\pi(\lambda)_{r}<\pi(\lambda)_{r+1} then there are at least

π(λ)r+1π(λ)r1=(πsr)(λ)rπ(λ)r\pi(\lambda)_{r+1}-\pi(\lambda)_{r}-1=(\pi s_{r})(\lambda)_{r}-\pi(\lambda)_{r}

entries bib_{i} strictly right of column cc that do not share a column with an entry in row rr. Here, it makes sense to define

ι(A)=er(πsr)(λ)rπ(λ)r(A).\iota(A)=e_{r}^{(\pi s_{r})(\lambda)_{r}-\pi(\lambda)_{r}}(A).

In either of these cases, note that AA gets mapped into C(πsr)(λ)C_{(\pi s_{r})(\lambda)}. This means both that ι\iota reverses the sign of AA, and our codomain is correct.

In the case where π(λ)rπ(λ)r+1\pi(\lambda)_{r}\geq\pi(\lambda)_{r+1} we have seen that the π(λ)r(πsr)(λ)r\pi(\lambda)_{r}-(\pi s_{r})(\lambda)_{r} entries in row rr of the rr alignment that do not share a column with an entry in row r+1r+1 lie strictly right of column cc. Similarly, in the case where π(λ)r<π(λ)r+1\pi(\lambda)_{r}<\pi(\lambda)_{r+1}, we know the rightmost (πsr)(λ)rπ(λ)r(\pi s_{r})(\lambda)_{r}-\pi(\lambda)_{r} in row r+1r+1 of the rr alignment that do not share a column with an entry in row rr all lie strictly right of column cc. In both cases, a1,,ac1a_{1},\ldots,a_{c-1} and b1,,bcb_{1},\ldots,b_{c} lie weakly left of column cc. So ι\iota will not change the rows of any a1,,ac1a_{1},\ldots,a_{c-1} or b1,,bcb_{1},\ldots,b_{c}. That is, ι\iota does not change the indices of any Ai,jA_{i,j} with j<cj<c, or with j=cj=c and i>ri>r. The selection of both cc and rr between AA and ι(A)\iota(A) therefore agree, and to apply ι2\iota^{2} to AA is to apply

er(πsrsr)(λ)r(πsr)(λ)rfrπ(λ)r(πsr)(λ)re_{r}^{(\pi s_{r}s_{r})(\lambda)_{r}-(\pi s_{r})(\lambda)_{r}}\circ f_{r}^{\pi(\lambda)_{r}-(\pi s_{r})(\lambda)_{r}}

or

fr(πsr)(λ)r(πsrsr)(λ)rer(πsr)(λ)rπ(λ)rf_{r}^{(\pi s_{r})(\lambda)_{r}-(\pi s_{r}s_{r})(\lambda)_{r}}\circ e_{r}^{(\pi s_{r})(\lambda)_{r}-\pi(\lambda)_{r}}

which are both the identity map by Theorem 5.10.

Since ι\iota reverses the sign of PP-arrays that are not PP-tableaux, terms cancel in equation 1 to get

cλ=Tsgn(T)c_{\lambda}=\sum_{T}\operatorname{sgn}(T)

summed over PP-tableaux in πSCπ(λ)\bigsqcup_{\pi\in S_{\ell}}C_{\pi(\lambda)}. If π(i)>π(i+1)\pi(i)>\pi(i+1) then π(λ)i<π(λ)i+1\pi(\lambda)_{i}<\pi(\lambda)_{i+1} which means each such PP-tableau is in CλC_{\lambda} as it must have partition weight. Furthermore, these PP-tableaux have positive sign so we conclude cλc_{\lambda} is the number of PP-tableaux of weight λ\lambda in CC. ∎

Recall that by Proposition 5.9, our crystal operators, and therefore our involution ι\iota, work by flipping connected components of the incomparability graph restricted to relevant rows. This is necessary if we want to obtain another PP-array from our input. As a quick point of comparison between our involution and previous variations used to obtain coarser ss-positivity theorems, Gasharov would have us flip all such connected components right of what we called column cc [Gas96], while Shareshian and Wachs would have us flip the subset of those connected components which have odd cardinality [SW16, Proof of Thm 6.3]. Our involution is even more restrained, flipping a minimal number of these components.

7. Natural Unit Interval Orders

A unit interval order is a poset isomorphic to a finite subset PP of {\mathbb{R}} with the relation u<Pvu<_{P}v when u+1<vu+1<v. These are axiomatized by the requirements that they be (3+1)-free and (2+2)-free, which can be seen as a modification to the argument presented in [SS58] or more directly in [BB03].

Definition 7.1.

A natural unit interval order is a finite poset (P,P)(P,\leq_{P}) on a subset of {\mathbb{N}} such that

  • u<Pvu<_{P}v implies u<vu<v as natural numbers, and

  • if u<Pwu<_{P}w with vwv\parallel w and vuv\parallel u, then u<v<wu<v<w as natural numbers.

These define the same isomorphism classes as the unit interval orders [SW16].

Definition 7.2.

[SW16] Given a finite graph G=(V,E)G=(V,E) with VV\subset{\mathbb{N}}, define the chromatic quasisymmetric function by

XG(x,q)=κqasc(κ)vVxκ(v)X_{G}(x,q)=\sum_{\kappa}q^{\mathrm{asc}(\kappa)}\prod_{v\in V}x_{\kappa(v)}

summed over all proper colorings of GG, where

asc(κ)=#{(u,v)Eκ(u)<κ(v) and u<v as natural numbers}.\mathrm{asc}(\kappa)=\#\{(u,v)\in E\mid\kappa(u)<\kappa(v)\text{ and }u<v\text{ as natural numbers}\}.

An edge that counts towards asc(κ)\mathrm{asc}(\kappa) is an ascent.

We of course recover the chromatic symmetric function as XG(x)=XG(x,1)X_{G}(x)=X_{G}(x,1).

If PP is a (3+1)-free poset on a subset of {\mathbb{N}}, then for A𝒜PA\in\mathcal{A}_{P} we write asc(A)\mathrm{asc}(A) to mean asc(κ)\mathrm{asc}(\kappa) where κ\kappa is the proper coloring of inc(P)\operatorname{inc}(P) that corresponds to AA by sending row ii of AA to the number ii. In other words, asc(A)\mathrm{asc}(A) is the number of pairs (x,y)P×P(x,y)\in P\times P such that xyx\parallel y, x<yx<y as natural numbers, and xx occurs in a higher row of AA than yy. When PP is a natural unit interval order we will see that the crystal on 𝒜P\mathcal{A}_{P} respects this statistic.

Theorem 7.3.

If PP is a natural unit interval order then asc\mathrm{asc} is constant on connected components of the PP-array crystal.

Proof.

Let A𝒜PA\in\mathcal{A}_{P} with fr(A)0f_{r}(A)\neq 0. We must show asc(A)=asc(fr(A))\mathrm{asc}(A)=\mathrm{asc}(f_{r}(A)).

Let GG be the graph induced by inc(P)\operatorname{inc}(P) by restricting to the vertices in rows rr and r+1r+1 of AA. By Proposition 5.9, fr(A)f_{r}(A) is obtained from AA by swapping the rows of all elements in some connected components CC of GG. Because GG is bipartite and PP is (3+1)-free, the degree of each vertex is at most 2 and therefore CC is a path or a cycle. Since 𝐰𝐭(fr(A))=𝐰𝐭(A)αr\mathbf{wt}(f_{r}(A))=\mathbf{wt}(A)-\alpha_{r} we know CC contains some t+1t+1 elements in row rr of AA, and tt elements in row r+1r+1. Since GG is bipartite and CC has an odd number of elements, CC is in fact a path.

