This paper was converted on www.awesomepapers.org from LaTeX by an anonymous user.
Want to know more? Visit the Converter page.

Natural dualities for varieties generated by finite positive MV-chains

Wolfgang Poiger University of Luxembourg
6 Avenue de la Fonte
L-4364 Esch-sur-Alzette
Luxembourg
wolfgang.poiger@uni.lu
Abstract.

We provide a simple natural duality for the varieties generated by the negation- and implication- free reduct of a finite MV-chain. We study these varieties through the dual equivalence thus obtained. For example, we fully characterize their algebraically closed, existentially closed and injective members. We also explore the relationship between this natural duality and Priestley duality in terms of distributive skeletons and Priestley powers.

Key words and phrases:
Positive MV-algebras, Natural dualities, Finite-valued Łukasiewicz logics, Priestley duality, Boolean power
1991 Mathematics Subject Classification:
08C20, 06D35, 06D50

1. Introduction

Just like distributive lattices are the negation-free subreducts of Boolean algebras, positive 𝖬𝖵\mathsf{MV}-algebras (recently introduced in [1]), are the negation-free subreducts of 𝖬𝖵\mathsf{MV}-algebras. While the variety 𝖬𝖵\mathsf{MV} of 𝖬𝖵\mathsf{MV}-algebras provides algebraic semantics for Łukasiewicz infinite-valued logic (see, e.g., [7, Chapter 4]), its subvarieties 𝖬𝖵n=𝕊(Łn)\mathsf{MV}_{n}=\mathbb{H}\mathbb{S}\mathbb{P}(\text{\bf\L}_{n}), generated by finite 𝖬𝖵\mathsf{MV}-chains Łn\text{\bf\L}_{n}, provide algebraic semantics for Łukasiewicz finitely-valued logics (the subvarieties 𝖬𝖵n\mathsf{MV}_{n} were first studied in [12]). In this paper, we study the varieties 𝖯𝖬𝖵n=𝕊(𝐏Łn)\mathsf{PMV}_{n}=\mathbb{H}\mathbb{S}\mathbb{P}(\mathbf{P\text{\bf\L}}_{n}) generated by finite positive 𝖬𝖵\mathsf{MV}-chains 𝐏Łn\mathbf{P\text{\bf\L}}_{n} (that is, negation-free reducts of Łn\text{\bf\L}_{n}). Our main tool for this study is the theory of natural dualities.

In its simplest form, natural duality theory [8] provides a general framework to obtain a dual equivalence between a quasi-variety 𝒜=𝕀𝕊(𝐌)\mathcal{A}=\mathbb{I}\mathbb{S}\mathbb{P}(\mathbf{M}) generated by a finite algebra 𝐌\mathbf{M} and a category of structured Stone spaces 𝒳=𝕀𝕊c+(𝐌~)\mathcal{X}=\mathbb{I}\mathbb{S}_{c}\mathbb{P}^{+}(\utilde{\mathbf{M}}) generated by a discrete structure 𝐌~\utilde{\mathbf{M}} based on the same set as 𝐌\mathbf{M} (and therefore called an alter ego of 𝐌\mathbf{M}). Examples of natural dualities are Stone duality, which arises if 𝐌\mathbf{M} is the two-element Boolean algebra and its alter ego 𝐌~\utilde{\mathbf{M}} is the two-element discrete space, and Priestley duality, which arises if 𝐌\mathbf{M} is the two-element distributive lattice and its alter-ego 𝐌~\utilde{\mathbf{M}} is the two-element discrete space with order 010\leq 1. The great utility of these dualities may be seen as a consequence of the fact that the alter-egos described above are very simple structures. A general theme of natural duality theory may be phrased as simple structures yield useful dualities.

For the varieties 𝖬𝖵n\mathsf{MV}_{n}, natural dualities were developed and studied in [20]. Since finite 𝖬𝖵\mathsf{MV}-chains are semi-primal, it is easy to come up with simple alter-egos Ł~n\utilde{\text{\bf\L}}_{n}. Indeed, by [8, Theorem 3.3.14] the only structure relevant for this duality is given by the collection of subalgebras 𝕊(Łn)\mathbb{S}(\text{\bf\L}_{n}). One reason why this is sufficient is that every subalgebra of Łnףn\text{\bf\L}_{n}\times\text{\bf\L}_{n} is a direct product of subalgebras. This is not true anymore in the case of 𝐏Łn\mathbf{P\text{\bf\L}}_{n} (for example, the order relation \leq itself is a subalgebra of 𝐏Łn×𝐏Łn\mathbf{P\text{\bf\L}}_{n}\times\mathbf{P\text{\bf\L}}_{n}). We show that, instead, a simple alter-ego of 𝐏Łn\mathbf{P\text{\bf\L}}_{n} can be obtained from a certain collection of subalgebras of the order \leq which can be easily computed algorithmically.

To make the case for the utility of these alter-egos, we investigate the dualities they yield to derive various results about the varieties 𝖯𝖬𝖵n\mathsf{PMV}_{n}. For example, we completely characterize the injective, algebraically closed and existentially closed members of 𝖯𝖬𝖵n\mathsf{PMV}_{n}. We also explore the relationship to Priestley duality, which can be expressed in terms of distributive skeletons and Priestley powers. We show that these constructions give rise to an adjunction between 𝖣𝖫\mathsf{DL} (the variety of distributive lattices) and 𝖯𝖬𝖵n\mathsf{PMV}_{n}, similar to the adjunction [17, Section 4] between 𝖡𝖠\mathsf{BA} (the variety of Boolean algebras) and 𝖬𝖵n\mathsf{MV}_{n} obtained from functors taking the Boolean skeleton and the Boolean power, respectively. We expect this to prove useful in future applications, exploring modal logic over 𝖯𝖬𝖵n\mathsf{PMV}_{n} as an analogue of Dunn’s positive modal logic [10] in the setting of modal finitely-valued Łukasiewicz logic [13].

The paper is structured as follows. In Section 2, we recall the most important background information on 𝖬𝖵\mathsf{MV}- and 𝖬𝖵n\mathsf{MV}_{n}-algebras (Subsection 2.1) and on natural dualities (Subsection 2.2). In Section 3, we begin our study of finite positive 𝖬𝖵\mathsf{MV}-chains 𝐏Łn\mathbf{P\text{\bf\L}}_{n} and the varieties 𝖯𝖬𝖵n\mathsf{PMV}_{n} they generate (Subsection 3.1). We proceed to develop the natural dualities for these varieties (Subsection 3.2). In Section 4, we explore some ramifications of this duality. More specifically, we give an explicit axiomatization of the category dual to 𝖯𝖬𝖵2\mathsf{PMV}_{2} generated by the three-element chain (Subsection 4.1), we explore the relationship between 𝖯𝖬𝖵n\mathsf{PMV}_{n} and 𝖣𝖫\mathsf{DL} as described above (Subsection 4.2) and we characterize the algebraically and existentially closed algebras in 𝖯𝖬𝖵n\mathsf{PMV}_{n} via this relationship (Subsection 4.3). In the concluding Section 5, we collect some open questions and ideas for further research.

2. Preliminaries

In this section, we give short overviews of the two most important topics related to this paper. In Subsection 2.1, we recall the basics of 𝖬𝖵\mathsf{MV}-algebras, with a focus on finite 𝖬𝖵\mathsf{MV}-chains and the varieties 𝖬𝖵n\mathsf{MV}_{n} they generate. In Subsection 2.2, we recall important prerequisites from the theory of natural dualities. For further information on these topics, the reader may consult the textbooks [7] about 𝖬𝖵\mathsf{MV}-algebras and [8] about natural dualities (in particular, we will often refer to the latter throughout this entire paper).

2.1. MV-algebras

It is well-known that Boolean algebras provide an appropriate algebraic counterpart to classical propositional logic. Similarly, to Łukasiewicz infinitely-valued logic, an appropriate algebraic counterpart is provided by 𝖬𝖵\mathsf{MV}-algebras, introduced by Chang [6] in 1958. The variety 𝖬𝖵\mathsf{MV} of 𝖬𝖵\mathsf{MV}-algebras is generated by the standard 𝖬𝖵\mathsf{MV}-algebra

[0,1],,,,,¬,0,1\langle[0,1],\odot,\oplus,\wedge,\vee,\neg,0,1\rangle

based on the real unit interval with its usual bounded lattice structure and additional operations

xy=𝗆𝖺𝗑{0,x+y1}, xy=𝗆𝗂𝗇{1,x+y}, ¬x=1x.x\odot y=\mathsf{max}\{0,x+y-1\},\text{ }x\oplus y=\mathsf{min}\{1,x+y\},\text{ }\neg x=1-x.

