A Crystal Analysis of -Arrays
Abstract.
Gasharov introduced the combinatorial objects known as -arrays to prove -positivity for the chromatic symmetric functions of incomparability graphs of (3+1)-free posets. We define a crystal, a directed colored graph with some additional axioms, on the set of -arrays. The components of the crystal have -positive characters, thereby refining the -positivity theorems of Gasharov, as well as Shareshian and Wachs. The crystal hints at a possible generalization of the Robinson-Schensted correspondence applied to -arrays.
1. Introduction
The chromatic symmetric function generalizes the chromatic polynomial of a graph [Sta95]. The Stanley-Stembridge Conjecture [SS93, Conjecture 5.5] states that the chromatic symmetric function of the incomparability graph of a (3+1)-free poset is a positive sum of elementary symmetric functions. The conjecture has long motivated research into the chromatic symmetric functions of these graphs.
In particular, Gasharov showed the weaker result that these symmetric functions are a positive sum of Schur functions, or are “-positive” [Gas96]. This was accomplished by reinterpreting the chromatic symmetric functions as generating functions for -arrays, a combinatorial object corresponding to proper colorings. Moreover, the coefficients of the expansion into Schur functions can be stated in terms of -arrays.
Stanley expressed the desire for a direct bijective proof of Gasharov’s result, which would generalize the Robinson-Schensted correspondence [Sta98]. A better understanding of Gasharov’s result could help in addressing the natural suspicion that it holds for the larger class of claw-free graphs [Sta98, Conjecture 1.4]. Some thought has gone towards finding such a Robinson-Schensted correspondence for -arrays [Mag92],[SWW97],[Cho99],[KP21] but the problem in its full generality remains open. Among the immediate consequences of this hypothetical correspondence would be a way to interpret each Schur function in the chromatic symmetric function as an explicit generating function for -arrays in its own right.
In this paper we similarly aim to refine the chromatic symmetric function as a sum of smaller -positive generating functions. Crystals where introduced by Kashiwara [Kas90] and have often served as a paradigm for interpreting and achieving -positivity results, in part due to their connection with the representation theory of Lie groups. We thus construct a crystal on the set of -arrays. The crystal determines a sign-reversing involution, similar to the one in Gasharov’s proof, which we use to show that the crystal components have -positive character. This refines the -positivity theorem of Gasharov.
Guay-Paquet reduced the Stanley-Stembridge Conjecture to the case of unit interval orders [GP13]. More recently, Shareshian and Wachs’ defined a quasisymmetric generalization of the chromatic symmetric function which, when applied to incomparability graphs of natural unit interval orders, suggests a strengthened version of the conjecture and yields an analogously refined -positivity theorem [SW16]. We show that our crystal is also applicable to this quasisymmetric setting, further refining the -positivity theorem. Shareshian and Wachs use an involution similar to Gasharov’s, but more efficient in some sense. By the same measure, our involution is optimal.
Our goals are similar to [KP21] which, subject to additional poset avoidance conditions that are conjectured to be unnecessary, refines -positivity of chromatic quasisymmetric functions for natural unit interval orders. The paper also presents a Robinson-Schensted correspondence in this case. In comparison, our work more generally deals with underlying (3+1)-free posets without additional constraints.
We begin in Section 2 by reviewing the necessary context around -arrays and the chromatic symmetric function. In Section 3 we will explain what we mean by a crystal and discuss the diagram crystal defined in [Ass22]. In Section 4 we will define the alignment of a -array which is a sort of “pairing rule” that will allows us to define the crystal on -arrays in Section 5. The -positivity property of this crystal will be proved in Section 6, and its applicability to the chromatic quasisymmetric function for natural unit interval orders demonstrated in Section 7. Finally, in Section 8 we will attempt to push our construction further by writing individual Schur functions in the expansion as generating functions when they correspond to partitions of length 1 or 2, even when our -array crystal does not tell us how to do so.
This last development relies heavily on the diagram crystal in [Ass22], and the proof is fundamentally bijective which means it can be viewed as a sort of partial Robinson-Schensted correspondence. We are interested to see if the bijection can be extended to partitions of greater lengths. There is also the question of whether a crystal like ours can be defined on the proper colorings of an arbitrary claw-free graph, which would prove -positivity of their chromatic symmetric functions.
2. Chromatic Symmetric Functions
A proper coloring of a graph is a map such that whenever . An independent subset of contains no two elements that form an edge. Proper colorings are then equivalently defined by requiring that is an independent subset for all .
Definition 2.1.
[Sta95] The chromatic symmetric function of a finite graph is given by
where the sum is over all proper colorings of .
It is evident that these functions are indeed symmetric.
Given a poset , its incomparability graph, denoted , has vertex set and edges whenever and are incomparable in , henceforth denoted by . See Fig. 1 for an example of a poset and its incomparability graph. Notice that independent subsets of are precisely the chains in . That is, there is a canonical ordering on any independent subset. This observation motivates the following definition of objects that correspond to proper colorings of the incomparability graph.
Definition 2.2.
[Gas96] Let be a finite poset. A -array is an indexing of the elements of such that if is defined with then is also defined and . We let denote the set of -arrays.
We visualize a -array as the placement of the elements of on a grid indexed by matrix convention, where is placed in position . Fig. 2 shows two -arrays for the poset in Fig. 1.
Given a -array , the corresponding proper coloring of of is defined by . Given a proper coloring , the corresponding -array is obtained by letting be the elements of in increasing order. The weight of a -array is the weak composition whose th part is the number of elements in row . If is the corresponding proper coloring then so we realize that
Developing these combinatorial objects further, we have the following definition.
Definition 2.3.
[Gas96] Let be a poset. A -tableau is a -array with the additional constraint that whenever is defined with , then is also defined and .
The second -array in Fig. 2 is a -tableau. We see that the weight of a -tableau is a partition in general, i.e. if is a -tableau then for all .
A poset is (+)-free, for natural numbers and , if it does not contain as an induced subposet the disjoint union of a -chain with a -chain. The poset in Fig. 1 is (3+1)-free for instance.
Let denote the Schur function indexed by a partition . We say a symmetric function is -positive if it is a sum of Schur functions. A graph is said to be -positive if its chromatic symmetric function is. The following theorem by Gasharov now reveals the motivation behind the definition of -tableaux.
Theorem 2.4.
[Gas96] Let be a (3+1)-free poset. Then where is the number of -tableaux of weight . In particular, is -positive.
The theorem and its proof don’t give us an idea of which monomials (-arrays) “contribute” to which Schur functions (-tableaux) in any canonical way. Our primary goal in this paper is then to refine this result by developing a finer structure on -arrays for a more localized explanation of -positivity.
