Abstract.
Let be an algebraic variety, and let be a discrete subgroup whose real and complex spans agree. We describe the topological closure of the image of in , thereby extending a result of Peterzil-Starchenko in the case when is cocompact.
We also obtain a similar extension when is definable in an o-minimal structure with no restrictions on , and as an application prove the following conjecture of Gallinaro: for a closed semi-algebraic (such as a complex algebraic variety) and the coordinate-wise exponential map, we have where are positive-dimensional compact real tori and are semi-algebraic.
1. Introduction
Let be a vector space over or , a discrete subgroup, and a closed subset. Let denote the projection map. Ullmo-Yafaev [5] observed that as , the closures
|
|
|
form what we may call a “flow” of sets, which
converge to a closed limiting set exactly containing those cosets which an unbounded sequence of points can approach in Euclidean distance. Evidently we have
|
|
|
In the case where is a complex curve and is cocompact, [5, Theorem 2.4] shows consists of finitely many translates of real subtori . This was later extended to arbitrary discrete subgroups by Dinh-Vu [2].
When is a higher-dimensional variety, an example of Peterzil-Starchenko [4, Section 8] shows this description of doesn’t hold, even if is cocompact. However, they show that in this cocompact case, replacing translated subtori by algebraic families of translated subtori is enough [4, Theorem 1.1].
Our main result shows the cocompactness restriction can be removed when the real and complex spans of agree. For or and a subset of an -vector space , let denote its -linear span.
Theorem 1.1.
Let be an algebraic variety, a -subspace, a discrete subgroup with , and the quotient map. Then there are algebraic varieties with and positive-dimensional compact real tori such that
|
|
|
In particular, .
Remark 1.2.
As in [4], we will be able to take to only depend on and , and take positive-dimensional -subspaces only depending on and such that .
When is cocompact, [4] also shows that we may assume is a finite collection of points if is inclusion-maximal among , but this is false in this more general setting even for and .
The condition that the -span and -span of are equal is essential, even without the dimension conditions, as the following example of [2] shows.
Example 1.3 ([2, Example in Section 4]).
Let be the hypersurface in , and let . Letting be the projection and defining
|
|
|
we have
|
|
|
But one can show that any translate of a proper subset with an algebraic variety and a real vector subspace cannot intersect
in a full-dimensional set. So if , we obtain a contradiction by applying the Baire category theorem to the countable union of translates for of proper subsets of of the form , where is the connected component of at , obtains a contradiction.
Gallinaro [3, Question 6.3.2], in work on Zilber’s exponential-algebraic closedness conjecture (an equivalent formulation of Zilber’s quasi-minimality conjecture [6] as established by Bays-Kirby [1, Theorem 1.5]), has conjectured that such a decomposition should be possible if the are taken semi-algebraic. Our second main result, an o-minimal version of 1.1 with no restrictions on generalizing [4, Theorem 1.2], confirms this conjecture.
Theorem 1.4.
Fix an o-minimal structure extending the field . Let be a definable closed set, an -subspace, and a discrete subgroup with . Then for the quotient map, the following is true. There are definable closed sets with and compact positive-dimensional real tori such that
|
|
|
In particular, .
Remark 1.5.
As in [4], we will be able to take to only depend on and , and take positive-dimensional -subspaces only depending on and such that .
In the cocompact case [4] also shows that we may take to be compact if is inclusion-maximal amongst , but this is false in this more general setting even for and .
Corollary 1.6 ([3, Question 6.3.2]).
Let be a closed semi-algebraic set (such as a complex algebraic variety), and the map . Then there are semi-algebraic subsets with and compact positive-dimensional real tori such that
|
|
|
Proof.
We apply the theorem with in the semi-algebraic o-minimal structure , since is surjective with kernel , so is identified with the quotient map .
∎
To prove the cocompact case, the main technical tool introduced in [4] is a definable collection of “asymptotic flats” (or ) associated to which encode the linear behaviour of sequences of points of . Roughly speaking, limiting sequences of points are encoded by realizations of in a saturated extension of (or in ), and we associate to such a point the smallest flat defined over (or ) which is infinitesimally close to this realization.