For a detailed overview of 𝖬𝖵\mathsf{MV}-algebras and their relationship to many-valued logic, we refer the reader to [7] (and [19] for more advanced topics). In this paper, we focus on the finite subalgebras of the standard 𝖬𝖵\mathsf{MV}-algebra, which are all of the following form.

Definition 2.1.

Let n1n\geq 1 be a natural number. The (n+1)(n+1)-element 𝖬𝖵\mathsf{MV}-chain is given by

Łn={0,1n,n1n,1},,,,,¬,0,1,\text{\bf\L}_{n}=\langle\{0,\tfrac{1}{n},\dots\tfrac{n-1}{n},1\},\wedge,\vee,\odot,\oplus,\neg,0,1\rangle,

considered as a subalgebra of the standard 𝖬𝖵\mathsf{MV}-algebra. We use 𝖬𝖵n\mathsf{MV}_{n} to denote the variety 𝕊(Łn)\mathbb{H}\mathbb{S}\mathbb{P}(\text{\bf\L}_{n}) generated by Łn\text{\bf\L}_{n} (these varieties were first axiomatized by Grigolia in [12]).

Note that Ł1\text{\bf\L}_{1} is simply the two-element Boolean algebra and, therefore, 𝖬𝖵1\mathsf{MV}_{1} is the variety of Boolean algebras, the algebraic counterpart to classical propositional logic. The varieties 𝖬𝖵n\mathsf{MV}_{n} with n2n\geq 2 provide appropriate algebraic counterparts to Łukasiewicz finitely-valued logics. In particular, Łukasiewicz three-valued logic with Ł2\text{\bf\L}_{2} as algebra of truth-degrees is a popular research topic in non-classical logic.

It was shown in [20, Proposition 2.1] that every finite 𝖬𝖵\mathsf{MV}-chain Łn\text{\bf\L}_{n} is semi-primal [11], meaning that every operation f:{0,1n,,n1n,1}k{0,1n,,n1n,1}f\colon\{0,\frac{1}{n},\dots,\frac{n-1}{n},1\}^{k}\to\{0,\frac{1}{n},\dots,\frac{n-1}{n},1\} (k1k\geq 1) which preserves subalgebras of Łn\text{\bf\L}_{n} (that is, f(𝐒k)𝐒f(\mathbf{S}^{k})\subseteq\mathbf{S} for all subalgebras 𝐒Łn\mathbf{S}\subseteq\text{\bf\L}_{n}) is term-definable in Łn\text{\bf\L}_{n} (note that this is a straightforward generalization of the two-element Boolean algebra Ł1\text{\bf\L}_{1} being primal, meaning that every operation f:{0,1}k{0,1}f\colon\{0,1\}^{k}\to\{0,1\} can be expressed by a Boolean term). Some important consequences of this are that the variety 𝖬𝖵n\mathsf{MV}_{n} coincides with the quasi-variety 𝕀𝕊(Łn)\mathbb{I}\mathbb{S}\mathbb{P}(\text{\bf\L}_{n}) generated by Łn\text{\bf\L}_{n}, and that every 𝖬𝖵n\mathsf{MV}_{n}-algebra is a Boolean product (see, e.g., [5, Chapter IV]) of subalgebras of Łn\text{\bf\L}_{n}.

It is well-known that the subalgebras of Łn\text{\bf\L}_{n} are exactly given by

Łk{0,n,,(k1)n,1},,,,,¬,0,1,\text{\bf\L}_{k}\cong\langle\{0,\tfrac{\ell}{n},\dots,\tfrac{(k-1)\ell}{n},1\},\wedge,\vee,\odot,\oplus,\neg,0,1\rangle,

where n=kn=k\cdot\ell. Therefore, the lattice 𝕊(Łn)\mathbb{S}(\text{\bf\L}_{n}) of subalgebras of Łn\text{\bf\L}_{n} is isomorphic to the bounded lattice of divisors of nn.

It is also well-known (and another immediate consequence of Łn\text{\bf\L}_{n} being semi-primal) that, for every dŁnd\in\text{\bf\L}_{n}, the unary operation

τd(x)={1 if dx,0 otherwise \tau_{d}(x)=\begin{cases}1&\text{ if }d\leq x,\\ 0&\text{ otherwise }\end{cases}

is term-definable in Łn\text{\bf\L}_{n}. This means that, as shown in [14], 𝖬𝖵n\mathsf{MV}_{n} can be identified with a (proper, for n5n\geq 5) subvariety of the variety 𝖫𝖬n\mathsf{LM}_{n} of nn-valued Łukasiewicz-Moisil algebras, generated by the nn-element chain with ¬\neg defined as for Łn\text{\bf\L}_{n} and all τd\tau_{d} as fundamental operations (see [2] for an overview of Łukasiewicz-Moisil algebras).

The unary terms τd\tau_{d} can be very useful, for example, they are important in the algebraic study of modal extensions of Łukasiewicz finitely-valued logic [3, 13]. Notably, as shown in [21, pp. 344–345], only the operations \odot and \oplus are required to define these unary terms in Łn\text{\bf\L}_{n}. Thus, they will still be available in our study of finite positive 𝖬𝖵\mathsf{MV}-chains (also see Lemma 3.3).

2.2. Natural dualities

The theory of natural dualities provides a common framework to develop dual equivalences between quasi-varieties of algebras and structured Stone spaces. In particular, the theory encompasses and generalizes Stone duality for Boolean algebras and Priestley duality for distributive lattices. In this subsection, we give a selective overview of this theory. For more information, we refer the reader to the book [8], which we often cite throughout this paper.

Let 𝐌\mathbf{M} be a finite algebra (with underlying set MM) and let 𝒜=𝕀𝕊(𝐌)\mathcal{A}=\mathbb{I}\mathbb{S}\mathbb{P}(\mathbf{M}) be the quasi-variety it generates. An alter ego of 𝐌\mathbf{M} is a discrete topological structure (also with underlying set MM) of the form

𝐌~=M,𝒢,,,𝒯dis,\utilde{\mathbf{M}}=\langle M,\mathcal{G},\mathcal{H},\mathcal{R},\mathcal{T}_{\mathrm{dis}}\rangle,

where 𝒢\mathcal{G} is a collection of (total) homomorphisms 𝐌n𝐌\mathbf{M}^{n}\to\mathbf{M} (possibly nullary, which corresponds to constants), \mathcal{H} is a collection of partial homomorphisms, that is, homomorphisms from a subalgebra of 𝐌n\mathbf{M}^{n} to 𝐌\mathbf{M} and \mathcal{R} is a collection of algebraic relations, that is, subalgebras 𝐑𝐌n\mathbf{R}\subseteq\mathbf{M}^{n}. Lastly, 𝒯dis\mathcal{T}_{\mathrm{dis}} is the discrete topology on MM.

The topological quasi-variety 𝒳=𝕀𝕊c+(𝐌~)\mathcal{X}=\mathbb{I}\mathbb{S}_{c}\mathbb{P}^{+}(\utilde{\mathbf{M}}) generated by 𝐌~\utilde{\mathbf{M}} consists of structured Stone spaces (recall that a Stone space is a topological space (X,𝒯)(X,\mathcal{T}) which is compact, Hausdorff and totally disconnected)

𝐗=X,𝒢𝐗,𝐗,𝐗,𝒯,\mathbf{X}=\langle X,\mathcal{G}^{\mathbf{X}},\mathcal{H}^{\mathbf{X}},\mathcal{R}^{\mathbf{X}},\mathcal{T}\rangle,

of the same type as 𝐌~\utilde{\mathbf{M}} which are isomorphic to a closed substructure of a non-empty product of 𝐌~\utilde{\mathbf{M}}. The category 𝒳\mathcal{X} with structure-preserving continuous maps as morphisms is often described using the Preservation Theorem [8, Theorem 1.4.3] and the Separation Theorem [8, Theorem 1.4.3].