3. Crystals
A crystal is a colored directed graph consisting of the data . Here is a vertex set. For all the functions called the crystal raising and lowering operators respectively, must satisfy if and only if . The map is the weight map where is the set of -valued sequences with finitely many nonzero entries. Letting with the 1 as the th entry, whenever we also require that . The character of a crystal with vertex set is
Finally, a highest weight element of a crystal with vertex set is some such that for all . A more comprehensive description of crystals can be found in [BS17].
Be warned that we will overload the symbols and to be used on multiple vertex sets. However, there should be no ambiguity as it will be clear to which vertex set the maps are being applied.
In the following sections we will define a crystal for any (3+1)-free poset , with as already defined. We see that coincides with and is therefore -positive by Theorem 2.4. Showing that the character of any connected component of the crystal is -positive therefore generalizes this result, which is exactly what we intend to do. It will take us until Section 5 to define the operators and for this crystal, and until Section 6 to prove the refined -positivity result.
3.1. The Diagram Crystal
For the remainder of this section we will discuss Assaf’s diagram crystal [Ass22]. This is not a prerequisite for understanding anything up through Section 7. However, it may be a helpful example of a crystal with nice properties, and it is necessary for Section 8 where we partially succeed in pushing our refinement of Theorem 2.4 even further.
By a diagram we mean a finite subset of which we will interpret as positions in a grid using matrix convention. The elements of a diagram are referred to as its cells. We let denote the set of diagrams. The weight map on is defined so that is the number of cells in row of .
Definition 3.1.
[Ass22] Let be a diagram and . The set of -pairs of is a set of disjoint pairs of cells between rows and defined iteratively as follows. We say that two unpaired cells and in rows and respectively with weakly left of form an -pair whenever every other cell in rows and in a column weakly between and is already part of an -pair.
Definition 3.2.
[Ass22] We define on as follows. If every cell in row of is -paired then . Otherwise, take to be the rightmost cell in row of that is not -paired and set . That is, we “move” the cell to row .
Definition 3.3.
[Ass22] Given the above definition, the crystal lowering operator is implicitly defined as follows. Let . If every cell in row of is -paired then . Otherwise, take to be the leftmost cell in row of that is not -paired and set .
Fig. 3 shows the diagrams reachable from using only edges colored 1 and 2.
We will also find useful the notion of column -pairing which is defined similarly to -pairing.
Definition 3.4.
[Ass22] Let be a diagram and . The column -pairing of is an iterative construction where we say that two cells and in columns and respectively with in a row weakly below that of are column -paired whenever every other cell in columns and in a row weakly between and is already column -paired.
The following is a consequence of [Ass22, Theorem 4.2.5].
Proposition 3.5.
The diagram crystal raising and lowering operators do not change the number of column -pairs.
We will find this proposition applicable when a diagram shares a connected component in the crystal with a diagram that is “top-justified”, i.e. such that when with we have as well. In this case, Proposition 3.5 implies every cell in the shorter of the two columns and is column -paired.
A second invariant of components in the diagram crystal that we will find useful is given by the next lemma.
Lemma 3.6.
Let be a diagram and consider sequences of cells in such that and . The maximal length of such a sequence is unchanged by the crystal raising and lowering operators.
Proof.
Suppose is a sequence of cells in a diagram with and of maximal length. We will show that there is such a sequence of cells of length in if .
The only way this might not be the case is if for some and were to remove from . In this case, we have . Unless and , we get another sequence of cells in with the desired properties by simply replacing in the sequence with . So assume and .
We know is not -paired in . Then must be -paired with some with . Replacing in the sequence with then gives us a sequence in of length with the desired properties.
It is similar to show that if then has such a sequence of cells of length . ∎
Once again considering the cases of a component containing a top-justified diagram, the lemma says that the maximal length of a sequence of cells as described above is the maximal number of cells in a column.
Assaf’s Theorem 5.3.4 specializes to the following statement.
Theorem 3.7.
[Ass22] Let be a top-justified diagram. Then the character of the component of the diagram crystal containing is . Additionally, is the unique highest weight element in its connected component.
Remark 3.8.
The theorem as presented in [Ass22] actually shows that there is a crystal isomorphism between the relevant components of the diagram crystal and a tableaux crystal. The diagrams in a given component are then in weight preserving bijection with semi-standard Young tableaux of shape .
4. The Alignment
For the remainder of this paper, is always a finite (3+1)-free poset. In this section we will introduce the alignment of a -array. The alignment will be fundamental for defining the crystal operators on -arrays in Section 5. It is a way of horizontally spacing out the elements of rows and , and can be thought of as a “pairing rule,” analogous to the idea of -pairs for the diagram crystal, which helps us determine how and affect rows and .
Definition 4.1.
Let be a -array and let . Let the chains and be the elements of rows and of respectively. Let be the function inductively defined so that for each , and
Then we define the pre-alignment of to be the map
such that each maps to , and each to .
Fig. 4 shows a visualization of the pre-alignment for a -array if is as in Fig. 1, row of contains the elements and row contains .
mathmode, centertableaux,boxsize=1.5em{ytableau}
\none[r]&\none\nonebcd
\none[r+1]\noneah
Definition 4.2.
Let be a -array and let . Let the chains and be the elements of rows and of respectively. Let be the pre-alignment. We construct the alignment of as follows.
Suppose we have some . Select the rightmost element mapped to some such that column of is nonempty and contains no , if such an exists. Then we define
so that and coincides with elsewhere. If no such exists then the alignment of is defined to be .
mathmode, centertableaux,boxsize=1.5em{ytableau}
\none[r]&\none\nonebcd
\none[r+1]\nonea\noneh
Proposition 4.3.
The alignment of a -array is well-defined. Additionally, if and are the elements of rows and of respectively, then in the alignment each is in a column strictly left of and each is in a column strictly left of .
Proof.
Our attention is restricted entirely to rows and of . That the pre-alignment satisfies the condition on and is immediate from the definition. Let be the rightmost occupied column in the pre-alignment. Suppose we have as in Definition 4.2 that satisfies the condition on and , and the rightmost occupied column of is .
Should these inductive hypotheses continue to hold, we will have shown that the process to determine the alignment must terminate, as we are limited by in how far we can shift each element to the right. The other obstacle to well-definiteness is the question of whether , as in the definition, is unique when it exists. To this end, consider some column in which contains two elements, some and . If column contains an element in then by assumption it is either or . Thus, there is at most one element in column for which there is no greater element in column . This indeed proves that is uniquely determined when it exists.
Now suppose exists and resides in some column of . By choice of , column is nonempty in , so . In we know is mapped to column , so any column right of remains unoccupied. Moreover, if for some , then by the inductive hypothesis (if it exists) is strictly left of column in both and . If exists then it is strictly right of column of and using both the inductive hypothesis and the choice of . The same argument can be made when for some . Then the inductive hypothesis on and continues to hold. ∎
Lemma 4.4.