Suppose we have some uPCu\in P\setminus C and vPv\in P with uvu\parallel v. If vCv\notin C then neither element changes rows between AA and fr(A)f_{r}(A) so the pair (u,v)(u,v) is an ascent in both or neither of AA and fr(A)f_{r}(A). If vCv\in C then uu cannot reside in either row rr or r+1r+1 of AA. Again, the pair (u,v)(u,v) is an ascent in both or neither of AA and fr(A)f_{r}(A).

To show asc(A)=asc(fr(A))\mathrm{asc}(A)=\mathrm{asc}(f_{r}(A)) we must finally show that there is a 1-1 correspondence between ascents in AA and ascents in fr(A)f_{r}(A) which occur entirely within CC. In both cases, we will there is exactly one ascent involving each given vCv\in C from row r+1r+1 of AA (equivalently row rr of fr(A)f_{r}(A)), which is enough since each ascent must include exactly one such element. Since CC is a path containing t+1t+1 elements from row rr and tt elements from row r+1r+1 of AA, each element in row r+1r+1 has degree 2 in GG. Then there are u,wCu,w\in C in row rr of AA with u<Pwu<_{P}w, and with vv incomparable to both. By definition of a natural unit interval order, u<v<wu<v<w as natural numbers. Then (u,v)(u,v) is an ascent in AA but not fr(A)f_{r}(A), and (v,w)(v,w) is an ascent in fr(A)f_{r}(A) but not AA. These are the only elements in CC incomparable to vv, so these are the only possible ascents contained in CC involving vv. ∎

Now if CC is a connected component of the PP-array crystal for a natural unit interval order, it makes sense to define asc(C)\mathrm{asc}(C) as asc(A)\mathrm{asc}(A) for any ACA\in C. Therefore we have the following corollary.

Corollary 7.4.

If PP is a natural unit interval order then

Xinc(P)(x,q)=Cqasc(C)char(C)X_{\operatorname{inc}(P)}(x,q)=\sum_{C}q^{\mathrm{asc}(C)}\mathrm{char}(C)

summed over connected components of the PP-array crystal.

Still for a natural unit interval order, Shareshian and Wachs showed Xinc(P)(x,q)X_{\operatorname{inc}(P)}(x,q) is symmetric in xx, and in fact ss-positive in the sense that the coefficient of each qiq^{i} is ss-positive [SW16]. Corollary 7.4 together with Theorem 6.2 provide a new proof of these facts.

8. Two-Row PP-Tableaux

For the remainder of the paper we again assume only that the poset (P,P)(P,\leq_{P}) is (3+1)-free. We have seen that we can refine 𝒜P\mathcal{A}_{P} into connected components which have ss-positive characters, but these characters are still not single Schur functions in general. Take, for instance, the component shown in Fig. 8 which contains two PP-tableaux.

However, we will develop an explicit method to write the Schur functions corresponding to certain PP-tableaux as generating functions of disjoint connected subsets of 𝒜P\mathcal{A}_{P}. These PP-tableaux TT, are those such that 𝐰𝐭(T)i=0\mathbf{wt}(T)_{i}=0 for all i>2i>2, and we call them two-row PP-tableaux. If TT is a two-row PP-tableau we also say the diagram of TT is the image of the 1 alignment of TT, which we denote 𝔻(T){\mathbb{D}}(T).

Lemma 8.1.

If TT is a two-row PP-tableau then each cell in row 2 of 𝔻(T){\mathbb{D}}(T) has a cell directly above it in row 1.

Proof.

By Theorem 5.11 we have e1(T)=0e_{1}(T)=0 from which the result follows. ∎

For TT a two-row PP-tableau we have s𝐰𝐭(T)=s𝐰𝐭(𝔻(T))s_{\mathbf{wt}(T)}=s_{\mathbf{wt}({\mathbb{D}}(T))} which, by Lemma 8.1 and Theorem 3.7, is the character of the connected component of 𝔻(T){\mathbb{D}}(T) in the diagram crystal. In order to write s𝐰𝐭(T)s_{\mathbf{wt}(T)} as the generating function for a set of PP-arrays, we therefore want to associate the diagrams with highest weight 𝔻(T){\mathbb{D}}(T) to some PP-arrays in a weight preserving way. Let 𝒟(T)\mathcal{D}(T) denote this set of diagrams.

Definition 8.2.

Let TT be a two-row PP-tableau, and D𝒟(T)D\in\mathcal{D}(T). The filling or diagram filling of DD with respect to TT is a bijection LT(D):PDL_{T}(D):P\to D constructed column by column from left to right as follows.

Suppose we have determined the entries mapped to all cells strictly left of some column cc. If column cc of the 1 alignment of TT contains a unique entry, we map it to the unique cell in column cc of DD. Otherwise, column cc of the 1 alignment contains two entries x1,x2Px_{1},x_{2}\in P in rows 1 and 2 respectively. We assign x1x_{1} and x2x_{2} to the cells in column cc according to the first of the following rules whose prerequisites are met.

  1. (1)

    Suppose some yPy\in P is mapped to the topmost cell (r,c1)(r,c-1) in column c1c-1 of DD, and that there is exactly one xix_{i} greater than yy. Then we let srs\leq r be maximal such that (s,c)D(s,c)\in D and we map xix_{i} to (s,c)(s,c) and the remaining poset element to the remaining cell.

  2. (2)

    Suppose some yPy\in P is mapped to the lowest cell (r,c1)(r,c-1) in column c1c-1 of DD, and that there is exactly one xix_{i} greater than yy. Then we let srs\leq r be maximal such that (s,c)D(s,c)\in D and we map xix_{i} to (s,c)(s,c) and the remaining poset element to the remaining cell.

  3. (3)

    Map x1x_{1} and x2x_{2} to the upper and lower cells in column cc of DD respectively.

Proposition 8.3.

Let TT be a two-row PP-tableau, and D𝒟(T)D\in\mathcal{D}(T). The diagram filling LT(D)L_{T}(D) is well-defined.

Proof.

If column c>1c>1 contains two cells in DD, then Proposition 3.5 implies each cell in column c1c-1 must be column (c1)(c-1)-paired. Then for any (r,c1)D(r,c-1)\in D there exists srs\leq r with (s,c)D(s,c)\in D as presumed in rules (1) and (2). ∎

We denote the set of diagram fillings by

DFP={LT(D) T is a two-row P-tableau and D𝒟(T)}\mathrm{DF}_{P}=\{L_{T}(D)\mid\text{ $T$ is a two-row $P$-tableau and }D\in\mathcal{D}(T)\}

and the set of diagram fillings for a fixed two-row PP-tableau TT by

DFP,T={LT(D)D𝒟(T)}.\mathrm{DF}_{P,T}=\{L_{T}(D)\mid D\in\mathcal{D}(T)\}.

The point of this construction is that each row of a diagram filling increases in P\leq_{P} from left to right, so the filling specifies a PP-array. We will prove this shortly.

Lemma 8.4.

Let TT be a two-row PP-tableau, and D𝒟(T)D\in\mathcal{D}(T). Let x1,x2Px_{1},x_{2}\in P be in the same column cc in the 11 alignment of TT with x1x_{1} in row 1 and x2x_{2} in row 2. Suppose they satisfy the condition that whenever we have a distinct element y<Px1y<_{P}x_{1} we have y<Px2y<_{P}x_{2} as well. Then LT(D)(x1)L_{T}(D)(x_{1}) is in a row above LT(D)(x2)L_{T}(D)(x_{2}). In particular, this applies when x1<Px2x_{1}<_{P}x_{2}.