By the Preduality Theorem [8, Theorem 1.5.2], there exists a dual adjunction between 𝒜\mathcal{A} and 𝒳\mathcal{X} given by the contravariant hom-functors 𝖣:𝒜𝒳\mathsf{D}\colon\mathcal{A}\to\mathcal{X} and 𝖤:𝒳𝒜\mathsf{E}\colon\mathcal{X}\to\mathcal{A} defined by

𝖣(𝐀)=𝒜(𝐀,𝐌) and 𝖤(𝐗)=𝒳(𝐗,𝐌~)\mathsf{D}(\mathbf{A})=\mathcal{A}(\mathbf{A},\mathbf{M})\text{ and }\mathsf{E}(\mathbf{X})=\mathcal{X}(\mathbf{X},\utilde{\mathbf{M}})

for all 𝐀𝒜\mathbf{A}\in\mathcal{A} and 𝐗𝒳\mathbf{X}\in\mathcal{X}. The natural transformations e:1𝒜𝖤𝖣e\colon 1_{\mathcal{A}}\to\mathsf{ED} and ε:1𝒳𝖣𝖤\varepsilon\colon 1_{\mathcal{X}}\to\mathsf{DE} corresponding to this adjunction are given by evaluations

e𝐀(a)(u)=u(a)\displaystyle e_{\mathbf{A}}(a)(u)=u(a)\qquad for all 𝐀𝒜,u𝖣(𝐀) and aA,\displaystyle\text{for all }\mathbf{A}\in\mathcal{A},u\in\mathsf{D}(\mathbf{A})\text{ and }a\in A,
ε𝐗(x)(α)=α(x)\displaystyle\varepsilon_{\mathbf{X}}(x)(\alpha)=\alpha(x)\qquad for all 𝐗𝒳,α𝖤(𝐗) and xX.\displaystyle\text{for all }\mathbf{X}\in\mathcal{X},\alpha\in\mathsf{E}(\mathbf{X})\text{ and }x\in X.

If ee is a natural isomorphism, we say that 𝐌~\utilde{\mathbf{M}} yields a duality for 𝒜\mathcal{A} (this is also known as dual representation). If ε\varepsilon is a natural isomorphism as well, we say that 𝐌~\utilde{\mathbf{M}} yields a full duality for 𝒜\mathcal{A} (meaning that 𝖣\mathsf{D} and 𝖤\mathsf{E} establish a dual equivalence). In fact, in this paper we exclusively deal with strong dualities [8, Chapter 3], which are full dualities with the additional property that 𝐌~\utilde{\mathbf{M}} is injective in 𝒳\mathcal{X}.

In particular, for lattice-based algebras, strong dualities can often be obtained via the NU Strong Duality Corollary [8, Corollary 3.3.9].

Corollary 2.2.

[8] Let 𝐌\mathbf{M} have a majority term, and let all subalgebras of 𝐌\mathbf{M} be subdirectly irreducible. Then

𝐌~=M,K,P1,𝕊(𝐌×𝐌),𝒯dis,\utilde{\mathbf{M}}=\langle M,K,P_{1},\mathbb{S}(\mathbf{M}\times\mathbf{M}),\mathcal{T}_{\mathrm{dis}}\rangle,

yields a strong duality on 𝒜\mathcal{A}, where KK is the union of trivial (i.e., one-element) subalgebras of 𝐌\mathbf{M}, the set P1P_{1} consists of all unary partial homomorphisms 𝐌𝐌\mathbf{M}\to\mathbf{M} and 𝕊(𝐌×𝐌)\mathbb{S}(\mathbf{M}\times\mathbf{M}) consists of all binary algebraic operations.

While this corollary narrows down the structure needed to obtain a strong duality, this 𝐌~\utilde{\mathbf{M}} is usually still more complicated than it necessarily has to be. This is where (strong) entailment comes into play. We say that another alter ego 𝐌~=M,𝒢,,,𝒯dis\utilde{\mathbf{M}}^{\prime}=\langle M,\mathcal{G}^{\prime},\mathcal{H}^{\prime},\mathcal{R}^{\prime},\mathcal{T}_{\mathrm{dis}}\rangle strongly entails 𝐌~\utilde{\mathbf{M}} if whenever 𝐌~\utilde{\mathbf{M}} yields a strong duality on 𝒜\mathcal{A}, the same is true for 𝐌~\utilde{\mathbf{M}^{\prime}}. Similarly, we say that members of 𝒢\mathcal{G}^{\prime}\cup\mathcal{H}^{\prime}\cup\mathcal{R}^{\prime} strongly entail members of 𝒢\mathcal{G}\cup\mathcal{H}\cup\mathcal{R}. In the following, we give a list of admissible constructs for strong entailment relevant for this paper (see [8, Chapter 9] for a complete list of admissible constructs for entailment).

  1. (1)

    Any set of relations strongly entails the full product 𝐌2\mathbf{M}^{2}, the diagonal Δ𝐌={(m,m)m𝐌}\Delta_{\mathbf{M}}=\{(m,m)\mid m\in\mathbf{M}\} of 𝐌\mathbf{M} and the identity 𝗂𝖽𝐌\mathsf{id}_{\mathbf{M}} on 𝐌\mathbf{M}.

  2. (2)

    Any binary relation 𝐑\mathbf{R} strongly entails its converse 𝐑1={(b,a)(a,b𝐑)}\mathbf{R}^{-1}=\{(b,a)\mid(a,b\in\mathbf{R})\} and π1(𝐑Δ𝐌)\pi_{1}(\mathbf{R}\cap\Delta_{\mathbf{M}}).

  3. (3)

    Relations 𝐒,𝐑𝐌n\mathbf{S},\mathbf{R}\subseteq\mathbf{M}^{n} strongly entail their intersection 𝐒𝐑\mathbf{S}\cap\mathbf{R}.

  4. (4)

    Arbitrary relations 𝐒\mathbf{S} and 𝐑\mathbf{R} entail their product 𝐒×𝐑\mathbf{S}\times\mathbf{R}.

  5. (5)

    𝐌~\utilde{\mathbf{M}}^{\prime} strongly entails 𝐌~\utilde{\mathbf{M}} if it is obtained from 𝐌~\utilde{\mathbf{M}} by deleting a partial operation hh\in\mathcal{H} which has an extension in 𝒢\mathcal{G} and adding its domain to \mathcal{R}.

We say that 𝐌~\utilde{\mathbf{M}} yields an optimal strong duality if 𝒢\mathcal{G}\cup\mathcal{H}\cup\mathcal{R} is not strongly entailed by any of its proper subsets.

We illustrate the concepts introduced in this subsection by explaining how to obtain natural dualities for 𝖬𝖵n\mathsf{MV}_{n} (these dualities have been explored in [20]). This example is a specific instance of the proof of the Semi-primal Strong Duality Theorem [8, Theorem 3.3.14].

Example 2.3.

Let n1n\geq 1. The discrete structure

Ł~n={0,1n,n1n,1},𝕊(Łn),𝒯dis,\utilde{\text{\bf\L}}_{n}=\langle\{0,\tfrac{1}{n},\dots\tfrac{n-1}{n},1\},\mathbb{S}(\text{\bf\L}_{n}),\mathcal{T}_{\mathrm{dis}}\rangle,

where members of 𝕊(Łn)\mathbb{S}(\text{\bf\L}_{n}) are understood as unary relations, yields a strong duality on 𝖬𝖵n\mathsf{MV}_{n}.

Proof.