In the alignment of a -array , any element in row that does not share a column with an element in row is strictly left of any element in row that does not share a column with an element in row .
Proof.
This is clear for the row pre-alignment. Prior to moving an element from some column to column while obtaining the alignment, column must contain an element in each row while column contains exactly one element. Thus, the property is maintained as we move elements to the right. ∎
In Section 5 we will define our crystal operators on using the alignment. To prove that our operators are essentially inverses as required, we will want to see that they act predictably on the alignment. This motivates us to write a more static characterization of the alignment, as opposed to the procedural definition.
Definition 4.5.
Let be a -array. Let the chains and be the elements of rows and of respectively. A weak alignment of is a map satisfying the following properties:
-
(1)
each is mapped to row in a column strictly right of if it exists, and each is mapped to row in a column strictly right of if it exists,
-
(2)
if maps an element to some column , then it also maps an element to column ,
-
(3)
if with mapped to row and mapped to row then is mapped to a column strictly left of , and
-
(4)
if some is mapped to some column , then either maps some to column or it maps no elements to column .
Definition 4.6.
Let be a -array. Let the chains and be the elements of rows and of respectively. Let . We write when the position of each element in is in a column weakly left of its position in . This defines a partial order on such maps. If and are weak alignments of we write .
Proposition 4.7.
Let be a -array and . The alignment is the unique minimal weak alignment according to the partial order .
Proof.
That the alignment satisfies (1) and (4) follows by definition. Property (3) is clear in the pre-alignment, and can never be shifted right into a column containing . So (3) holds in the alignment as well.
Let denote the pre-alignment. For every element in a column of there is a lesser element in column . Therefore there is some chain of elements in consecutive columns where is in the first column and is in the rightmost nonempty column, call it . No element can move right of as we construct the alignment, and therefore each element in the chain is in the same position in the alignment. This proves that the alignment satisfies (2), and is therefore a weak alignment.
Now let be a weak alignment. For any there is some sequence
(possibly with ) that is increasing in and occupy consecutive columns in the pre-alignment, similarly to above. By properties (1) and (3), each element in this sequence must be in a column strictly right of the preceding one in . Thus, the position of in is weakly right of its position in the pre-alignment. The same is certainly true for each so .
Let be an intermediate step between the pre-alignment and alignment as in Definition 4.2, and assume . Suppose there exists a rightmost in such that the adjacent column to its right is nonempty and contains no element greater than . We will show lies strictly right in of its position in . This is true if is in the rightmost nonempty column of , which is weakly right of the rightmost nonempty column of , which is in turn strictly right of in . Otherwise, there is some one column right of in by (4).
Say lies in column in . If lies in a column strictly right of in , it must be in column for some by choice of . Then lies strictly right of column in which means lies strictly right of in .
Suppose instead lies in some column weakly left of in . Then and lie in opposite rows. However, this means any element right of in is greater than which contradicts our choice of . By induction we can now say that . Then if is the alignment we have . ∎
Using Proposition 4.7, we end the section with a final useful lemma.
Lemma 4.8.
If the alignment of maps a unique element to some column , then any element strictly left of is smaller than any element weakly right of in the alignment.
Proof.
Let be an element strictly left of , and an element weakly right of . If and share a row, then by (1) in Definition 4.5. We have by (4) in Definition 4.5, so if shares a row with we have as well. Thus, assume shares a row with and does not.
If is in row , let be the element in the same column of row which exists by Lemma 4.4. We have by (3) in Definition 4.5 so by the (3+1)-free condition.
Otherwise, it suffices to assume is the leftmost element in row in a column strictly right of . If does not share a column with any element in row then once again we have by (4) in Definition 4.5. So suppose we have some in the same column as in row . If we had in this circumstance, that would imply by the (3+1)-free condition, and also . Then moving the position of one column to the left would still satisfy conditions (1)-(4) in Definition 4.5, contradicting Proposition 4.7. ∎
5. The -Array Crystal
We now have the tools to define the crystal operators on .
Definition 5.1.
The crystal lowering operator acts on as follows. Let and be the entries of rows and of respectively.
-
•
If every column of the alignment with an entry in row also contains an entry in row then define .
-
•
Otherwise let be minimal such that does not share a column with an element in row in the alignment. Let be minimal such that there is no one column right of . Then we move to row , and any that shares a column with one of these entries to row .
Proposition 5.2.
The crystal lowering operator is well-defined, and if we have with then .
Proof.
Let and let and be the entries of rows and of respectively. Select as in the definition, assuming it exists. By Lemma 4.4 every nonempty column strictly right of the column containing in the alignment must contain an entry in row . In particular, there is no in any column strictly right of and it therefore makes sense to select as in the definition. The entries reside in consecutive columns of the alignment by Lemma 4.4 and property (1) of weak alignments, and for each there is some that shares a column with by choice of . Let be minimal such that either lies in a column strictly right of or does not exist. The relevant columns of the alignment are then as in Fig. 6 (which degenerates to just the column containing if ).
mathmode, centertableaux,boxsize=2.5em{ytableau}
ap&ap+1ap+2⋯ap+t
\nonebqbq+1⋯bq+t-1
We must show
-
(i)
-
(ii)
-
(iii)
-
(iv)
whenever these indices are valid. The point being that (i) and (ii) show row of is a chain, and (iii) and (iv) show row of is a chain. When we need not consider (iii) or (iv).
We have (i) immediately from Lemma 4.8. If is one column right of then (ii) follows by choice of . Otherwise, by Lemma 4.4 there is some with that shares a column with . By (3) in Definition 4.5, so we get (ii) by the (3+1)-free condition.
If we know so (iv) follows from the (3+1)-free condition. By property (3) in Definition 4.5 we have so (iii) follows from the (3+1)-free condition.
Fig. 6 makes clear that . ∎
Lemma 5.3.
Let be a -array. Let and be the elements whose rows are swapped by as in Fig. 6. Then for each .
Proof.
We have by choice of , thus . Since shares a column with in the alignment, we have by property (3) in Definition 4.5. ∎
As with the crystal lowering operator, we will soon define the crystal raising operator using the alignment of a -array. To eventually see that these two operations are inverses, we then want to know how affects the alignment. The answer is given by the following lemma.
Lemma 5.4.
Applying to a -array does not change the column of any entry in the alignment.
Proof.
Let and be the entries of rows and of respectively. Proposition 5.2 demonstrates that the entries of rows and in are respectively given by
and
for and as in the definition of , and minimal such that either does not exist or lies in a column strictly right of in the alignment of . Define
so that it agrees with the alignment, except on which are sent to row , and which are sent to row , without changing column assignments. This amounts to swapping the rows in Fig. 6. We must show that is the alignment of .