Proof.

The proof is by induction on the column index. If c=1c=1 then the column is governed by rule (3) so we are done.

Suppose c>1c>1 and that the column’s assignments are defined according to rule (2). This is to say there is some yPy\in P assigned to the lowest cell (r,c1)(r,c-1) in column c1c-1 of DD, and y<Px2y<_{P}x_{2} since we cannot have only that y<Px1y<_{P}x_{1}. We must have that (r,c1)(r,c-1) is distinct from the topmost cell in column c1c-1 since rule (1) does not apply. By Proposition 3.5, both cells in column c1c-1 are column (c1)(c-1)-paired which means that both cells in column cc are in rows weakly above rr. Therefore, when we take srs\leq r to be maximal such that (s,c)D(s,c)\in D it must be the case that (s,c)(s,c) is the lowest cell in column cc and is the image of x2x_{2}.

Finally suppose c>1c>1 and that the column’s assignments are defined according to rule (1). There is some y2Py_{2}\in P assigned to the topmost cell (r,c1)(r,c-1) in column c1c-1, and we know that y2Px1y_{2}\not<_{P}x_{1}. We therefore must have that y2y_{2} is in row 2 of the 1 alignment of TT. Let y1y_{1} be the element in row 1 column c1c-1 of the 1 alignment. If we have some z<Py1<Px1z<_{P}y_{1}<_{P}x_{1} then also z<Py2z<_{P}y_{2} by the (3+1)-free condition, but the inductive hypothesis contradicts LT(D)(y2)L_{T}(D)(y_{2}) being the topmost cell in column c1c-1. So rule (1) never actually applies in these circumstances. ∎

Remark 8.5.

If x1x_{1} and x2x_{2} are comparable, then x1<Px2x_{1}<_{P}x_{2} by property (3) of weak rr alignments, so Lemma 8.4 applies.

Proposition 8.6.

Let TT be a two-row PP-tableau and D𝒟(T)D\in\mathcal{D}(T). Suppose we have cells (r2,c1),(r1,c2)D(r_{2},c_{1}),(r_{1},c_{2})\in D such that r1r2r_{1}\leq r_{2} and c1<c2c_{1}<c_{2}. Further assume there is no distinct (r,c)D(r,c)\in D with r1rr2r_{1}\leq r\leq r_{2} and c1cc2c_{1}\leq c\leq c_{2}. Then LT(D)(x)=(r2,c1)L_{T}(D)(x)=(r_{2},c_{1}) and LT(D)(y)=(r1,c2)L_{T}(D)(y)=(r_{1},c_{2}) for some x<Pyx<_{P}y.

Proof.

Let x,yPx,y\in P be the entries mapped to the cells (r2,c1)(r_{2},c_{1}) and (r1,c2)(r_{1},c_{2}) respectively. If there is some column dd with c1<dc2c_{1}<d\leq c_{2} that contains only one entry in the 1 alignment, then x<Pyx<_{P}y by Lemma 4.8.

We may proceed under the assumption that there is no such column dd, and we first deal with the subcase where c2=c1+1c_{2}=c_{1}+1. Suppose (r2,c1)(r_{2},c_{1}) is the topmost cell in column c1c_{1}. If every entry in column c2c_{2} of the 1 alignment of TT is greater than xx, we are done. Otherwise, by definition of weak rr alignments there is one entry in column c2c_{2} that is greater than xx, and one entry in column c2c_{2} that is not. Rule (1) of the definition of diagram fillings therefore applies, and ensures that the entry greater than xx is assigned to (r1,c2)(r_{1},c_{2}). That is, x<Pyx<_{P}y.

Suppose instead that there is (r,c1)D(r,c_{1})\in D with r<r2r<r_{2}, hence r<r1r<r_{1} by assumption. Say LT(D)(z)=(r,c1)L_{T}(D)(z)=(r,c_{1}). If column c2c_{2} of the filling is defined according to rule (1), then there is a single entry ww in column c2c_{2} of the 1 alignment of TT that is greater than zz. We must have that zz and ww share a row in TT. Moreover, wyw\neq y since ww must be mapped to a row weakly less than r<r1r<r_{1}. So xx and yy share a row in TT implying x<Pyx<_{P}y. If column c2c_{2} of the filling is not defined according to rule (1), and every entry in column c2c_{2} of the 1 alignment of TT is greater than xx, we again have x<Pyx<_{P}y in particular. If column c2c_{2} of the filling is not defined according to rule (1) and there is exactly one entry in column c2c_{2} of the alignment greater than xx, then column c2c_{2} of the filling is defined according to rule (2). This ensures that the entry greater than xx is mapped to (r1,c2)(r_{1},c_{2}), which is to say x<Pyx<_{P}y.

Now suppose c2>c1+1c_{2}>c_{1}+1, still assuming there is no column dd with c1<dc2c_{1}<d\leq c_{2} containing just one cell. Proposition 3.5 implies that each cell in a column dd with c1d<c2c_{1}\leq d<c_{2} is column dd-paired. This further implies that the topmost cell in each such column dd is in a row weakly below the topmost cell in column d+1d+1. Then (r1,c2)(r_{1},c_{2}) cannot be the topmost cell in column c2c_{2}, else there would be some (r,c21)D(r,c_{2}-1)\in D with r1rr2r_{1}\leq r\leq r_{2}. So (r1,c2)(r_{1},c_{2}) is the lowest cell in its column. Since the 1 alignment of TT is a weak 1 alignment, there is a chain x<Pz<Pwx<_{P}z<_{P}w of entries in columns c1,c1+1,c2c_{1},c_{1}+1,c_{2}. If y=wy=w we are done, so assume not. We must have yPwy\not<_{P}w by Lemma 8.4 since (r1,c2)(r_{1},c_{2}) is the lowest cell in column c2c_{2}. Then x<Pyx<_{P}y by the (3+1)-free condition. ∎

In particular, if we apply Proposition 8.6 when r1=r2r_{1}=r_{2}, we see that the entries in each row of the diagram fillings form a chain. We have therefore justified our earlier claim that each diagram filling gives us a PP-array. Explicitly, for LDFPL\in\mathrm{DF}_{P} we write array(L)\mathrm{array}(L) to mean the PP-array {Ai,j}\{A_{i,j}\} where L(Ai,j)L(A_{i,j}) is the jjth cell from the left in row ii of Im(L)\operatorname{Im}(L). Let

DFAP={array(L)LDFP}\mathrm{DFA}_{P}=\{\mathrm{array}(L)\mid L\in\mathrm{DF}_{P}\}

denote the set of PP-arrays obtained from diagram fillings, and let

DFAP,T={array(L)LDFP,T}\mathrm{DFA}_{P,T}=\{\mathrm{array}(L)\mid L\in\mathrm{DF}_{P,T}\}

denote the set of PP-arrays obtained from diagram fillings with a fixed two-row PP-tableau TT.

Lemma 8.7.

Let TT a two-row PP-tableau. We have array(LT(𝔻(T)))=T\mathrm{array}(L_{T}({\mathbb{D}}(T)))=T.

Proof.