By Corollary 2.2, the structure

{0,1n,n1n,1},K,P1,𝕊(Łnףn),𝒯dis\langle\{0,\tfrac{1}{n},\dots\tfrac{n-1}{n},1\},K,P_{1},\mathbb{S}(\text{\bf\L}_{n}\times\text{\bf\L}_{n}),\mathcal{T}_{\mathrm{dis}}\rangle

yields a strong duality on 𝖬𝖵n\mathsf{MV}_{n} (where KK is the union of one-element subalgebras and P1P_{1} is the collection of all unary partial homomorphisms). Since Łn\text{\bf\L}_{n} is based on a bounded lattice, it has no one-element subalgebras, therefore K=K=\varnothing. Furthermore, the only homomorphism ŁkŁn\text{\bf\L}_{k}\to\text{\bf\L}_{n} defined on a subalgebra ŁkŁn\text{\bf\L}_{k}\subseteq\text{\bf\L}_{n} is the natural embedding of Łk\text{\bf\L}_{k}. Using the strong entailment constructs (1) and (5) above, it can be replaced by its domain Łk𝕊(Łn)\text{\bf\L}_{k}\in\mathbb{S}(\text{\bf\L}_{n}). Every subalgebra 𝐑𝕊(Łnףn)\mathbf{R}\in\mathbb{S}(\text{\bf\L}_{n}\times\text{\bf\L}_{n}) is simply a product of subalgebras of Łn\text{\bf\L}_{n}. Therefore, by (4) above, they are strongly entailed by 𝕊(Łn)\mathbb{S}(\text{\bf\L}_{n}) as well. ∎

It follows from [8, Theorem 9.2.6] that modifying the structure from Example 2.3 to only include the meet-irreducible members of the lattice 𝕊(Łn)\mathbb{S}(\text{\bf\L}_{n}) yields an optimal strong duality (also see [8, Theorem 8.3.2]).

In the next section, we aim to come up with a similarly simple natural duality for varieties generated by positive 𝖬𝖵\mathsf{MV}-chains.

3. Natural dualities for varieties generated by positive MV-chains

In Subsection 3.1, we introduce the varieties 𝖯𝖬𝖵n\mathsf{PMV}_{n} of positive 𝖬𝖵n\mathsf{MV}_{n}-algebras, generated by the positive 𝖬𝖵n\mathsf{MV}_{n}-chains 𝐏Łn\mathbf{P\text{\bf\L}}_{n}. We prove some basic facts about congruences and subalgebras of 𝐏Łn\mathbf{P\text{\bf\L}}_{n} and show that the variety generated by 𝐏Łn\mathbf{P\text{\bf\L}}_{n} coincides with the quasi-variety generated by 𝐏Łn\mathbf{P\text{\bf\L}}_{n}. In Subsection 3.2, we develop our natural dualities for the varieties 𝖯𝖬𝖵n\mathsf{PMV}_{n}. In particular, to this end the systematic study of subalgebras of the order relation \leq (which is itself a subalgebra of 𝐏Łn×𝐏Łn\mathbf{P\text{\bf\L}}_{n}\times\mathbf{P\text{\bf\L}}_{n}) plays an important role.

3.1. Positive MV-chains

Following the recent paper [1], we use the term positive 𝖬𝖵\mathsf{MV}-algebra to refer to a negation-free (and implication-free) subreduct of an 𝖬𝖵\mathsf{MV}-algebra. In particular, we focus on finite positive 𝖬𝖵\mathsf{MV}-chains defined as follows.

Definition 3.1.

Let n1n\geq 1 be a natural number. The (n+1)(n+1)-element positive 𝖬𝖵\mathsf{MV}-chain is given by

𝐏Łn={0,1n,n1n,1},,,,,0,1,\mathbf{P\text{\bf\L}}_{n}=\langle\{0,\tfrac{1}{n},\dots\tfrac{n-1}{n},1\},\wedge,\vee,\odot,\oplus,0,1\rangle,

understood as a reduct of Łn\text{\bf\L}_{n}. We write 𝖯𝖬𝖵n\mathsf{PMV}_{n} for the variety 𝕊(𝐏Łn)\mathbb{H}\mathbb{S}\mathbb{P}(\mathbf{P\text{\bf\L}}_{n}) generated by 𝐏Łn\mathbf{P\text{\bf\L}}_{n}, and we refer to members of 𝖯𝖬𝖵n\mathsf{PMV}_{n} as positive 𝖬𝖵n\mathsf{MV}_{n}-algebras or 𝖯𝖬𝖵n\mathsf{PMV}_{n}-algebras.

Our first result about 𝐏Łn\mathbf{P\text{\bf\L}}_{n} is that its subalgebras are the same as the subalgebras of Łn\text{\bf\L}_{n} and, therefore (recall Subsection 2.1), the subalgebra-lattice 𝕊(𝐏Łn)\mathbb{S}(\mathbf{P\text{\bf\L}}_{n}) is isomorphic to the bounded lattice of diviors of nn.

Proposition 3.2.

The subalgebras of 𝐏Łn\mathbf{P\text{\bf\L}}_{n} are exactly given by the subuniverses

𝐏Łk{0,n,,(k1)n,1},\mathbf{P\text{\bf\L}}_{k}\cong\{0,\tfrac{\ell}{n},\dots,\tfrac{(k-1)\ell}{n},1\},

where n=kn=k\cdot\ell.

Proof.

Let 𝐋𝐏Łn\mathbf{L}\subseteq\mathbf{P\text{\bf\L}}_{n} be an arbitrary subalgebra and let n\frac{\ell}{n} be the unique minimal element of 𝐋\mathbf{L} which is not zero. If =n\ell=n, then 𝐋=𝐏Ł1\mathbf{L}=\mathbf{P\text{\bf\L}}_{1} holds, so assume <n\ell<n. Note that this implies n12\frac{\ell}{n}\leq\frac{1}{2}, since otherwise nn\frac{\ell}{n}\odot\frac{\ell}{n} would be an element of 𝐋\mathbf{L} greater than zero but strictly smaller than n\frac{\ell}{n}, contradicting our choice of \ell. Furthermore, \ell needs to be a divisor of nn, since otherwise we can find natural numbers x1x\geq 1 and 0<r<0<r<\ell with n=x+rn=x\ell+r. But then xnn=rn\frac{x\ell}{n}\odot\frac{\ell}{n}=\frac{r}{n} is a member of 𝐋\mathbf{L} above zero but strictly below n\frac{\ell}{n}, again contradicting our choice of \ell. Thus we showed that \ell divides nn and therefore, by closure of 𝐋\mathbf{L} under \oplus, we showed that 𝐏Łk\mathbf{P\text{\bf\L}}_{k} as in the proposition is contained in 𝐋\mathbf{L}.

Suppose towards contradiction that there is some sn𝐋𝐏Łk\frac{s}{n}\in\mathbf{L}{\setminus}\mathbf{P\text{\bf\L}}_{k}. Then <s\ell<s holds by the above assumption and we can find natural numbers k>x>1k>x>1 and 0<r<0<r<\ell such that s=x+rs=x\ell+r. This is equivalent to

r+n=sx+n=s+(kx).r+n=s-x\ell+n=s+(k-x)\ell.

Therefore, we conclude that rn=sn(kx)n\frac{r}{n}=\frac{s}{n}\odot\frac{(k-x)\ell}{n} is in 𝐋\mathbf{L}, once more contradicting minimality in our choice of \ell. ∎

As noted at the end of Subsection 2.1, the unary operations τd\tau_{d} can be defined from \odot and \oplus alone. This fact will be of high importance in many proofs later on.

Lemma 3.3.

[21] For every d𝐏Łnd\in\mathbf{P\text{\bf\L}}_{n}, the unary operation τd:ŁnŁn\tau_{d}\colon\text{\L}_{n}\to\text{\L}_{n} given by

τd(x)={1 if dx,0 otherwise \tau_{d}(x)=\begin{cases}1&\text{ if }d\leq x,\\ 0&\text{ otherwise }\end{cases}

is term-definable in 𝐏Łn\mathbf{P\text{\bf\L}}_{n}.

Remark 3.4.

While we chose to exclusively focus on 𝐏Łn\mathbf{P\text{\bf\L}}_{n} in this paper, all results up until Lemma 3.9 actually hold for every finite algebra 𝐃\mathbf{D} which has a bounded-lattice reduct and in which τd\tau_{d} defined as above is term-definable in 𝐃\mathbf{D} for every d𝐃d\in\mathbf{D}. In particular, this encompasses the negation-free reducts of the finite Łukasiewicz-Moisil chains (see, e.g., [2]).

Our first goal is to show that the variety 𝖯𝖬𝖵n\mathsf{PMV}_{n} coincides with the quasi-variety 𝕀𝕊(𝐏Łn)\mathbb{I}\mathbb{S}\mathbb{P}(\mathbf{P\text{\bf\L}}_{n}) generated by 𝐏Łn\mathbf{P\text{\bf\L}}_{n}. For this, we essentially only have to show the following.

Lemma 3.5.