We see that inherits from the alignment of properties (1), (2), and (4) in Definition 4.5. The only entries in row of weakly left of some with are among . All these entries occupy the same position in the alignment of so cannot violate (3). For , the only entries in row of left of that do not also occupy row in the alignment of are for which are less than and therefore do not violate (3) in Definition 4.5. The only elements of row left of in are that are lesser than . Each for shares a column with an incomparable element by Lemma 5.3, so cannot violate (3). So is a weak alignment of .
Suppose we have a weak alignment of such that . We will show . Since is the leftmost element in row of the alignment of that does not share a column with an entry in row , we know from Lemma 4.4 that occupy adjacent columns in the alignment of , hence in . Properties (1) and (3) of weak alignments force each element in this chain to be strictly right of the previous element in , so the elements of this chain occupy the same columns in and .
Take for and suppose occupies the same column in and for any . The only elements greater than are those , and possibly some for . We have assumed that each such greater element occupies the same column in and . Recalling that is the leftmost element in row of the alignment of that does not share a column with an entry in row , Lemma 4.4 precludes from being strictly right of in the alignment, hence in . Then in , (3) and (4) place one column left of the leftmost entry greater than . Property (4) forces to occupy the same position in .
Since by choice of we have for each , we know by the (3+1)-free condition (if exists). We also have by Lemma 5.3. This means that in , each such is one column left of the leftmost entry greater than if such an entry exists. We have already determined that and agree on the positions of entries greater than any of , other than these entries themselves. Now properties (1) and (4) of weak alignments prohibit from placing any of these strictly left of its position in .
It remains only to show that and agree on . Define
to agree with the alignment of (hence the column assignments of ), except on the positions of where it instead agrees with . We know places each left of so it satisfies (1). Column assignments in all agree with which therefore satisfies (2) and (4).
If for some and then the positions of these entries in agrees with the alignment of and therefore they do not violate (3). For we can only have for some . The positions of these elements in agree with so cannot violate (3) either. Then is a weak alignment that precedes the alignment of according . Then is, in fact, the alignment of by Proposition 4.7. In particular, for we have . Therefore so is the alignment of by Proposition 4.7. ∎
We next give a series of analogous statements for the crystal raising operator. The proofs are mostly, but not entirely, symmetric.
Definition 5.5.
The crystal raising operator acts on as follows. Let and be the entries of rows and of respectively.
-
•
If every column of the alignment with an entry in row also contains an entry in row then define .
-
•
Otherwise let be maximal such that does not share a column with an entry in row in the alignment. Let be minimal such that there is no one column right of . Then we move to row , and any that shares a column with one of these entries to row .
Proposition 5.6.
The crystal raising operator is well-defined, and if we have with then .
Proof.
Let and let and be the entries of rows and of respectively. Select as in the definition, assuming it exists. If the column immediately right of in the alignment contains some , then by Lemma 4.8, and it therefore makes sense to select as in the definition of . The entries reside in consecutive columns of the alignment by choice of and property (3) of weak alignments, and for each there is some that shares a column with . Let be minimal such that either lies in a column strictly right of or does not exist. The relevant columns of the alignment are then as shown in Fig. 7 (which degenerates to just the column containing if ).
mathmode, centertableaux,boxsize=2.5em{ytableau}
\none&aqaq+1⋯aq+t-1
bpbp+1bp+2⋯bp+t
To show that both rows of are chains, it suffices to show
-
(i)
-
(ii)
-
(iii)
-
(iv)
whenever these indices are valid. When we need not consider (iii) or (iv).
We have (i) immediately from Lemma 4.8. By choice of we know that , if it exists, lies one column right . Then (ii) follows by choice of .
If we have so (iv) follows from the (3+1)-free condition. We also know so we must have or we could violate the characterization of the alignment of given in Proposition 4.7 by shifting one position to the left. Thus (iii) follows from the (3+1)-free condition.
Fig. 7 makes clear that . ∎
Lemma 5.7.
Let be a -array. Let and be the elements whose rows are swapped by as in Fig. 7. Then for each .
Proof.
We have by choice of . Were we to have , we could shift left one position in the alignment of and we would still have a weak alignment, contradicting Proposition 4.7.
On the other hand, by property (3) of weak alignments. ∎
Lemma 5.8.
Applying to a -array does not change the column of any element in the alignment.
Proof.
Let and be the entries of rows and of respectively. Proposition 5.6 demonstrates that rows and in are given by
and
where and are as in the definition of , and is minimal such that either does not exist or lies in a column strictly right of in the alignment of . Define
so that it agrees with the alignment of , except on which are sent to row , and which are sent to row . This amounts to swapping the rows in Fig. 7. We must show that is the alignment of .
We see that inherits from the alignment of properties (1), (2), and (4) in Definition 4.5. Any entry in row of weakly left of for some is also in row weakly left of in the alignment of and therefore cannot violate (3). The only elements in row of weakly left of for are either in the same position in the alignment of , or are some . Either way, such cannot be part of a violation of (3). Each with shares a column in with an incomparable element by Lemma 5.7 and so cannot violate (3) either. So is a weak alignment.
Suppose we have a weak alignment such that . We will show that . Since is the rightmost entry in row of the alignment of that does not share a column with an entry in row , we know from Lemma 4.4 that occupy adjacent columns in the alignment of , hence in . Properties (1) and (3) of weak alignments force each element in this chain to lie strictly right of the previous one in , so the elements of this chain occupy the same columns in and .
Let be some element of the chain , and assume we have determined all elements greater than in the chain to occupy the same position in both and . In this case, we have in fact determined by the previous paragraph that all entries greater than , in the chain or otherwise, occupy the same position in both and . If , i.e. lies in a column left of in the alignment of , then this chain is vacuous as there cannot exist in a column strictly right of by choice of . Assuming we then know must lie weakly left of in , hence in , by choice of . Then the position of is uniquely determined by (3) and (4) in both and to be one column left of the leftmost greater element . Since occupies the same position in and by induction, so to does .
It remains to show and agree on . Define
to agree with the alignment of (hence the column assignments of ), except on the positions of where it instead agrees with . We know places each left of so it satisfies (1). Column positions of agree with which therefore satisfies (2) and (4).
The positions of each with and each agree between and the alignment of , so no such can violate (3) in . For , we can only have if . The positions of these elements in agree with so cannot violate (3) either. Then is a weak alignment that precedes the alignment of according to . Then is, in fact, the alignment of by Proposition 4.7. In particular, for we have . Therefore so is the alignment of by Proposition 4.7. ∎
Proposition 5.9.
Let be a -array. Consider the induced subgraph of restricted to vertices in rows and of . Applying or to swaps the rows of the elements in a single connected component of .
Proof.