If some column cc of LT(𝔻(T))L_{T}({\mathbb{D}}(T)) is not defined according to rule (1) or (2) in Definition 8.2, then the column assignments of entries in this column agree with TT. Rules (1) and (2) only apply if there are some x,yx,y in columns c1c-1 and cc of the 1 alignment of TT respectively with xPyx\not<_{P}y. Then yy must be placed in the row opposite to xx in both TT and array(LT(𝔻(T)))\mathrm{array}(L_{T}({\mathbb{D}}(T))). By induction, we see that TT and array(LT(𝔻(T)))\mathrm{array}(L_{T}({\mathbb{D}}(T))) must agree on the rows of all elements in column cc of the 1 alignment of TT. ∎

Lemma 8.8.

Let TT be a two-row PP-tableau and D𝒟(T)D\in\mathcal{D}(T). Let xPx\in P and say LT(D)(x)=(r,c)L_{T}(D)(x)=(r,c). If column c+1c+1 of DD contains two cells, then there exists y>Pxy>_{P}x with LT(D)(y)=(s,c+1)L_{T}(D)(y)=(s,c+1) for some srs\leq r.

Proof.

Suppose (r,c)(r,c) is the topmost cell in column cc of DD. If there is exactly one y>Pxy>_{P}x in column c+1c+1 of LT(D)L_{T}(D) then rule (1) in the definition of LT(D)L_{T}(D) ensures it resides in a row weakly above rr. Otherwise, both elements in column c+1c+1 are greater than LT(D)(r,c)L_{T}(D)(r,c), with at least one still being weakly above row rr by Proposition 3.5.

Suppose instead that (r,c)(r,c) is the lower cell in column cc and that it is distinct from the topmost cell. Then all cells in column c+1c+1 of DD are weakly above row rr by Proposition 3.5, and at least one such cell corresponds to an entry greater than xx by Proposition 4.7. ∎

Lemma 8.9.

Let TT be a two-row PP-tableau and D𝒟(T)D\in\mathcal{D}(T). Suppose for some x,yPx,y\in P we have LT(D)(x)=(r1,c1)L_{T}(D)(x)=(r_{1},c_{1}) and LT(D)(y)=(r2,c2)L_{T}(D)(y)=(r_{2},c_{2}) with r1r2r_{1}\leq r_{2} and c1c2c_{1}\leq c_{2}. Then xPyx\not>_{P}y.

Proof.

If there is some column dd with c1<dc2c_{1}<d\leq c_{2} that contains only one cell in DD, then the result follows by Lemma 4.8. So assume not.

In light of Lemma 8.8 we may take a chain x=x1<Px2<P<Pxkx=x_{1}<_{P}x_{2}<_{P}\cdots<_{P}x_{k} where each consecutive element is one column to the right, and in a row weakly above the position of the previous element, and xkx_{k} is in column c2c_{2} of LT(D)L_{T}(D). If xk=yx_{k}=y we are done, and if not then xkx_{k} is in a weakly row above r1r_{1} and therefore strictly above r2r_{2}. Now y<Px<Pxky<_{P}x<_{P}x_{k} would be a contradiction of Lemma 8.4. ∎

Lemma 8.10.

Let TT be a two-row PP-tableau and let D𝒟(T){𝔻(T)}D\in\mathcal{D}(T)\setminus\{{\mathbb{D}}(T)\}. Let r1r\geq 1 be minimal such that er(D)0e_{r}(D)\neq 0. Let xPx\in P be the element such that LT(D)(x)L_{T}(D)(x) is the rightmost cell in row r+1r+1 that is not rr-paired. Then xx is the rightmost entry in row r+1r+1 of the rr alignment of array(LT(D))\mathrm{array}(L_{T}(D)) that does not share a column with an entry in row rr.

Proof.

Let a1<P<Pama_{1}<_{P}\cdots<_{P}a_{m} and b1<P<Pbnb_{1}<_{P}\cdots<_{P}b_{n} be the entries of rows rr and r+1r+1 in array(LT(D))\mathrm{array}(L_{T}(D)) respectively. Let pp be maximal such that LT(D)(bp)L_{T}(D)(b_{p}) is not rr-paired. Say LT(D)(bp)=(r+1,c)L_{T}(D)(b_{p})=(r+1,c).

Suppose we have some aka_{k} with kk maximal such that LT(D)(ak)L_{T}(D)(a_{k}) is in a column strictly left of column cc. Say LT(D)(ak)=(r,c)L_{T}(D)(a_{k})=(r,c^{\prime}) and assume akPbpa_{k}\not<_{P}b_{p}. By Lemma 3.6, there can be no sequence of cells (r1,c1),(r2,c2),(r3,c3)D(r_{1},c_{1}),(r_{2},c_{2}),(r_{3},c_{3})\in D with each ri<ri+1r_{i}<r_{i+1} and cici+1c_{i}\leq c_{i+1}. Thus, LT(D)(ak)L_{T}(D)(a_{k}) cannot be (r1)(r-1)-paired without forming such a sequence together with the (r1)(r-1)-paired cell and (r+1,c)(r+1,c). By choice of rr, we must then have r=1r=1. Since akPbpa_{k}\not<_{P}b_{p} we can say that column c+1c^{\prime}+1 of the 1 alignment of TT contains two entries using Lemma 4.8. Then in DD, we must have (1,c+1)(1,c^{\prime}+1) column cc^{\prime}-paired with LT(D)(ak)=(1,c)L_{T}(D)(a_{k})=(1,c^{\prime}) contradicting either the choice of aka_{k}, or the fact that LT(D)(bp)=(2,c)L_{T}(D)(b_{p})=(2,c) is not 1-paired. Then we must have ak<Pbpa_{k}<_{P}b_{p}.

Since LT(D)(bp)L_{T}(D)(b_{p}) is not 1-paired, each LT(D)(ai)L_{T}(D)(a_{i}) with iki\leq k must be 1-paired to some LT(D)(bj)L_{T}(D)(b_{j}) with j<pj<p. Any LT(D)(aki)L_{T}(D)(a_{k-i}) must then be in a column weakly left of LT(D)(bpi1)L_{T}(D)(b_{p-i-1}) for i0i\geq 0. Then akiPbpi1a_{k-i}\not>_{P}b_{p-i-1} by Lemma 8.9. In particular, this puts aka_{k} in a column strictly left of bpb_{p} in the 1 pre-alignment of array(LT(D))\mathrm{array}(L_{T}(D)). In the 1 alignment of array(LT(D))\mathrm{array}(L_{T}(D)), aka_{k} remains in a column strictly left of bpb_{p} since ak<Pbpa_{k}<_{P}b_{p}.

We must determine the positions of the remaining aia_{i} in the rr alignment of array(LT(D))\mathrm{array}(L_{T}(D)) (no longer assuming r=1r=1 since aka_{k} as defined above may not exist). Let q1q\geq 1 be minimal such that either aqa_{q} does not exist, or LT(D)(aq)L_{T}(D)(a_{q}) is in a column strictly right of LT(D)(bp)L_{T}(D)(b_{p}). Note that npmq+1n-p\leq m-q+1 since any LT(D)(bi)L_{T}(D)(b_{i}) with i>pi>p is rr-paired with some LT(D)(aj)L_{T}(D)(a_{j}) with jqj\geq q by choice of pp. This also means each LT(D)(bp+i)L_{T}(D)(b_{p+i}) with i1i\geq 1 is in a column weakly right of LT(D)(aq+i1)L_{T}(D)(a_{q+i-1}).