Every subalgebra 𝐏Łk𝐏Łn\mathbf{P\text{\bf\L}}_{k}\subseteq\mathbf{P\text{\bf\L}}_{n} (including 𝐏Łn\mathbf{P\text{\bf\L}}_{n} itself) is simple.

Proof.

Let θ\theta be a congruence relation on 𝐒\mathbf{S} and let c,d𝐏Łkc,d\in\mathbf{P\text{\bf\L}}_{k} be distinct elements with (c,d)θ(c,d)\in\theta. We show that θ\theta is the trivial congruence identifying all members of 𝐏Łk\mathbf{P\text{\bf\L}}_{k}. Without loss of generality, we assume c<dc<d. Since τd\tau_{d} from Lemma 3.3 is term-definable in 𝐏Łn\mathbf{P\text{\bf\L}}_{n}, we have (0,1)=(τd(c),τd(d))θ(0,1)=(\tau_{d}(c),\tau_{d}(d))\in\theta and (1,0)θ(1,0)\in\theta by symmetry. Now, for arbitrary x,y𝐏Łkx,y\in\mathbf{P\text{\bf\L}}_{k}, we have

(x,y)=((1,0)(x,x))((0,1)(y,y))θ,(x,y)=\big{(}(1,0)\wedge(x,x)\big{)}\vee\big{(}(0,1)\wedge(y,y)\big{)}\in\theta,

which implies θ=𝐏Łk2\theta=\mathbf{P\text{\bf\L}}_{k}^{2}. ∎

Since 𝖯𝖬𝖵n\mathsf{PMV}_{n} is congruence distributive (because 𝐏Łn\mathbf{P\text{\bf\L}}_{n} is lattice-based and thus has a majority term), a standard application of Jónsson’s Lemma [16] yields the following (see, e.g., [8, Theorem 1.3.6]).

Corollary 3.6.

𝖯𝖬𝖵n=𝕀𝕊(𝐏Łn)\mathsf{PMV}_{n}=\mathbb{I}\mathbb{S}\mathbb{P}(\mathbf{P\text{\bf\L}}_{n}).

This allows us to study the variety 𝖯𝖬𝖵n\mathsf{PMV}_{n} via the theory of natural dualities in what follows.

3.2. The natural dualities

This subsection is dedicated to finding a simple alter-ego 𝐏Ł~n\utilde{\mathbf{P\text{\bf\L}}}_{n} of 𝐏Łn\mathbf{P\text{\bf\L}}_{n} which yields a ‘useful’ [8, Chapter 6] strong duality on 𝖯𝖬𝖵n\mathsf{PMV}_{n}. Since 𝐏Łn\mathbf{P\text{\bf\L}}_{n} has a bounded lattice reduct, it has a majority term and no trivial subalgebras. Furthermore, by Lemma 3.5 we know that every subalgebra of 𝐏Łn\mathbf{P\text{\bf\L}}_{n} is subdirectly irreducible. Therefore, we may use Corollary 2.2 (i.e., the NU Strong Duality Corollary [8, Corollary 3.3.9]) as our starting point. This states that

(1) {0,1n,,n1n,1},P1,𝕊(𝐏Łn×𝐏Łn),𝒯dis,\langle\{0,\tfrac{1}{n},\dots,\tfrac{n-1}{n},1\},P_{1},\mathbb{S}(\mathbf{P\text{\bf\L}}_{n}\times\mathbf{P\text{\bf\L}}_{n}),\mathcal{T}_{\mathrm{dis}}\rangle,

yields a strong duality for 𝖯𝖬𝖵n\mathsf{PMV}_{n}, where P1P_{1} is the set of all unary partial homomorphisms 𝐏Łn𝐏Łn\mathbf{P\text{\bf\L}}_{n}\to\mathbf{P\text{\bf\L}}_{n}. In the following we show that, as for Łn\text{\bf\L}_{n}, the only partial homomorphisms of this kind are the identities of subalgebras of 𝐏Łn\mathbf{P\text{\bf\L}}_{n}.

Lemma 3.7.

Let 𝐏Łk𝐏Łn\mathbf{P\text{\bf\L}}_{k}\subseteq\mathbf{P\text{\bf\L}}_{n} be a subalgebra. Then the only homomorphism 𝐏Łk𝐏Łn\mathbf{P\text{\bf\L}}_{k}\to\mathbf{P\text{\bf\L}}_{n} is the identity on 𝐏Łk\mathbf{P\text{\bf\L}}_{k} followed by inclusion.

Proof.

Let h:𝐏Łk𝐃h\colon\mathbf{P\text{\bf\L}}_{k}\to\mathbf{D} be a homomorphism. Suppose the are some s𝐏Łks\in\mathbf{P\text{\bf\L}}_{k} and d𝐏Łnd\in\mathbf{P\text{\bf\L}}_{n} such that h(s)=dh(s)=d and sds\neq d. Recall that τd\tau_{d} and τs\tau_{s} from Lemma 3.3 are term-definable and thus preserved by hh. If s<ds<d then 1=τd(h(s))=h(τd(s))=h(0)=01=\tau_{d}(h(s))=h(\tau_{d}(s))=h(0)=0 yields a contradiction. If r<sr<s then 1=h(τs(s))=τs(h(s))=τs(d)=01=h(\tau_{s}(s))=\tau_{s}(h(s))=\tau_{s}(d)=0 also yields a contradiction. Thus no such elements ss and dd can exist and we showed that h(s)=sh(s)=s holds for all s𝐏Łks\in\mathbf{P\text{\bf\L}}_{k}. ∎

Therefore, as in Example 2.3, the collection P1P_{1} of unary partial homomorphisms is strongly entailed by the collection of unary algebraic relations 𝕊(𝐏Łn)\mathbb{S}(\mathbf{P\text{\bf\L}}_{n}). Now we take a closer look at the binary algebraic relations in 𝕊(𝐏Łn×𝐏Łn)\mathbb{S}(\mathbf{P\text{\bf\L}}_{n}\times\mathbf{P\text{\bf\L}}_{n}). Contrary to Łn\text{\bf\L}_{n}, the algebra 𝐏Łn×𝐏Łn\mathbf{P\text{\bf\L}}_{n}\times\mathbf{P\text{\bf\L}}_{n} has subalgebras which are not direct products of subalgebras of 𝐏Łn\mathbf{P\text{\bf\L}}_{n}. For example, since all operations of 𝐏Łn\mathbf{P\text{\bf\L}}_{n} are order-preserving, the relation \leq and its converse \geq are clearly subalgebras of 𝐏Łn×𝐏Łn\mathbf{P\text{\bf\L}}_{n}\times\mathbf{P\text{\bf\L}}_{n}. In the following, we show that every other subalgebra of 𝐏Łn\mathbf{P\text{\bf\L}}_{n} which is not a direct product of subalgebras is contained in one of those.

Lemma 3.8.

Every subalgebra 𝐑𝐏Łn×𝐏Łn\mathbf{R}\subseteq\mathbf{P\text{\bf\L}}_{n}\times\mathbf{P\text{\bf\L}}_{n} which is not a direct product of subalgebras of 𝐏Łn\mathbf{P\text{\bf\L}}_{n} is a subalgebra of \leq or of \geq.

Proof.

Suppose that 𝐑\mathbf{R} is neither a subset of \leq nor of \geq. We show that this implies that 𝐑\mathbf{R} is a direct product of subalgebras of 𝐏Łn\mathbf{P\text{\bf\L}}_{n}. Since 𝐑\mathbf{R} is not a subset of \leq, there is (d1,c1)𝐑(d_{1},c_{1})\in\mathbf{R} with d1>c1d_{1}>c_{1}. Similarly, there is (c2,d2)𝐑(c_{2},d_{2})\in\mathbf{R} with c2<d2c_{2}<d_{2}. This implies that (1,0)=τd1(d1,c1)(1,0)=\tau_{d_{1}}(d_{1},c_{1}) and (0,1)=τd2(c2,d2)(0,1)=\tau_{d_{2}}(c_{2},d_{2}) are both in 𝐑\mathbf{R}. As in the proof of Lemma 3.5, with this we can show that 𝐑\mathbf{R} is the full direct product of its two projections 𝗉𝗋1(𝐑)\mathsf{pr}_{1}(\mathbf{R}) and 𝗉𝗋2(𝐑)\mathsf{pr}_{2}(\mathbf{R}). ∎

Since every binary relation strongly entails its converse and all products of subalgebras of 𝐏Łn\mathbf{P\text{\bf\L}}_{n} are strongly entailed by 𝕊(𝐏Łn)\mathbb{S}(\mathbf{P\text{\bf\L}}_{n}), it follows that the structure

(2) {0,1n,,n1n,1},𝕊(𝐏Łn)𝕊(),𝒯dis\langle\{0,\tfrac{1}{n},\dots,\tfrac{n-1}{n},1\},\mathbb{S}(\mathbf{P\text{\bf\L}}_{n})\cup\mathbb{S}(\leq),\mathcal{T}_{\mathrm{dis}}\rangle

yields a strong duality for 𝖯𝖬𝖵n\mathsf{PMV}_{n}, since it strongly entails the structure from Equation (1).