We will prove this for , with the argument for being symmetric. If swaps the row of some , and if is incomparable to , then cannot share a row with either before or after applying which is to say swaps the row of as well. Thus swaps the rows of elements in a union of connected components of .
Now we must show that all elements whose rows are swapped by belong to the same connected component. Let and be the entries of rows and of respectively. Let and be the entries whose rows will be changed by , as in Fig. 6. We have that for by Lemma 5.3. That is to say each column in Fig. 6 is a subset of a connected component. This also implies , and we have by definition of . Thus there is an edge in between each column in Fig. 6. So all of and belong to the same connected component as desired. ∎
We have seen in Propositions 5.2 and 5.6 that and are well-defined and affect the weight map in the correct way. The following theorem then completes the verification that is a crystal.
Theorem 5.10.
For we have if and only if .
Proof.
If then by Lemma 5.4 and Lemma 4.4, the leftmost entry in row of the alignment of that does not share a column with an entry in row , is the rightmost element in row of the alignment of that does not share a column with an entry in row . By Proposition 5.9, both and operate by swapping the rows of the entries in the connected component of of the induced subgraph of restricted to vertices in rows and of , or equivalently . Thus . The other direction is similar. ∎
Fig. 8 shows an example of a poset and a subset of with edges given by the crystal.
db
b
d
\none
db
c
d&b
c&a
db
c&a
d
c
d&a
d&b
c
b
c
In the context of our crystal on , the -tableaux now hold crystal-theoretic significance.
Theorem 5.11.
The highest weight elements of are the -tableaux.
Proof.
Let and take to be arbitrary. Let and be the entries of rows and of respectively. Suppose . Then every nonempty column in the alignment of contains some . By property (2) of weak alignments this means each is in column of the alignment. Each is necessarily in column or greater, so by property (3). This shows that rows and of satisfy the required column condition of -tableaux.
Conversely, suppose and for each . Then each gets mapped to column in the pre-alignment of . As entries shift right to obtain the -alignment, the chain must stay put, and the entries will never move past the rightmost occupied column . Thus, every nonempty column in the alignment of contains some which means .
We have shown that is equivalent to the -tableau column condition on elements in rows and . Therefore is a highest weight element if and only if it is a -tableau. ∎
6. -Positivity
Note that the crystal on induces a crystal on any subset. In this section we will be studying characters of connected components of . If is a connected component, we will use the notation to denote the set of -arrays in with weight .
Proposition 6.1.
If is a connected component of then is a symmetric function.
Proof.
We must show that the cardinalities of and match when is a permutation of . It suffices to assume for a simple transposition , and without loss of generality.
The next result is our awaited refinement of Theorem 2.4. The proof follows in the spirit of Gasharov’s by using the Jacobi-Trudi identity and the usual inner product on symmetric functions to get an alternating formula for the Schur coefficients in terms of the monomial coefficients [Gas96]. However, the involution we use to cancel terms is based on our crystal operators, which allows us to stay within a connected component of the crystal.
Theorem 6.2.
Let be a connected component of . Then where is the number of -tableaux in of weight .
Proof.
Let be the expansion of into the Schur basis for symmetric functions. Set and let be a partition of . For we let denote the weak composition with th component for . Notice that when , as we have for some which yields
The Jacobi-Trudi identity says
where here denotes the complete homogeneous symmetric function of the weak composition . If is not a weak composition, i.e. it has a negative part, then is considered to be zero. Recall that the Schur functions are an orthonormal basis with respect to the inner product on symmetric functions defined by where stands for the monomial symmetric function indexed by . Therefore
(1) |
where takes the value when .
We will define an involution . Let for some . If is a -tableau then set . Otherwise, there is a minimal such that some exists with , but either does not exist or . With so fixed, let be maximal among such .
For convenience denote rows and of by and . For we have which puts in column of the pre-alignment of . If does not exist, then is placed in column of the pre-alignment. This is to say column either contains or or is emtpy. Since is (3+1)-free and when , we have that such are less than , if it exists. Then every entry in a column strictly left of in the pre-alignment is less than any entry in column . This prohibits any of these lesser entries from occupying column in the alignment, as none of them can enter column until both and have vacated, but neither can an entry be moved into a previously empty column. This is to say that in the alignment, the entries weakly left of column are exactly and .
The remaining entries and now lie strictly right of column in the alignment. So if then there are at least
such that do not share a column with an entry in row . Then it makes sense to define
If instead then there are at least
entries strictly right of column that do not share a column with an entry in row . Here, it makes sense to define
In either of these cases, note that gets mapped into . This means both that reverses the sign of , and our codomain is correct.
In the case where we have seen that the entries in row of the alignment that do not share a column with an entry in row lie strictly right of column . Similarly, in the case where , we know the rightmost in row of the alignment that do not share a column with an entry in row all lie strictly right of column . In both cases, and lie weakly left of column . So will not change the rows of any or . That is, does not change the indices of any with , or with and . The selection of both and between and therefore agree, and to apply to is to apply
or
which are both the identity map by Theorem 5.10.
Since reverses the sign of -arrays that are not -tableaux, terms cancel in equation 1 to get
summed over -tableaux in . If then which means each such -tableau is in as it must have partition weight. Furthermore, these -tableaux have positive sign so we conclude is the number of -tableaux of weight in . ∎
Recall that by Proposition 5.9, our crystal operators, and therefore our involution , work by flipping connected components of the incomparability graph restricted to relevant rows. This is necessary if we want to obtain another -array from our input. As a quick point of comparison between our involution and previous variations used to obtain coarser -positivity theorems, Gasharov would have us flip all such connected components right of what we called column [Gas96], while Shareshian and Wachs would have us flip the subset of those connected components which have odd cardinality [SW16, Proof of Thm 6.3]. Our involution is even more restrained, flipping a minimal number of these components.
7. Natural Unit Interval Orders
A unit interval order is a poset isomorphic to a finite subset of with the relation when . These are axiomatized by the requirements that they be (3+1)-free and (2+2)-free, which can be seen as a modification to the argument presented in [SS58] or more directly in [BB03].
Definition 7.1.
A natural unit interval order is a finite poset on a subset of such that
-
•
implies as natural numbers, and
-
•
if with and , then as natural numbers.
These define the same isomorphism classes as the unit interval orders [SW16].
Definition 7.2.
[SW16] Given a finite graph with , define the chromatic quasisymmetric function by
summed over all proper colorings of , where
An edge that counts towards is an ascent.
We of course recover the chromatic symmetric function as .
If is a (3+1)-free poset on a subset of , then for we write to mean where is the proper coloring of that corresponds to by sending row of to the number . In other words, is the number of pairs such that , as natural numbers, and occurs in a higher row of than . When is a natural unit interval order we will see that the crystal on respects this statistic.
Theorem 7.3.
If is a natural unit interval order then is constant on connected components of the -array crystal.