Suppose bp+kPaq+kb_{p+k}\not<_{P}a_{q+k} for some k0k\geq 0, and LT(D)(bp+k)L_{T}(D)(b_{p+k}) is in a column strictly left of LT(D)(aq+k)L_{T}(D)(a_{q+k}). If k>0k>0, further assume LT(D)(bp+k)L_{T}(D)(b_{p+k}) shares a column with LT(D)(aq+k1)L_{T}(D)(a_{q+k-1}). We claim bp+k+1b_{p+k+1} exists and LT(D)(bp+k+1)L_{T}(D)(b_{p+k+1}) shares a column with LT(D)(aq+k)L_{T}(D)(a_{q+k}). If k=0k=0 so that LT(D)(bp)L_{T}(D)(b_{p}) does not share a column with any cell in row rr, this fact is necessitated by Proposition 8.6 and our remark that LT(D)(bp+k+1)L_{T}(D)(b_{p+k+1}) is in a column weakly right of LT(D)(aq+k)L_{T}(D)(a_{q+k}).

When k>0k>0 we have LT(D)(aq+k1)L_{T}(D)(a_{q+k-1}) and LT(D)(bp+k)L_{T}(D)(b_{p+k}) sharing a column. The former cannot be (r1)(r-1)-paired without violating Lemma 3.6, so we must have r=1r=1 by choice of rr. Since bp+kPaq+kb_{p+k}\not<_{P}a_{q+k}, Lemma 4.8 implies LT(D)(aq+k)L_{T}(D)(a_{q+k}) shares a column with another cell. This cell can only be in row 2, and therefore corresponds to bp+k+1b_{p+k+1}, again by Lemma 3.6.

Therefore, there is some 0\ell\geq 0 such that (perhaps vacuously)

  1. (a)

    bp+iPaq+ib_{p+i}\not<_{P}a_{q+i} for all 0i<0\leq i<\ell,

  2. (b)

    LT(D)(bp+i)L_{T}(D)(b_{p+i}) and LT(D)(aq+i1)L_{T}(D)(a_{q+i-1}) share a column for all 1i<1\leq i<\ell, and

  3. (c)

    if aq+a_{q+\ell} exists then bp+<Paq+b_{p+\ell}<_{P}a_{q+\ell}.

Additionally, if >0\ell>0 we know r=1r=1.

Recall that each LT(D)(bp+i)L_{T}(D)(b_{p+i}) with i1i\geq 1 is weakly right of the column containing LT(D)(aq+i1)L_{T}(D)(a_{q+i-1}), and therefore bp+iPaq+i1b_{p+i}\not<_{P}a_{q+i-1} by Lemma 8.9. We can now say that in the rr pre-alignment of array(LT(D))\mathrm{array}(L_{T}(D)), the entries b1,,bp+,aq+,,amb_{1},\ldots,b_{p+\ell},a_{q+\ell},\ldots,a_{m} lie in consecutive columns. If aq+a_{q+\ell} actually exists, then ama_{m} lies in the rightmost occupied column pq+m+1np-q+m+1\geq n. If aq+a_{q+\ell} does not exist, then bnb_{n} lies in the rightmost occupied column. In either case, the entries b1,,bp+,aq+,,amb_{1},\ldots,b_{p+\ell},a_{q+\ell},\ldots,a_{m} will remain in consecutive column in the rr alignment of array(LT(D))\mathrm{array}(L_{T}(D)). Moreover, the entries bp++1,,bnb_{p+\ell+1},\ldots,b_{n} will be among the columns containing aq+,,ama_{q+\ell},\ldots,a_{m}.

To complete the proof, it remains to show that aq,,aq+1a_{q},\ldots,a_{q+\ell-1} occupy columns p+1,,p+p+1,\ldots,p+\ell in the rr alignment. This relies, mainly, on showing that aq+iPbq+i+1a_{q+i}\not<_{P}b_{q+i+1} for each 0i<0\leq i<\ell. This is all vacuous when =0\ell=0 so assume >0\ell>0 hence r=1r=1.

Assume to the contrary that aq+i<Pbq+i+1a_{q+i}<_{P}b_{q+i+1} for some 0i<0\leq i<\ell. Lemma 8.4 asserts that aq+ia_{q+i} is in row 1, and bq+i+1b_{q+i+1} in row 2 of TT. In fact, aq,,aq+ia_{q},\ldots,a_{q+i} must all reside in row 1 of TT, and bp,,bq+i+1b_{p},\ldots,b_{q+i+1} in row 2 since bp+jPaq+jb_{p+j}\not<_{P}a_{q+j} for each 0ji0\leq j\leq i. There must then be some yPy\in P in row 1 of TT such that LT(D)(y)L_{T}(D)(y) shares a column with LT(D)(bp)=(2,c)L_{T}(D)(b_{p})=(2,c). If we have some x<Py<Paqx<_{P}y<_{P}a_{q}, then since bpPaqb_{p}\not<_{P}a_{q}, the (3+1)-free condition gives x<Pbpx<_{P}b_{p}. By Lemma 8.4, we then have LT(D)(y)L_{T}(D)(y) in a row above LT(D)(bp)L_{T}(D)(b_{p}), which is to say row 1. This contradicts the choice of pp such that LT(D)(bp)L_{T}(D)(b_{p}) is not rr-paired.

Now aq+1Pbp+a_{q+\ell-1}\not<_{P}b_{p+\ell} and we have seen bp+b_{p+\ell} lies in column p+p+\ell of the rr alignment of array(LT(D))\mathrm{array}(L_{T}(D)). We also saw that column p++1p+\ell+1 is either empty or contains aq+a_{q+\ell}. Property (4) of weak rr alignments therefore requires aq+1a_{q+\ell-1} to be in column p+p+\ell. If 0<i<0<i<\ell and aq+ia_{q+i} lies in column p+i+1p+i+1, then by Property (4) again we must have aq+i1a_{q+i-1} in column p+ip+i, as aq+i1a_{q+i-1} is not smaller than bp+ib_{p+i} in column p+ip+i.

To summarize, the entries aq,,ama_{q},\ldots,a_{m} lie in columns p+1,,p+mq+1p+1,\ldots,p+m-q+1 of the rr alignment of array(LT(D))\mathrm{array}(L_{T}(D)), while bp+1,,bnb_{p+1},\ldots,b_{n} lie in a subset of those same columns. Since each aia_{i} with i<qi<q lies in a column strictly left of bpb_{p} in the rr alignment, bpb_{p} is the rightmost entry in row r+1r+1 of the rr alignment of array(LT(D))\mathrm{array}(L_{T}(D)) that does not share a column with an entry in row rr. ∎

Proposition 8.11.

Let TT be a two-row PP-tableau and let D𝒟(T){𝔻(T)}D\in\mathcal{D}(T)\setminus\{{\mathbb{D}}(T)\}. Let r1r\geq 1 be minimal such that er(D)0e_{r}(D)\neq 0. Then array(LT(er(D)))=er(array(LT(D)))\mathrm{array}(L_{T}(e_{r}(D)))=e_{r}(\mathrm{array}(L_{T}(D))).

Proof.

Let a1<P<Pama_{1}<_{P}\cdots<_{P}a_{m} and b1<P<Pbnb_{1}<_{P}\cdots<_{P}b_{n} be the entries of rows rr and r+1r+1 in array(LT(D))\mathrm{array}(L_{T}(D)) respectively. Let pp be maximal such that the cell corresponding to bpb_{p} in LT(D)L_{T}(D) is not rr-paired. Let GG be the induced subgraph of inc(P)\operatorname{inc}(P) on the vertices in a1,,ama_{1},\ldots,a_{m} and b1,,bnb_{1},\ldots,b_{n}. By Lemma 8.10 and Proposition 5.9, we obtain er(array(LT(D)))e_{r}(\mathrm{array}(L_{T}(D))) from array(LT(D))\mathrm{array}(L_{T}(D)) by taking the vertices in the connected component of GG containing bpb_{p}, and swapping them between rows rr and r+1r+1. We must show the same description holds for array(LT(er(D)))\mathrm{array}(L_{T}(e_{r}(D))).