While the structure given in Equation (2) is already much simpler than that in Equation (1), it is still far from optimal. Therefore, we keep on studying 𝕊()\mathbb{S}(\leq) in order to further simplify this alter ego.

A somewhat special role is played by the subalgebra of the order 𝕊()\lhd\in\mathbb{S}(\leq) given by

={(x,y)x=0 or y=1}.\lhd=\{(x,y)\mid x=0\text{ or }y=1\}.

It is easy to see that this is a subalgebra since 0x=0x=00\wedge x=0\odot x=0 and 1x=1x=11\vee x=1\oplus x=1 for all x𝐏Łnx\in\mathbf{P\text{\bf\L}}_{n}. Unfortunately, except for the case n=2n=2, this is not the only non-diagonal proper subalgebra of the order relation. However, it is minimal among those subalgebras in the following sense.

Lemma 3.9.

Let 𝐑𝐏Łn×𝐏Łn\mathbf{R}\subseteq\mathbf{P\text{\bf\L}}_{n}\times\mathbf{P\text{\bf\L}}_{n} be a subalgebra of the order \leq, which is not the diagonal of a subalgebra of 𝐏Łn\mathbf{P\text{\bf\L}}_{n}, and 𝐒=𝗉𝗋1(𝐑)×𝗉𝗋2(𝐑)\mathbf{S}=\mathsf{pr}_{1}(\mathbf{R})\times\mathsf{pr}_{2}(\mathbf{R}). Then 𝐒𝐑𝐒\lhd{\mid}_{\mathbf{S}}\subseteq\mathbf{R}\subseteq{\leq}{\mid}_{\mathbf{S}}.

Proof.

Since 𝐑\mathbf{R} is not a diagonal, there is a pair (x,y)𝐑(x,y)\in\mathbf{R} with xyx\neq y, implying x<yx<y. Therefore, τy(x,y)=(0,1)𝐑\tau_{y}(x,y)=(0,1)\in\mathbf{R} as well. Now, for any (x,y)𝐑(x^{\prime},y^{\prime})\in\mathbf{R} we find that

(0,y)=(x,y)(0,1) and (x,1)=(x,y)(0,1)(0,y^{\prime})=(x^{\prime},y^{\prime})\wedge(0,1)\text{ and }(x^{\prime},1)=(x^{\prime},y^{\prime})\vee(0,1)

are also members of 𝐑\mathbf{R}, finishing the proof. ∎

Since diagonals of subalgebras are strongly entailed by 𝕊(𝐏Łn)\mathbb{S}(\mathbf{P\text{\bf\L}}_{n}) already, we only need to consider subalgebras in-between (restrictions of) \lhd and \leq. In order to describe these subalgebras, the following ‘closure’ downwards in the first and upwards in the second component will be crucial.

Definition 3.10.

Let 𝐒=𝐏Łk×𝐏Łk\mathbf{S}=\mathbf{P\text{\bf\L}}_{k}\times\mathbf{P\text{\bf\L}}_{k^{\prime}} be a product of subalgebras of 𝐏Łn\mathbf{P\text{\bf\L}}_{n} (recall Proposition 3.2). Let (x,y)𝐒(x,y)\in\mathbf{S} with xyx\leq y. We denote by C(x,y),𝐒C_{(x,y),\mathbf{S}} the following subset of 𝐒\mathbf{S} and \leq.

C(x,y),𝐒={(x,y)𝐒xx and yy}.C_{(x,y),\mathbf{S}}=\{(x^{\prime},y^{\prime})\in\mathbf{S}\mid x^{\prime}\leq x\text{ and }y\leq y^{\prime}\}.

If 𝐒=𝐏Łn×𝐏Łn\mathbf{S}=\mathbf{P\text{\bf\L}}_{n}\times\mathbf{P\text{\bf\L}}_{n}, we simply use C(x,y)C_{(x,y)} instead of C(x,y),𝐒C_{(x,y),\mathbf{S}}.

For example, Figure 1 depicts the subsets C(26,36)C_{(\frac{2}{6},\frac{3}{6})} and C(26,36),𝐒C_{(\frac{2}{6},\frac{3}{6}),\mathbf{S}} for 𝐒=𝐏Ł3×𝐏Ł2\mathbf{S}=\mathbf{P\text{\bf\L}}_{3}\times\mathbf{P\text{\bf\L}}_{2} as subsets of 𝐏Ł6×𝐏Ł6\mathbf{P\text{\bf\L}}_{6}\times\mathbf{P\text{\bf\L}}_{6}.

(1,1)(1,1) (56,56)(\tfrac{5}{6},\tfrac{5}{6}) (56,1)(\tfrac{5}{6},1) (46,46)(\tfrac{4}{6},\tfrac{4}{6}) (46,56)(\tfrac{4}{6},\tfrac{5}{6}) (46,1)(\tfrac{4}{6},1) (36,36)(\tfrac{3}{6},\tfrac{3}{6}) (36,46)(\tfrac{3}{6},\tfrac{4}{6}) (36,56)(\tfrac{3}{6},\tfrac{5}{6}) (36,1)(\tfrac{3}{6},1) (26,26)(\tfrac{2}{6},\tfrac{2}{6}) (26,36)(\tfrac{2}{6},\tfrac{3}{6}) (26,46)(\tfrac{2}{6},\tfrac{4}{6}) (26,56)(\tfrac{2}{6},\tfrac{5}{6}) (26,1)(\tfrac{2}{6},1) (16,16)(\tfrac{1}{6},\tfrac{1}{6}) (16,26)(\tfrac{1}{6},\tfrac{2}{6}) (16,36)(\tfrac{1}{6},\tfrac{3}{6}) (16,46)(\tfrac{1}{6},\tfrac{4}{6}) (16,56)(\tfrac{1}{6},\tfrac{5}{6}) (16,1)(\tfrac{1}{6},1) (0,0)(0,0) (0,16)(0,\tfrac{1}{6}) (0,26)(0,\tfrac{2}{6}) (0,36)(0,\tfrac{3}{6}) (0,46)(0,\tfrac{4}{6}) (0,56)(0,\tfrac{5}{6}) (0,1)(0,1) (1,1)(1,1) (56,56)(\tfrac{5}{6},\tfrac{5}{6}) (56,1)(\tfrac{5}{6},1) (46,46)(\tfrac{4}{6},\tfrac{4}{6}) (46,56)(\tfrac{4}{6},\tfrac{5}{6}) (46,1)(\tfrac{4}{6},1) (36,36)(\tfrac{3}{6},\tfrac{3}{6}) (36,46)(\tfrac{3}{6},\tfrac{4}{6}) (36,56)(\tfrac{3}{6},\tfrac{5}{6}) (36,1)(\tfrac{3}{6},1) (26,26)(\tfrac{2}{6},\tfrac{2}{6}) (26,36)(\tfrac{2}{6},\tfrac{3}{6}) (26,46)(\tfrac{2}{6},\tfrac{4}{6}) (26,56)(\tfrac{2}{6},\tfrac{5}{6}) (26,1)(\tfrac{2}{6},1) (16,16)(\tfrac{1}{6},\tfrac{1}{6}) (16,26)(\tfrac{1}{6},\tfrac{2}{6}) (16,36)(\tfrac{1}{6},\tfrac{3}{6}) (16,46)(\tfrac{1}{6},\tfrac{4}{6}) (16,56)(\tfrac{1}{6},\tfrac{5}{6}) (16,1)(\tfrac{1}{6},1) (0,0)(0,0) (0,16)(0,\tfrac{1}{6}) (0,26)(0,\tfrac{2}{6}) (0,36)(0,\tfrac{3}{6}) (0,46)(0,\tfrac{4}{6}) (0,56)(0,\tfrac{5}{6}) (0,1)(0,1)

Figure 1. The sets C(26,36)C_{(\frac{2}{6},\frac{3}{6})} and C(26,36),𝐏Ł3×𝐏Ł2C_{(\frac{2}{6},\frac{3}{6}),\mathbf{P\text{\bf\L}}_{3}\times\mathbf{P\text{\bf\L}}_{2}} in the case n=6n=6.