Proof.
Let with . We must show .
Let be the graph induced by by restricting to the vertices in rows and of . By Proposition 5.9, is obtained from by swapping the rows of all elements in some connected components of . Because is bipartite and is (3+1)-free, the degree of each vertex is at most 2 and therefore is a path or a cycle. Since we know contains some elements in row of , and elements in row . Since is bipartite and has an odd number of elements, is in fact a path.
Suppose we have some and with . If then neither element changes rows between and so the pair is an ascent in both or neither of and . If then cannot reside in either row or of . Again, the pair is an ascent in both or neither of and .
To show we must finally show that there is a 1-1 correspondence between ascents in and ascents in which occur entirely within . In both cases, we will there is exactly one ascent involving each given from row of (equivalently row of ), which is enough since each ascent must include exactly one such element. Since is a path containing elements from row and elements from row of , each element in row has degree 2 in . Then there are in row of with , and with incomparable to both. By definition of a natural unit interval order, as natural numbers. Then is an ascent in but not , and is an ascent in but not . These are the only elements in incomparable to , so these are the only possible ascents contained in involving . ∎
Now if is a connected component of the -array crystal for a natural unit interval order, it makes sense to define as for any . Therefore we have the following corollary.
Corollary 7.4.
If is a natural unit interval order then
summed over connected components of the -array crystal.
8. Two-Row -Tableaux
For the remainder of the paper we again assume only that the poset is (3+1)-free. We have seen that we can refine into connected components which have -positive characters, but these characters are still not single Schur functions in general. Take, for instance, the component shown in Fig. 8 which contains two -tableaux.
However, we will develop an explicit method to write the Schur functions corresponding to certain -tableaux as generating functions of disjoint connected subsets of . These -tableaux , are those such that for all , and we call them two-row -tableaux. If is a two-row -tableau we also say the diagram of is the image of the 1 alignment of , which we denote .
Lemma 8.1.
If is a two-row -tableau then each cell in row 2 of has a cell directly above it in row 1.
Proof.
By Theorem 5.11 we have from which the result follows. ∎
For a two-row -tableau we have which, by Lemma 8.1 and Theorem 3.7, is the character of the connected component of in the diagram crystal. In order to write as the generating function for a set of -arrays, we therefore want to associate the diagrams with highest weight to some -arrays in a weight preserving way. Let denote this set of diagrams.
Definition 8.2.
Let be a two-row -tableau, and . The filling or diagram filling of with respect to is a bijection constructed column by column from left to right as follows.
Suppose we have determined the entries mapped to all cells strictly left of some column . If column of the 1 alignment of contains a unique entry, we map it to the unique cell in column of . Otherwise, column of the 1 alignment contains two entries in rows 1 and 2 respectively. We assign and to the cells in column according to the first of the following rules whose prerequisites are met.
-
(1)
Suppose some is mapped to the topmost cell in column of , and that there is exactly one greater than . Then we let be maximal such that and we map to and the remaining poset element to the remaining cell.
-
(2)
Suppose some is mapped to the lowest cell in column of , and that there is exactly one greater than . Then we let be maximal such that and we map to and the remaining poset element to the remaining cell.
-
(3)
Map and to the upper and lower cells in column of respectively.
Proposition 8.3.
Let be a two-row -tableau, and . The diagram filling is well-defined.
Proof.
If column contains two cells in , then Proposition 3.5 implies each cell in column must be column -paired. Then for any there exists with as presumed in rules (1) and (2). ∎
We denote the set of diagram fillings by
and the set of diagram fillings for a fixed two-row -tableau by
The point of this construction is that each row of a diagram filling increases in from left to right, so the filling specifies a -array. We will prove this shortly.
Lemma 8.4.
Let be a two-row -tableau, and . Let be in the same column in the alignment of with in row 1 and in row 2. Suppose they satisfy the condition that whenever we have a distinct element we have as well. Then is in a row above . In particular, this applies when .
Proof.
The proof is by induction on the column index. If then the column is governed by rule (3) so we are done.
Suppose and that the column’s assignments are defined according to rule (2). This is to say there is some assigned to the lowest cell in column of , and since we cannot have only that . We must have that is distinct from the topmost cell in column since rule (1) does not apply. By Proposition 3.5, both cells in column are column -paired which means that both cells in column are in rows weakly above . Therefore, when we take to be maximal such that it must be the case that is the lowest cell in column and is the image of .
Finally suppose and that the column’s assignments are defined according to rule (1). There is some assigned to the topmost cell in column , and we know that . We therefore must have that is in row 2 of the 1 alignment of . Let be the element in row 1 column of the 1 alignment. If we have some then also by the (3+1)-free condition, but the inductive hypothesis contradicts being the topmost cell in column . So rule (1) never actually applies in these circumstances. ∎
Remark 8.5.
If and are comparable, then by property (3) of weak alignments, so Lemma 8.4 applies.
Proposition 8.6.
Let be a two-row -tableau and . Suppose we have cells such that and . Further assume there is no distinct with and . Then and for some .
Proof.
Let be the entries mapped to the cells and respectively. If there is some column with that contains only one entry in the 1 alignment, then by Lemma 4.8.
We may proceed under the assumption that there is no such column , and we first deal with the subcase where . Suppose is the topmost cell in column . If every entry in column of the 1 alignment of is greater than , we are done. Otherwise, by definition of weak alignments there is one entry in column that is greater than , and one entry in column that is not. Rule (1) of the definition of diagram fillings therefore applies, and ensures that the entry greater than is assigned to . That is, .
Suppose instead that there is with , hence by assumption. Say . If column of the filling is defined according to rule (1), then there is a single entry in column of the 1 alignment of that is greater than . We must have that and share a row in . Moreover, since must be mapped to a row weakly less than . So and share a row in implying . If column of the filling is not defined according to rule (1), and every entry in column of the 1 alignment of is greater than , we again have in particular. If column of the filling is not defined according to rule (1) and there is exactly one entry in column of the alignment greater than , then column of the filling is defined according to rule (2). This ensures that the entry greater than is mapped to , which is to say .
Now suppose , still assuming there is no column with containing just one cell. Proposition 3.5 implies that each cell in a column with is column -paired. This further implies that the topmost cell in each such column is in a row weakly below the topmost cell in column . Then cannot be the topmost cell in column , else there would be some with . So is the lowest cell in its column. Since the 1 alignment of is a weak 1 alignment, there is a chain of entries in columns . If we are done, so assume not. We must have by Lemma 8.4 since is the lowest cell in column . Then by the (3+1)-free condition. ∎
In particular, if we apply Proposition 8.6 when , we see that the entries in each row of the diagram fillings form a chain. We have therefore justified our earlier claim that each diagram filling gives us a -array. Explicitly, for we write to mean the -array where is the th cell from the left in row of . Let
denote the set of -arrays obtained from diagram fillings, and let
denote the set of -arrays obtained from diagram fillings with a fixed two-row -tableau .