Say LT(D)(bp)=(r+1,c)L_{T}(D)(b_{p})=(r+1,c). Notice that LT(D)L_{T}(D) and LT(er(D))L_{T}(e_{r}(D)) agree in all columns strictly left of cc, as the diagram fillings are defined column by column from left to right, and DD and er(D)e_{r}(D) coincide in those columns.

Next we consider how column cc differs in LT(D)L_{T}(D) and LT(er(D))L_{T}(e_{r}(D)). We claim LT(er(D))(bp)=(r,c)L_{T}(e_{r}(D))(b_{p})=(r,c). This is clear if column cc of the 11 alignment of TT contains a single entry. Otherwise, column cc of both diagram fillings will be defined according to the same rule (1), (2), or (3) in the definition. We see that (r+1,c)(r+1,c) is the topmost cell in column cc of DD if and only if (r,c)(r,c) is the topmost cell in column cc of er(D)e_{r}(D). So if column cc is defined by rule (3) we indeed get LT(er(D))(bp)=(r,c)L_{T}(e_{r}(D))(b_{p})=(r,c).

If (r,c1)D(r,c-1)\notin D, then for any (s,c1)D(s,c-1)\in D, (r+1,c)(r+1,c) is the lowest cell in column cc weakly above row ss in DD if and only if (r,c)(r,c) is the lowest cell in column cc weakly above row ss in er(D)e_{r}(D). Similarly, if there is (r,c)D(r^{\prime},c)\in D distinct from (r+1,c)(r+1,c), then it is the lowest cell in column cc weakly above row ss in DD if and only if this is also true in er(D)e_{r}(D). Therefore if column cc is defined according to rules (1) or (2), we will again get that LT(er(D))(bp)=(r,c)L_{T}(e_{r}(D))(b_{p})=(r,c).

If instead (r,c1)D(r,c-1)\in D, then also (r+1,c1)D(r+1,c-1)\in D as (r+1,c)(r+1,c) is not rr-paired. In this case we must have r=1r=1 by choice of rr because (r,c1)(r,c-1) cannot be (r1)(r-1)-paired without violating Lemma 3.6. It would also violate Lemma 3.6 to have a cell in row 3 or greater of column cc in DD, so we are back in the case where column cc of the diagram fillings contains only the entry bpb_{p}.

Let q1q\geq 1 be minimal such that either aqa_{q} does not exist, or lies in a column strictly right of bpb_{p} in the 1 alignment of TT. Suppose for some k0k\geq 0 and all 0ik0\leq i\leq k we have

  1. (a)

    LT(D)(bp+i)=(r+1,c+i)L_{T}(D)(b_{p+i})=(r+1,c+i) and LT(er(D))(bp+i)=(r,c+i)L_{T}(e_{r}(D))(b_{p+i})=(r,c+i), and

  2. (b)

    if i>0i>0 then LT(D)(aq+i1)=(r,c+i)L_{T}(D)(a_{q+i-1})=(r,c+i) and LT(er(D))(aq+i1)=(r+1,c+i)L_{T}(e_{r}(D))(a_{q+i-1})=(r+1,c+i).

We will show that if aq+ka_{q+k} exists with LT(D)(aq+k)=(r,c+k+1)L_{T}(D)(a_{q+k})=(r,c+k+1), and bp+kPaq+kb_{p+k}\not<_{P}a_{q+k} then the same hypotheses apply for k+1k+1, and otherwise that column c+k+1c+k+1 is identical in LT(D)L_{T}(D) and LT(er(D))L_{T}(e_{r}(D)).

First assume LT(D)(aq+k)=(r,c+k+1)L_{T}(D)(a_{q+k})=(r,c+k+1) and bp+kPaq+kb_{p+k}\not<_{P}a_{q+k}. The latter assumption with Proposition 8.6 implies either (r,c+k)D(r,c+k)\in D or (r+1,c+k+1)D(r+1,c+k+1)\in D. In either case, we have cells in rows rr and r+1r+1 of the same column, so the cell in row rr cannot be (r1)(r-1)-paired without violating Lemma 3.6. This means r=1r=1 by choice of rr.

If we are in the case (1,c+k)=(r,c+k)D(1,c+k)=(r,c+k)\in D then k>0k>0 hence LT(D)(aq+k1)=(1,c+i)L_{T}(D)(a_{q+k-1})=(1,c+i). Since bp+kPaq+kb_{p+k}\not<_{P}a_{q+k}, LT(D)(aq+k)=(1,c+k+1)L_{T}(D)(a_{q+k})=(1,c+k+1) cannot be the only cell in its column using Lemma 4.8. A cell in row 3 or greater of column c+i+1c+i+1 would again contradict Lemma 3.6 together with (1,c+k)(1,c+k) and (2,c+k)(2,c+k). Therefore we have (r+1,c+k+1)=(2,c+k+1)D(r+1,c+k+1)=(2,c+k+1)\in D anyway. It must be the case that LT(D)(bp+k+1)=(2,c+k+1)L_{T}(D)(b_{p+k+1})=(2,c+k+1).

Now LT(er(D))L_{T}(e_{r}(D)) must bijectively assign aq+ka_{q+k} and bp+k+1b_{p+k+1} to the cells (1,c+k+1)(1,c+k+1) and (2,c+k+1)(2,c+k+1). We have LT(er(D))(bp+k)=(1,c+k)L_{T}(e_{r}(D))(b_{p+k})=(1,c+k), and bp+kPaq+kb_{p+k}\not<_{P}a_{q+k}. For LT(er(D))L_{T}(e_{r}(D)) to have increasing rows as per Proposition 8.6, the only choice is LT(er(D))(aq+k)=(2,c+k+1)L_{T}(e_{r}(D))(a_{q+k})=(2,c+k+1) and LT(er(D))(bp+k+1)=(1,c+k+1)L_{T}(e_{r}(D))(b_{p+k+1})=(1,c+k+1). Then (a) and (b) hold true for k+1k+1 as claimed.

Assume aq+ka_{q+k} does not exist or LT(D)(aq+k)L_{T}(D)(a_{q+k}) is not in column c+k+1c+k+1. Equivalently, (r,c+k+1)D(r,c+k+1)\notin D. We will show LT(D)L_{T}(D) and LT(er(D))L_{T}(e_{r}(D)) coincide in column c+k+1c+k+1. If bp+k+1b_{p+k+1} exists then by choice of pp the cells of bp+1,,bp+k+1b_{p+1},\ldots,b_{p+k+1} are rr-paired with a subset of the cells of aq,,ama_{q},\ldots,a_{m}. In particular, aq+ka_{q+k} would have to also exist and LT(D)(bp+k+1)L_{T}(D)(b_{p+k+1}) lies in a column weakly right of LT(D)(aq+k)L_{T}(D)(a_{q+k}), hence strictly right of column c+k+1c+k+1. Therefore, we can see that (r+1,c+k+1)D(r+1,c+k+1)\notin D. If k>0k>0 then we have seen r=1r=1 and (1,c+k),(2,c+k)D(1,c+k),(2,c+k)\in D. Using Lemma 3.6, there can be no cell in column c+k+1c+k+1 of DD in row 3 or greater. Thus column c+k+1c+k+1 of DD is vacant, and the two diagram fillings trivially agree in this column.