In the next lemma, we show that non-diagonal subalgebras of the order are closed under these subsets in the following sense.

Lemma 3.11.

Let 𝐑𝐏Łn×𝐏Łn\mathbf{R}\subseteq\mathbf{P\text{\bf\L}}_{n}\times\mathbf{P\text{\bf\L}}_{n} be a subalgebra of the order \leq which is not the diagonal of a subalgebra of 𝐏Łn\mathbf{P\text{\bf\L}}_{n}, and 𝐒=𝗉𝗋1(𝐑)×𝗉𝗋2(𝐑)\mathbf{S}=\mathsf{pr}_{1}(\mathbf{R})\times\mathsf{pr}_{2}(\mathbf{R}). If (x,y)𝐑(x,y)\in\mathbf{R}, then C(x,y),𝐒𝐑C_{(x,y),\mathbf{S}}\subseteq\mathbf{R} as well.

Proof.

By Lemma 3.9 we know that 𝐒𝐑\lhd{\mid}_{\mathbf{S}}\subseteq\mathbf{R}. Now let (x,y)𝐑(x,y)\in\mathbf{R}, and say (x,y)𝐒(x^{\prime},y^{\prime})\in\mathbf{S} satisfies xxx^{\prime}\leq x and yyy\leq y^{\prime}. Then (x,y)=(x,y)(x,1)(x^{\prime},y)=(x,y)\wedge(x^{\prime},1) is in 𝐑\mathbf{R} and, thus, (x,y)=(x,y)(0,y)(x^{\prime},y^{\prime})=(x^{\prime},y)\vee(0,y^{\prime}) is also in 𝐑\mathbf{R}. ∎

Therefore, clearly every 𝐑\mathbf{R} as in the above lemma is a union of sets of the form C(x,y),𝐒C_{(x,y),\mathbf{S}}. However, not all unions of sets of this form necessarily yield subalgebras. In the following, we identify exactly those unions which do give rise to subalgebras of 𝐏Łn×𝐏Łn\mathbf{P\text{\bf\L}}_{n}\times\mathbf{P\text{\bf\L}}_{n}.

Proposition 3.12.

Let 𝐒=𝐏Łk×𝐏Łk\mathbf{S}=\mathbf{P\text{\bf\L}}_{k}\times\mathbf{P\text{\bf\L}}_{k^{\prime}} be a product of subalgebras of 𝐏Łn\mathbf{P\text{\bf\L}}_{n}.

  1. (1)

    Let 𝐑𝐏Łn×𝐏Łn\mathbf{R}\subseteq\mathbf{P\text{\bf\L}}_{n}\times\mathbf{P\text{\bf\L}}_{n} be a subalgebra of \leq, which is not the diagonal of a subalgebra of 𝐏Łn\mathbf{P\text{\bf\L}}_{n}, with 𝗉𝗋1(𝐑)×𝗉𝗋2(𝐑)=𝐒\mathsf{pr}_{1}(\mathbf{R})\times\mathsf{pr}_{2}(\mathbf{R})=\mathbf{S}. Then 𝐑\mathbf{R} can be expressed as

    𝐑=i=0kC(ik,yi),𝐒\mathbf{R}=\bigcup_{i=0}^{k}C_{(\frac{i}{k},y_{i}),\mathbf{S}}

    where yiy_{i} is the minimal element of 𝐏Łk\mathbf{P\text{\bf\L}}_{k^{\prime}} with (ik,yi)𝐑(\frac{i}{k},y_{i})\in\mathbf{R} (in particular, y0=0y_{0}=0 and yk=1y_{k}=1).

  2. (2)

    Let y0,,yky_{0},\dots,y_{k} be an increasing sequence of elements of 𝐏Łk\mathbf{P\text{\bf\L}}_{k^{\prime}} with y0=0,yk=1y_{0}=0,y_{k}=1 and ikyi\frac{i}{k}\leq y_{i} for all i=1,,k1i=1,\dots,k-1. Then

    𝐑=i=0kC(ik,yi),𝐒\mathbf{R}=\bigcup_{i=0}^{k}C_{(\frac{i}{k},y_{i}),\mathbf{S}}

    is a subalgebra of 𝐒\mathbf{S} if and only if the conditions

    (ik,yi)(jk,yj)𝐑 and (ik,yi)(jk,yj)𝐑(\tfrac{i}{k},y_{i})\odot(\tfrac{j}{k},y_{j})\in\mathbf{R}\text{ and }(\tfrac{i}{k},y_{i})\oplus(\tfrac{j}{k},y_{j})\in\mathbf{R}

    hold for all i,j{1,,k1}i,j\in\{1,\dots,k-1\}.

Proof.

(1): By Lemma 3.11 we have i=0kC(ik,yi),𝐒𝐑\bigcup_{i=0}^{k}C_{(\frac{i}{k},y_{i}),\mathbf{S}}\subseteq\mathbf{R}. Conversely, if (ik,y)𝐑(\frac{i}{k},y)\in\mathbf{R} then yiyy_{i}\leq y by minimality of yiy_{i} and therefore (ik,y)C(ik,yi),𝐒(\frac{i}{k},y)\in C_{(\frac{i}{k},y_{i}),\mathbf{S}}.

(2): Clearly these conditions are necessary for 𝐑\mathbf{R} to be a subalgebra. We show that they are also sufficient. So, supposing these condition hold, we want to show that 𝐑\mathbf{R} is indeed a subalgebra. First note that 𝐒=C(0,0),𝐒C(1,1),𝐒𝐑\lhd{\mid}_{\mathbf{S}}=C_{(0,0),\mathbf{S}}\cup C_{(1,1),\mathbf{S}}\subseteq\mathbf{R}, in particular this implies that both constants (0,0)(0,0) and (1,1)(1,1) are contained in 𝐑\mathbf{R}. Now let (x,y)(x,y) and (x,y)(x^{\prime},y^{\prime}) be two elements of 𝐑\mathbf{R}, say (x,y)C(ik,yi),𝐒(x,y)\in C_{(\frac{i}{k},y_{i}),\mathbf{S}} and (x,y)C(jk,yj),𝐒(x^{\prime},y^{\prime})\in C_{(\frac{j}{k},y_{j}),\mathbf{S}}. Furthermore, without loss of generality we assume iji\leq j.

We first establish the closure under the lattice operations. To show closure under meets, we note that

(x,y)(x,y)={(x,y)if xx,yy,(x,y)if xx,yy,(x,y)if xx,yy,(x,y)if xx,yy.(x,y)\wedge(x^{\prime},y^{\prime})=\begin{cases}(x,y)&\text{if }x\leq x^{\prime},y\leq y^{\prime},\\ (x^{\prime},y^{\prime})&\text{if }x^{\prime}\leq x,y^{\prime}\leq y,\\ (x^{\prime},y)&\text{if }x^{\prime}\leq x,y\leq y^{\prime},\\ (x,y^{\prime})&\text{if }x\leq x^{\prime},y^{\prime}\leq y.\end{cases}

In the first two cases the meet is obviously still in 𝐑\mathbf{R}. In the third case the two inequalities xxikx^{\prime}\leq x\leq\frac{i}{k} and yiyy_{i}\leq y imply (x,y)C(ik,yi),𝐒(x^{\prime},y)\in C_{(\frac{i}{k},y_{i}),\mathbf{S}}. In the fourth and final case the two inequalities xxjkx\leq x^{\prime}\leq\frac{j}{k} and yjyy_{j}\leq y^{\prime} imply (x,y)C(jk,yj),𝐒(x,y^{\prime})\in C_{(\frac{j}{k},y_{j}),\mathbf{S}}. Closure under joins is established analogously since

(x,y)(x,y)={(x,y)if xx,yy,(x,y)if xx,yy,(x,y)if xx,yy,(x,y)if xx,yy.(x,y)\vee(x^{\prime},y^{\prime})=\begin{cases}(x,y)&\text{if }x^{\prime}\leq x,y^{\prime}\leq y,\\ (x^{\prime},y^{\prime})&\text{if }x\leq x^{\prime},y\leq y^{\prime},\\ (x^{\prime},y)&\text{if }x\leq x^{\prime},y^{\prime}\leq y,\\ (x,y^{\prime})&\text{if }x^{\prime}\leq x,y\leq y^{\prime}.\end{cases}

Note that in the third case we get (x,y)C(jk,yj),𝐒(x^{\prime},y)\in C_{(\frac{j}{k},y_{j}),\mathbf{S}} and in the fourth case we get (x,y)C(ik,yi),𝐒(x,y^{\prime})\in C_{(\frac{i}{k},y_{i}),\mathbf{S}}.