The key idea in our proof is that if we decompose our ambient vector space as , then a sequence of points limiting to a coset of has convergent -component, and the corresponding asymptotic flat would then have linear part contained in . This motivates us to consider just the sub-family of flats of with no linear part in the direction, and by doing so we can carry out a very similar argument in both the complex algebraic and o-minimal settings.
Acknowledgements. We thank Y. Peterzil, S. Starchenko, and F. Gallinaro for helpful answers to questions.
2. Model theory setup
We closely follow the setup of [4], which we recall briefly. Fix a cardinal . will be considered as an ordered field over the language . Let be the expansion of the field by all subsets of for all , the corresponding language, and a -saturated extension. Denote by the underlying field. Fix an o-minimal expansion of with corresponding language , and let be the corresponding reduct of , which is also -saturated.
We denote for the set of infinitesimal elements and the set of bounded elements (neither of which are definable in ). We denote the standard part map, and for a subset we denote
|
|
|
The complex numbers will be considered as a structure with signature . We denote by , the set of infinitesimals , and the set of bounded elements . With these identifications, we may similarly define and for a subset . Through the identification , we may consider the expansion of by all subsets of for all .
Denote the language of a valued field, with a unary predicate for the valuation ring, and the -structure of the valued field augmented with the set of bounded elements. Note also that is definable in by the formula . Note that is not a reduct of and in particular not -saturated, since for example the finitely-satisfiable collection of formulas is not satisfiable.
We will denote to be either or .
If is one of the languages when working in the real setting or when working in the complex setting, then an -definable partial type is a finitely satisfiable collection of formulas over the language with free variables and constants in . We denote by the set of realizations of over .
Suppose we are in one of the -saturated structures , or , and consider types defined over a set of constants with . Two such types are considered equivalent if for every finite there exists a finite such that and vice versa. By -saturation, two such types are equivalent if and only if . If are any two types, then the sum is defined by
|
|
|
By -saturation, for two such types we have , and consequently for three such types , the types and are equivalent.
For , we can consider as an -definable subset of . By abuse of notation we also use to denote the partial type of all -formulas with constants in satisfied by , and we write for the set of realizations of over . Also by abuse of notation, we identify with the partial type in or and with the partial type in , so that and . These abuses of notation are consistent with the sum notation for types, as by -saturatedness for we have
|
|
|
Finally, by -saturatedness, for any we have
|
|
|
where is the topological closure.
4. Asymptotic flats
Let
be the Grassmannian of affine -dimensional flats of , and let
|
|
|
Note that
and .
For , we denote by the minimal -flat under inclusion such that (that this exists is [4, Proposition 4.2] when and as noted in [4, Section 7.1], the proof also works for ).
For define
and
|
|
|
By [4, Theorems 4.5 and 7.1] this is a definable subset of , and by definition if and only if , in which case (see [4, Lemma 4.8]). In particular . Write .
A slight refinement of the arguments in [4] shows that if is cocompact in , then
|
|
|
We will adapt this now to lattices with an -linear subspace of .
Let be the subset of affine -dimensional flats of such that the linear part of is contained in , and
|
|
|
For , we define
and
|
|
|
Clearly this is a definable subset, and . Write .
Theorem 4.1.
If is a discrete subgroup and is an -linear subspace such that , then
|
|
|
Before proving the theorem, we start by proving some lemmas.
Lemma 4.2.
Suppose that . Then for , we have if and only if , in which case . In particular,
|
|
|
Proof.
If , then for some , so
|
|
|
Conversely, if , then
|
|
|
so and this shows .
∎
Definition 4.3.
For , we define to be the complete -type of with -constants if and to be the complete -type of with -constants if .
Lemma 4.4.
For and , then . Also, if then , so in particular
|
|
|
Proof.
corresponds to a partial type that satisfies by construction. Similarly for (noting that this partial type is definable over with -coefficients when and over with -coefficients when ).