Suppose instead k=0k=0. Any (s,c+1)D(s,c+1)\in D is the lowest cell in its column weakly above the row of LT(D)(bp)=(r+1,c)L_{T}(D)(b_{p})=(r+1,c) in DD if and only if it is the lowest cell in its column weakly above the row of LT(er(D))(bp)=(r,c)L_{T}(e_{r}(D))(b_{p})=(r,c) in er(D)e_{r}(D). Similarly if there is (r,c)D(r^{\prime},c)\in D distinct from (r+1,c)(r+1,c) then (s,c+1)(s,c+1) is the lowest cell in its column weakly above rr^{\prime} in DD if and only if this is also the case in er(D)e_{r}(D). It follows that LT(D)L_{T}(D) and LT(er(D))L_{T}(e_{r}(D)) will be defined the same way in column c+1c+1.

Finally, assume LT(D)(aq+k)=(r,c+k+1)L_{T}(D)(a_{q+k})=(r,c+k+1), but bp+k<Paq+kb_{p+k}<_{P}a_{q+k}. We will once again show the two diagram fillings agree in column c+k+1c+k+1. If the column contains only one cell then this is immediate so we will assume it contains two. We have several cases.

  • Case: k=0k=0 and (r+1,c+1)D(r+1,c+1)\notin D
    Any (s,c+1)D(s,c+1)\in D is the lowest cell in its column weakly above the row of LT(D)(bp)=(r+1,c)L_{T}(D)(b_{p})=(r+1,c) in DD if and only if it is the lowest cell in its column weakly above the row of LT(er(D))(bp)=(r,c)L_{T}(e_{r}(D))(b_{p})=(r,c) in er(D)e_{r}(D). If there is (r,c)D(r^{\prime},c)\in D distinct from (r+1,c)(r+1,c) then (s,c+1)(s,c+1) is similarly the lowest cell in its column below row rr^{\prime} in DD if and only if the same is true in er(D)e_{r}(D). Column c+1c+1 will therefore be defined identically in LT(D)L_{T}(D) and LT(er(D))L_{T}(e_{r}(D)).

  • Case: k=0k=0 and (r+1,c+1)D(r+1,c+1)\in D
    If column c+1c+1 is defined in LT(D)L_{T}(D) and LT(er(D))L_{T}(e_{r}(D)) by rule (3) we are done, so assume not.

    We must have bpb_{p} less than the entry corresponding to (r+1,c+1)(r+1,c+1) in DD, hence every entry in column c+1c+1. If LT(D)(bp)L_{T}(D)(b_{p}) is the topmost cell in its column, then the conditions for defining column c+1c+1 of LT(D)L_{T}(D) or LT(er(D))L_{T}(e_{r}(D)) according to rule (1) are not satisfied. If LT(D)(bp)L_{T}(D)(b_{p}) is the lowest cell in its column, then the conditions for defining column c+1c+1 of LT(D)L_{T}(D) or LT(er(D))L_{T}(e_{r}(D)) according to rule (2) are not satisfied. Thus, there must be (r,c)D(r^{\prime},c)\in D distinct from (r+1,c)(r+1,c), and column c+1c+1 of both diagram fillings is determined by mapping the unique entry in column c+1c+1 of the 1 alignment of TT to the lowest cell in column c+1c+1 weakly above row rr^{\prime}.

  • Case: k>0k>0
    We have seen that we must have r=1r=1, and we know (1,c+k),(2,c+k)Der(D)(1,c+k),(2,c+k)\in D\cap e_{r}(D). Using Lemma 3.6, the two cells in column c+k+1c+k+1 of Der(D)D\cap e_{r}(D) can only be (1,c+k+1)(1,c+k+1) and (2,c+k+1)(2,c+k+1). Thus LT(D)(bp+k+1)=(2,c+k+1)L_{T}(D)(b_{p+k+1})=(2,c+k+1). We know bp+k1Paq+kb_{p+k-1}\not<_{P}a_{q+k} so the (3+1)(3+1)-free condition implies aq+k<Pbp+k+1a_{q+k}<_{P}b_{p+k+1}. Thus, every entry in column c+k+1c+k+1 of the 1 alignment of TT is greater than every entry in column c+kc+k. Then column c+k+1c+k+1 of LT(D)L_{T}(D) and LT(er(D))L_{T}(e_{r}(D)) are defined according to rule (3).

Now we fix k0k\geq 0 to be maximal such that for all 0i<k0\leq i<k hypotheses (a) and (b) hold. We have summarily shown that array(LT(er(D)))\mathrm{array}(L_{T}(e_{r}(D))) is obtained from array(LT(D))\mathrm{array}(L_{T}(D)) by putting aq,,aq+k1a_{q},\ldots,a_{q+k-1} in row r+1r+1 and putting bp,,bp+kb_{p},\ldots,b_{p+k} in row rr. Together, these entries form a union CC of connected components of GG, since array(LT(er(D)))\mathrm{array}(L_{T}(e_{r}(D))) is, in fact, a PP-array.

To finish, we must show that CC is actually a single connected component of GG, i.e. the connected component containing bpb_{p}. Assume k>0k>0 hence r=1r=1, else this is trivial. For every 0i<k0\leq i<k we have LT(D)(aq+i)L_{T}(D)(a_{q+i}) above LT(D)(bp+i+1)L_{T}(D)(b_{p+i+1}) in the same column and LT(er(D))(aq+i)L_{T}(e_{r}(D))(a_{q+i}) below LT(er(D))(bp+i+1)L_{T}(e_{r}(D))(b_{p+i+1}) in the same column. Then we must have aq+ibp+i+1a_{q+i}\parallel b_{p+i+1} by Lemma 8.4. We also know bp+iPaq+ib_{p+i}\not<_{P}a_{q+i} for each 0i<k0\leq i<k, and it now suffices to show bp+iPaq+ib_{p+i}\not>_{P}a_{q+i}. If we had bp+i>Paq+i>Paq+i1b_{p+i}>_{P}a_{q+i}>_{P}a_{q+i-1} for i>0i>0, this would contradict that aq+i1bp+ia_{q+i-1}\parallel b_{p+i} as just shown.

Then assume bp>Paqb_{p}>_{P}a_{q}. If bpb_{p} is the only entry in its column of the 1 alignment of TT, then it is in row 1 of TT and aqa_{q} in row 2. This is impossible by property (3) of weak 11 alignments. Then there must be some xPx\in P with LT(D)(x)=(s,c)L_{T}(D)(x)=(s,c) and s>2s>2. Because bpb_{p} and aqa_{q} cannot share a row in TT, xx and aqa_{q} do share a row. Thus x<Paq<Pbpx<_{P}a_{q}<_{P}b_{p} but this contradicts Lemma 8.4. We conclude CC is a connected component of GG and we are done. ∎

Theorem 8.12.

The map

φ:T two-row P-tableau{(T,D)D𝒟(T)}DFAP\varphi:\bigsqcup_{T\text{ two-row $P$-tableau}}\{(T,D)\mid D\in\mathcal{D}(T)\}\to\mathrm{DFA}_{P}

given by (T,D)array(LT(D))(T,D)\mapsto\mathrm{array}(L_{T}(D)) is a bijection, and 𝐰𝐭(D)=𝐰𝐭(φ(T,D))\mathbf{wt}(D)=\mathbf{wt}(\varphi(T,D)). Additionally, DFAP,T\mathrm{DFA}_{P,T} is a connected subset of 𝒜P\mathcal{A}_{P} for each two-row PP-tableau TT.