Lemma 8.7.
Let a two-row -tableau. We have .
Proof.
If some column of is not defined according to rule (1) or (2) in Definition 8.2, then the column assignments of entries in this column agree with . Rules (1) and (2) only apply if there are some in columns and of the 1 alignment of respectively with . Then must be placed in the row opposite to in both and . By induction, we see that and must agree on the rows of all elements in column of the 1 alignment of . ∎
Lemma 8.8.
Let be a two-row -tableau and . Let and say . If column of contains two cells, then there exists with for some .
Proof.
Suppose is the topmost cell in column of . If there is exactly one in column of then rule (1) in the definition of ensures it resides in a row weakly above . Otherwise, both elements in column are greater than , with at least one still being weakly above row by Proposition 3.5.
Lemma 8.9.
Let be a two-row -tableau and . Suppose for some we have and with and . Then .
Proof.
If there is some column with that contains only one cell in , then the result follows by Lemma 4.8. So assume not.
In light of Lemma 8.8 we may take a chain where each consecutive element is one column to the right, and in a row weakly above the position of the previous element, and is in column of . If we are done, and if not then is in a weakly row above and therefore strictly above . Now would be a contradiction of Lemma 8.4. ∎
Lemma 8.10.
Let be a two-row -tableau and let . Let be minimal such that . Let be the element such that is the rightmost cell in row that is not -paired. Then is the rightmost entry in row of the alignment of that does not share a column with an entry in row .
Proof.
Let and be the entries of rows and in respectively. Let be maximal such that is not -paired. Say .
Suppose we have some with maximal such that is in a column strictly left of column . Say and assume . By Lemma 3.6, there can be no sequence of cells with each and . Thus, cannot be -paired without forming such a sequence together with the -paired cell and . By choice of , we must then have . Since we can say that column of the 1 alignment of contains two entries using Lemma 4.8. Then in , we must have column -paired with contradicting either the choice of , or the fact that is not 1-paired. Then we must have .
Since is not 1-paired, each with must be 1-paired to some with . Any must then be in a column weakly left of for . Then by Lemma 8.9. In particular, this puts in a column strictly left of in the 1 pre-alignment of . In the 1 alignment of , remains in a column strictly left of since .
We must determine the positions of the remaining in the alignment of (no longer assuming since as defined above may not exist). Let be minimal such that either does not exist, or is in a column strictly right of . Note that since any with is -paired with some with by choice of . This also means each with is in a column weakly right of .
Suppose for some , and is in a column strictly left of . If , further assume shares a column with . We claim exists and shares a column with . If so that does not share a column with any cell in row , this fact is necessitated by Proposition 8.6 and our remark that is in a column weakly right of .
When we have and sharing a column. The former cannot be -paired without violating Lemma 3.6, so we must have by choice of . Since , Lemma 4.8 implies shares a column with another cell. This cell can only be in row 2, and therefore corresponds to , again by Lemma 3.6.
Therefore, there is some such that (perhaps vacuously)
-
(a)
for all ,
-
(b)
and share a column for all , and
-
(c)
if exists then .
Additionally, if we know .
Recall that each with is weakly right of the column containing , and therefore by Lemma 8.9. We can now say that in the pre-alignment of , the entries lie in consecutive columns. If actually exists, then lies in the rightmost occupied column . If does not exist, then lies in the rightmost occupied column. In either case, the entries will remain in consecutive column in the alignment of . Moreover, the entries will be among the columns containing .
To complete the proof, it remains to show that occupy columns in the alignment. This relies, mainly, on showing that for each . This is all vacuous when so assume hence .
Assume to the contrary that for some . Lemma 8.4 asserts that is in row 1, and in row 2 of . In fact, must all reside in row 1 of , and in row 2 since for each . There must then be some in row 1 of such that shares a column with . If we have some , then since , the (3+1)-free condition gives . By Lemma 8.4, we then have in a row above , which is to say row 1. This contradicts the choice of such that is not -paired.
Now and we have seen lies in column of the alignment of . We also saw that column is either empty or contains . Property (4) of weak alignments therefore requires to be in column . If and lies in column , then by Property (4) again we must have in column , as is not smaller than in column .
To summarize, the entries lie in columns of the alignment of , while lie in a subset of those same columns. Since each with lies in a column strictly left of in the alignment, is the rightmost entry in row of the alignment of that does not share a column with an entry in row . ∎
Proposition 8.11.
Let be a two-row -tableau and let . Let be minimal such that . Then .
Proof.
Let and be the entries of rows and in respectively. Let be maximal such that the cell corresponding to in is not -paired. Let be the induced subgraph of on the vertices in and . By Lemma 8.10 and Proposition 5.9, we obtain from by taking the vertices in the connected component of containing , and swapping them between rows and . We must show the same description holds for .
Say . Notice that and agree in all columns strictly left of , as the diagram fillings are defined column by column from left to right, and and coincide in those columns.
Next we consider how column differs in and . We claim . This is clear if column of the alignment of contains a single entry. Otherwise, column of both diagram fillings will be defined according to the same rule (1), (2), or (3) in the definition. We see that is the topmost cell in column of if and only if is the topmost cell in column of . So if column is defined by rule (3) we indeed get .
If , then for any , is the lowest cell in column weakly above row in if and only if is the lowest cell in column weakly above row in . Similarly, if there is distinct from , then it is the lowest cell in column weakly above row in if and only if this is also true in . Therefore if column is defined according to rules (1) or (2), we will again get that .
If instead , then also as is not -paired. In this case we must have by choice of because cannot be -paired without violating Lemma 3.6. It would also violate Lemma 3.6 to have a cell in row 3 or greater of column in , so we are back in the case where column of the diagram fillings contains only the entry .
Let be minimal such that either does not exist, or lies in a column strictly right of in the 1 alignment of . Suppose for some and all we have
-
(a)
and , and
-
(b)
if then and .
We will show that if exists with , and then the same hypotheses apply for , and otherwise that column is identical in and .
First assume and . The latter assumption with Proposition 8.6 implies either or . In either case, we have cells in rows and of the same column, so the cell in row cannot be -paired without violating Lemma 3.6. This means by choice of .
If we are in the case then hence . Since , cannot be the only cell in its column using Lemma 4.8. A cell in row 3 or greater of column would again contradict Lemma 3.6 together with and . Therefore we have anyway. It must be the case that .
Now must bijectively assign and to the cells and . We have , and . For to have increasing rows as per Proposition 8.6, the only choice is and . Then (a) and (b) hold true for as claimed.