∎
Lemma 4.5.
For we have .
Proof.
After a linear change of coordinates, we may assume that . Then by 4.2 we have , and writing we have , so the left hand side is contained in . Additionally, and by 4.4 we also have , so the right hand side is also contained in .
Let be a discrete subgroup with . Then so by [4, Proposition 5.1] in the complex case and [4, Proposition 7.3] in the real case, we have
|
|
|
Because , for the last coordinates of the sum to be bounded we need the element from to lie in , which in particular means it is infinitesimally close to an element of . Therefore,
|
|
|
Intersecting both sides of the equality with , we obtain the desired equality.
∎
Proof of 4.1.
We may suppose that . Then since , if a sum for some then we must have . Therefore,
|
|
|
|
|
|
where the third equality is by 4.4.
∎
Remark 4.6.
In the cocompact case, every positive-dimensional algebraic set has a nontrivial asymptotic flat by [4, Lemma 4.8]. In contrast, may be empty. For example, the parabola in has no nontrivial asymptotic flats relative to the lattice , because any unbounded solution is unbounded in both coordinates.
5. Neat families
In this section we take “definable” to mean defianble either over in the language of ordered fields, or over in the language of fields, according to whether the setting is real or complex. By Chevalley’s theorem, in the latter case the definable sets are exactly constructible sets, i.e., Boolean combinations of algebraic sets.
For a flat , we write for the linear part of (the -subspace such that we can write for some ), and for a subset , we define to be the smallest -linear space containing for all .
Definition 5.1.
A “neat” family of flats is a definable family such that
-
(1)
is a connected -submanifold.
-
(2)
For any nonempty open subset we have .
Theorem 5.2 ([4, Theorem 7.7 and Section 6.1]).
Every definable family can be written as a finite union of neat definable families.
Proof.
In the real setting, this is exactly what is proved in [4, Theorem 7.7]. In the complex setting, we may decompose into finitely many smooth pieces, and then further decompose each of those pieces into its finitely many irreducible components, so it suffices to show that if is smooth and irreducible then it is neat. A smooth irreducible set is a connected -submanifold, so it suffices to show that for any nonempty open subset that . Any nonempty open subset is Zariski dense in by irreducibility of , so because the Zariski-closed set of those such that contains , it must therefore be all of . Hence for all , so , and .
∎
By this theorem, we may break up the definable family of flats as where each is a neat family in with . We need the following proposition, the analogue of [4, Proposition 6.2 and Proposition 7.6] for .
Proposition 5.3.
If is a neat family of -dimensional flats of in , then is topologically dense in .
Proof.
The proof of [4, Proposition 7.6] carries over with essentially no modifications.
First we show the analogue of [4, Proposition 7.6(1)], that the set is topologically dense in . Indeed, there are only countably many closed real Lie subgroups of , so by the Baire Category theorem it suffices to show for any proper real Lie subgroup that the set is nowhere dense in . This set is equal to , where is the maximal -linear subspace contained in (either the connected component of in the real setting or in the complex setting). Since this is definable, it suffices to show that it does not contain an open subset of . But since is neat, , so not every for can be contained in since is a proper subspace of .
Now we show is topologically dense in , the analogue of [4, Proposition 7.6(2)]. Indeed, by what we have just shown, there is a sequence such that , or equivalently . Hence contains in its closure, and therefore contains in its closure.
∎
Now the proofs of 1.1 and 1.4 proceed identical to [4, Theorem 7.8]. We sketch how this works. For each , let be a complementary -subspace to . For the intersection is a single point , and we let be the closure of the definable set of such points as we range over . Letting , we have , and [4, Section 6.2 and 7.3.1, Proofs of Clause (i)] applied to shows that with this construction, . Let and . Then we have (by 4.1 for the first equality, by 5.3 and the fact that is closed for the second equality, that for the third equality, and that is closed for the fourth equality) that
|
|
|