Proof.

We have that φ\varphi is onto by definition of DFAP\mathrm{DFA}_{P}, and it is also immediate that 𝐰𝐭(D)=𝐰𝐭(φ(T,D))\mathbf{wt}(D)=\mathbf{wt}(\varphi(T,D)) whenever D𝒟(T)D\in\mathcal{D}(T).

Let TT be a two-row PP-tableau and D𝒟(T)D\in\mathcal{D}(T). If D𝔻(T)D\neq{\mathbb{D}}(T) then we may take r1r\geq 1 to be minimal such that er(D)0e_{r}(D)\neq 0 and we get that er(φ(T,D))=φ(T,er(D))e_{r}(\varphi(T,D))=\varphi(T,e_{r}(D)) by Proposition 8.11. Repeated application shows that some sequence of raising operations applied to φ(T,D)\varphi(T,D) gives us φ(T,𝔻(T))=T\varphi(T,{\mathbb{D}}(T))=T, by Lemma 8.7, with the corresponding sequence of PP-arrays being contained in DFAP,T\mathrm{DFA}_{P,T}. Therefore DFAP,T\mathrm{DFA}_{P,T} is a connected subsets of the PP-array crystal.

Moreover, we claim that rr as chosen is minimal such that er(φ(T,D))0e_{r}(\varphi(T,D))\neq 0. To see this, let 1s<r1\leq s<r. Let a1<P<Pama_{1}<_{P}\cdots<_{P}a_{m} and b1<P<Pbnb_{1}<_{P}\cdots<_{P}b_{n} be the entries in rows ss and s+1s+1 of φ(T,D)\varphi(T,D) respectively. By choice of rr, the cell of each bib_{i} in LT(D)L_{T}(D) is ss-paired. In particular, aia_{i} exists and must lie in a column weakly left of bib_{i}. By Lemma 8.9, aiPbia_{i}\not>_{P}b_{i} which confirms that es(A)=0e_{s}(A)=0.

Therefore, the sequence of raising operations applied to φ(T,D)\varphi(T,D) to obtain TT depends only on φ(T,D)\varphi(T,D), not DD or TT per se. This is to say that if we have φ(T,D)=φ(T,D)\varphi(T,D)=\varphi(T^{\prime},D^{\prime}) for some two-row PP-tableau TT^{\prime} and diagram D𝒟(T)D^{\prime}\in\mathcal{D}(T^{\prime}) then the same sequence of raising operations applied to φ(T,D)\varphi(T,D) yields TT^{\prime}, which thus coincides with TT.

Finally, we must show that when DD and DD^{\prime} are distinct diagrams in 𝒟(T)\mathcal{D}(T) then φ(T,D)φ(T,D)\varphi(T,D)\neq\varphi(T,D^{\prime}). We may take some (r,c)DD(r,c)\in D\setminus D^{\prime} and we get that row rr of φ(T,D)\varphi(T,D) contains an entry from column cc of the 1 alignment of TT, while row rr of φ(T,D)\varphi(T,D^{\prime}) contains no such entry. Therefore φ\varphi is a bijection. ∎

Corollary 8.13.

For TT a two-row PP-tableau we have

s𝐰𝐭(T)=ADFAP,Ti1xi𝐰𝐭(A)i.s_{\mathbf{wt}(T)}=\sum_{A\in\mathrm{DFA}_{P,T}}\prod_{i\geq 1}x_{i}^{\mathbf{wt}(A)_{i}}.
Proof.

Using Theorem 3.7 and Theorem 8.12 we have

s𝐰𝐭(T)=s𝐰𝐭(𝔻(T))=D𝒟(T)i1xi𝐰𝐭(D)i=ADFAP,Ti1xi𝐰𝐭(A)i.s_{\mathbf{wt}(T)}=s_{\mathbf{wt}({\mathbb{D}}(T))}=\sum_{D\in\mathcal{D}(T)}\prod_{i\geq 1}x_{i}^{\mathbf{wt}(D)_{i}}=\sum_{A\in\mathrm{DFA}_{P,T}}\prod_{i\geq 1}x_{i}^{\mathbf{wt}(A)_{i}}.

Recall from Remark 3.8 that 𝒟(T)\mathcal{D}(T) is in explicit weight preserving bijection with semi-standard Young tableau. Thus, Theorem 8.12 can be thought of as a partial Robinson-Schensted correspondence for PP-arrays. It would be nice to extend the result to a full bijection, though such an extension is unlikely to be straightforward. For one thing, our partial bijection has the notable property that its image for a fixed PP-tableau is a connected subset of 𝒜P\mathcal{A}_{P}, but after removing this subset for the two-row PP-tableau in Fig. 8 the remaining maximal connected subsets are not individually ss-positive.

References

  • [Ass22] Sami Assaf, Demazure crystals for Kohnert polynomials, Transactions of the AMS 375 (2022), 2147–2186.
  • [BB03] Barry Balof and Kenneth Bogart, Simple inductive proofs of the fishburn and mirkin theorem and the scott-suppes theorem, Order 20 (2003), no. 1, 49–51.
  • [BS17] Daniel Bump and Anne Schilling, Crystal bases: Representations and combinatorics, World Scientific Publishing Company, New Jersey, 2017.
  • [Cho99] Timothy Y. Chow, Descents, quasi-symmetric functions, robinson-schensted for posets, and the chromatic symmetric function, Journal of Algebraic Combinatorics 10 (1999), 227–240.
  • [Gas96] Vesselin Gasharov, Incomparability graphs of (3 + 1)-free posets are s-positive, Discrete Mathematics 157 (1996), no. 1, 193–197.
  • [GP13] Mathieu Guay-Paquet, A modular relation for the chromatic symmetric functions of (3+1)-free posets, 2013.
  • [Kas90] Masaki Kashiwara, Crystalizing the qq-analogue of universal enveloping algebras, Comm. Math. Phys. 133 (1990), no. 2, 249–260.
  • [KP21] Dongkwan Kim and Pavlo Pylyavskyy, Robinson–schensted correspondence for unit interval orders, Sel. Math. New Ser. 27 (2021).
  • [Mag92] Alexander Magid, Enumeration of convex polyominoes: A generalization of the robinson-schensted correspondence and the dimer problem, Ph.D. thesis, Brandeis University, 1992.
  • [SS58] Dana Scott and Patrick Suppes, Foundational aspects of theories of measurement, The Journal of Symbolic Logic 23 (1958), no. 2, 113–128.
  • [SS93] Richard P. Stanley and John R. Stembridge, On immanants of jacobi-trudi matrices and permutations with restricted position, Journal of Combinatorial Theory, Series A 62 (1993), no. 2, 261–279.
  • [Sta95] Richard P. Stanley, A symmetric function generalization of the chromatic polynomial of a graph, Advances in Mathematics 111 (1995), no. 1, 166–194.
  • [Sta98] by same author, Graph colorings and related symmetric functions: ideas and applications a description of results, interesting applications, & notable open problems, Discrete Mathematics 193 (1998), no. 1, 267–286.
  • [SW16] John Shareshian and Michelle L. Wachs, Chromatic quasisymmetric functions, Advances in Mathematics 295 (2016), 497–551.
  • [SWW97] Thomas S. Sundquist, David G. Wagner, and Julian West, A robinson–schensted algorithm for a class of partial orders, Journal of Combinatorial Theory, Series A 79 (1997), no. 1, 36–52.