Assume does not exist or is not in column . Equivalently, . We will show and coincide in column . If exists then by choice of the cells of are -paired with a subset of the cells of . In particular, would have to also exist and lies in a column weakly right of , hence strictly right of column . Therefore, we can see that . If then we have seen and . Using Lemma 3.6, there can be no cell in column of in row 3 or greater. Thus column of is vacant, and the two diagram fillings trivially agree in this column.
Suppose instead . Any is the lowest cell in its column weakly above the row of in if and only if it is the lowest cell in its column weakly above the row of in . Similarly if there is distinct from then is the lowest cell in its column weakly above in if and only if this is also the case in . It follows that and will be defined the same way in column .
Finally, assume , but . We will once again show the two diagram fillings agree in column . If the column contains only one cell then this is immediate so we will assume it contains two. We have several cases.
-
•
Case: and
Any is the lowest cell in its column weakly above the row of in if and only if it is the lowest cell in its column weakly above the row of in . If there is distinct from then is similarly the lowest cell in its column below row in if and only if the same is true in . Column will therefore be defined identically in and . -
•
Case: and
If column is defined in and by rule (3) we are done, so assume not.We must have less than the entry corresponding to in , hence every entry in column . If is the topmost cell in its column, then the conditions for defining column of or according to rule (1) are not satisfied. If is the lowest cell in its column, then the conditions for defining column of or according to rule (2) are not satisfied. Thus, there must be distinct from , and column of both diagram fillings is determined by mapping the unique entry in column of the 1 alignment of to the lowest cell in column weakly above row .
-
•
Case:
We have seen that we must have , and we know . Using Lemma 3.6, the two cells in column of can only be and . Thus . We know so the -free condition implies . Thus, every entry in column of the 1 alignment of is greater than every entry in column . Then column of and are defined according to rule (3).
Now we fix to be maximal such that for all hypotheses (a) and (b) hold. We have summarily shown that is obtained from by putting in row and putting in row . Together, these entries form a union of connected components of , since is, in fact, a -array.
To finish, we must show that is actually a single connected component of , i.e. the connected component containing . Assume hence , else this is trivial. For every we have above in the same column and below in the same column. Then we must have by Lemma 8.4. We also know for each , and it now suffices to show . If we had for , this would contradict that as just shown.
Then assume . If is the only entry in its column of the 1 alignment of , then it is in row 1 of and in row 2. This is impossible by property (3) of weak alignments. Then there must be some with and . Because and cannot share a row in , and do share a row. Thus but this contradicts Lemma 8.4. We conclude is a connected component of and we are done. ∎
Theorem 8.12.
The map
given by is a bijection, and . Additionally, is a connected subset of for each two-row -tableau .
Proof.
We have that is onto by definition of , and it is also immediate that whenever .
Let be a two-row -tableau and . If then we may take to be minimal such that and we get that by Proposition 8.11. Repeated application shows that some sequence of raising operations applied to gives us , by Lemma 8.7, with the corresponding sequence of -arrays being contained in . Therefore is a connected subsets of the -array crystal.
Moreover, we claim that as chosen is minimal such that . To see this, let . Let and be the entries in rows and of respectively. By choice of , the cell of each in is -paired. In particular, exists and must lie in a column weakly left of . By Lemma 8.9, which confirms that .
Therefore, the sequence of raising operations applied to to obtain depends only on , not or per se. This is to say that if we have for some two-row -tableau and diagram then the same sequence of raising operations applied to yields , which thus coincides with .
Finally, we must show that when and are distinct diagrams in then . We may take some and we get that row of contains an entry from column of the 1 alignment of , while row of contains no such entry. Therefore is a bijection. ∎
Corollary 8.13.
For a two-row -tableau we have
Recall from Remark 3.8 that is in explicit weight preserving bijection with semi-standard Young tableau. Thus, Theorem 8.12 can be thought of as a partial Robinson-Schensted correspondence for -arrays. It would be nice to extend the result to a full bijection, though such an extension is unlikely to be straightforward. For one thing, our partial bijection has the notable property that its image for a fixed -tableau is a connected subset of , but after removing this subset for the two-row -tableau in Fig. 8 the remaining maximal connected subsets are not individually -positive.
References
- [Ass22] Sami Assaf, Demazure crystals for Kohnert polynomials, Transactions of the AMS 375 (2022), 2147–2186.
- [BB03] Barry Balof and Kenneth Bogart, Simple inductive proofs of the fishburn and mirkin theorem and the scott-suppes theorem, Order 20 (2003), no. 1, 49–51.
- [BS17] Daniel Bump and Anne Schilling, Crystal bases: Representations and combinatorics, World Scientific Publishing Company, New Jersey, 2017.
- [Cho99] Timothy Y. Chow, Descents, quasi-symmetric functions, robinson-schensted for posets, and the chromatic symmetric function, Journal of Algebraic Combinatorics 10 (1999), 227–240.
- [Gas96] Vesselin Gasharov, Incomparability graphs of (3 + 1)-free posets are s-positive, Discrete Mathematics 157 (1996), no. 1, 193–197.
- [GP13] Mathieu Guay-Paquet, A modular relation for the chromatic symmetric functions of (3+1)-free posets, 2013.
- [Kas90] Masaki Kashiwara, Crystalizing the -analogue of universal enveloping algebras, Comm. Math. Phys. 133 (1990), no. 2, 249–260.
- [KP21] Dongkwan Kim and Pavlo Pylyavskyy, Robinson–schensted correspondence for unit interval orders, Sel. Math. New Ser. 27 (2021).
- [Mag92] Alexander Magid, Enumeration of convex polyominoes: A generalization of the robinson-schensted correspondence and the dimer problem, Ph.D. thesis, Brandeis University, 1992.
- [SS58] Dana Scott and Patrick Suppes, Foundational aspects of theories of measurement, The Journal of Symbolic Logic 23 (1958), no. 2, 113–128.
- [SS93] Richard P. Stanley and John R. Stembridge, On immanants of jacobi-trudi matrices and permutations with restricted position, Journal of Combinatorial Theory, Series A 62 (1993), no. 2, 261–279.
- [Sta95] Richard P. Stanley, A symmetric function generalization of the chromatic polynomial of a graph, Advances in Mathematics 111 (1995), no. 1, 166–194.
- [Sta98] by same author, Graph colorings and related symmetric functions: ideas and applications a description of results, interesting applications, & notable open problems, Discrete Mathematics 193 (1998), no. 1, 267–286.
- [SW16] John Shareshian and Michelle L. Wachs, Chromatic quasisymmetric functions, Advances in Mathematics 295 (2016), 497–551.
- [SWW97] Thomas S. Sundquist, David G. Wagner, and Julian West, A robinson–schensted algorithm for a class of partial orders, Journal of Combinatorial Theory, Series A 79 (1997), no. 1, 36–52.