Now let {,}\ast\in\{\odot,\oplus\}, and note that (x,y)C(ik,yi),𝐒(x,y)\in C_{(\frac{i}{k},y_{i}),\mathbf{S}} and (x,y)C(jk,yj),𝐒(x^{\prime},y^{\prime})\in C_{(\frac{j}{k},y_{j}),\mathbf{S}} together with monotonicity of \ast imply

xxikjk and yiyjyy.x\ast x^{\prime}\leq\tfrac{i}{k}\ast\tfrac{j}{k}\text{ and }y_{i}\ast y_{j}\leq y\ast y^{\prime}.

However, by assumption we have (ikjk,yiyj)𝐑(\frac{i}{k}\ast\frac{j}{k},y_{i}\ast y_{j})\in\mathbf{R} say it is contained in C(hk,yh),𝐒C_{(\frac{h}{k},y_{h}),\mathbf{S}}. Thus

xxikjkhk and yhyiyjyyx\ast x^{\prime}\leq\tfrac{i}{k}\ast\tfrac{j}{k}\leq\tfrac{h}{k}\text{ and }y_{h}\leq y_{i}\ast y_{j}\leq y\ast y^{\prime}

immediately implies that (x,y)(x,y)(x,y)\ast(x^{\prime},y^{\prime}) is also contained in C(hk,yh),𝐒C_{(\frac{h}{k},y_{h}),\mathbf{S}}, finishing the proof. ∎

For example, in Figure 2, on the left hand side the union

C(0,0)C(16,26)C(26,36)C(36,56)C(46,1)C(56,1)C(1,1)C_{(0,0)}\cup C_{(\frac{1}{6},\frac{2}{6})}\cup C_{(\frac{2}{6},\frac{3}{6})}\cup C_{(\frac{3}{6},\frac{5}{6})}\cup C_{(\frac{4}{6},1)}\cup C_{(\frac{5}{6},1)}\cup C_{(1,1)}

inside 𝐏Ł6×𝐏Ł6\mathbf{P\text{\bf\L}}_{6}\times\mathbf{P\text{\bf\L}}_{6} is depicted. By Proposition 3.12, we can easily confirm that this is a subalgebra by checking that the ‘corner elements’ (16,26),(26,36)(\frac{1}{6},\frac{2}{6}),(\frac{2}{6},\frac{3}{6}) and (36,56)(\frac{3}{6},\frac{5}{6}) are closed under the opertaions \odot and \oplus. On the right hand side of Figure 2, the union

C(0,0)C(16,26)C(26,36)C(36,1)C(46,1)C(56,1)C(1,1)C_{(0,0)}\cup C_{(\frac{1}{6},\frac{2}{6})}\cup C_{(\frac{2}{6},\frac{3}{6})}\cup C_{(\frac{3}{6},1)}\cup C_{(\frac{4}{6},1)}\cup C_{(\frac{5}{6},1)}\cup C_{(1,1)}

is depicted. This is not a subalgebra because (16,26)(26,36)=(36,56)(\frac{1}{6},\frac{2}{6})\oplus(\frac{2}{6},\frac{3}{6})=(\frac{3}{6},\frac{5}{6}) is not contained in this union.

(1,1)(1,1) (56,56)(\tfrac{5}{6},\tfrac{5}{6}) (56,1)(\tfrac{5}{6},1) (46,46)(\tfrac{4}{6},\tfrac{4}{6}) (46,56)(\tfrac{4}{6},\tfrac{5}{6}) (46,1)(\tfrac{4}{6},1) (36,36)(\tfrac{3}{6},\tfrac{3}{6}) (36,46)(\tfrac{3}{6},\tfrac{4}{6}) (36,56)(\tfrac{3}{6},\tfrac{5}{6}) (36,1)(\tfrac{3}{6},1) (26,26)(\tfrac{2}{6},\tfrac{2}{6}) (26,36)(\tfrac{2}{6},\tfrac{3}{6}) (26,46)(\tfrac{2}{6},\tfrac{4}{6}) (26,56)(\tfrac{2}{6},\tfrac{5}{6}) (26,1)(\tfrac{2}{6},1) (16,16)(\tfrac{1}{6},\tfrac{1}{6}) (16,26)(\tfrac{1}{6},\tfrac{2}{6}) (16,36)(\tfrac{1}{6},\tfrac{3}{6}) (16,46)(\tfrac{1}{6},\tfrac{4}{6}) (16,56)(\tfrac{1}{6},\tfrac{5}{6}) (16,1)(\tfrac{1}{6},1) (0,0)\pagecolor{blue!25}(0,0) (0,16)(0,\tfrac{1}{6}) (0,26)(0,\tfrac{2}{6}) (0,36)(0,\tfrac{3}{6}) (0,46)(0,\tfrac{4}{6}) (0,56)(0,\tfrac{5}{6}) (0,1)(0,1) (1,1)(1,1) (56,56)(\tfrac{5}{6},\tfrac{5}{6}) (56,1)(\tfrac{5}{6},1) (46,46)(\tfrac{4}{6},\tfrac{4}{6}) (46,56)(\tfrac{4}{6},\tfrac{5}{6}) (46,1)(\tfrac{4}{6},1) (36,36)(\tfrac{3}{6},\tfrac{3}{6}) (36,46)(\tfrac{3}{6},\tfrac{4}{6}) (36,56)(\tfrac{3}{6},\tfrac{5}{6}) (36,1)(\tfrac{3}{6},1) (26,26)(\tfrac{2}{6},\tfrac{2}{6}) (26,36)(\tfrac{2}{6},\tfrac{3}{6}) (26,46)(\tfrac{2}{6},\tfrac{4}{6}) (26,56)(\tfrac{2}{6},\tfrac{5}{6}) (26,1)(\tfrac{2}{6},1) (16,16)(\tfrac{1}{6},\tfrac{1}{6}) (16,26)(\tfrac{1}{6},\tfrac{2}{6}) (16,36)(\tfrac{1}{6},\tfrac{3}{6}) (16,46)(\tfrac{1}{6},\tfrac{4}{6}) (16,56)(\tfrac{1}{6},\tfrac{5}{6}) (16,1)(\tfrac{1}{6},1) (0,0)\pagecolor{blue!25}(0,0) (0,16)(0,\tfrac{1}{6}) (0,26)(0,\tfrac{2}{6}) (0,36)(0,\tfrac{3}{6}) (0,46)(0,\tfrac{4}{6}) (0,56)(0,\tfrac{5}{6}) (0,1)(0,1)

Figure 2. Only the subset on the left is a subalgebra of 𝐏Ł6×𝐏Ł6\mathbf{P\text{\bf\L}}_{6}\times\mathbf{P\text{\bf\L}}_{6}.

Now that we have a good grasp on the subalgebras of 𝐏Łn×𝐏Łn\mathbf{P\text{\bf\L}}_{n}\times\mathbf{P\text{\bf\L}}_{n}, we aim to show that, ultimately, only subdirect products 𝐑𝐏Łn×𝐏Łn\mathbf{R}\subseteq\mathbf{P\text{\bf\L}}_{n}\times\mathbf{P\text{\bf\L}}_{n} (meaning 𝗉𝗋1(𝐑)=𝗉𝗋2(𝐑)=𝐏Łn\mathsf{pr}_{1}(\mathbf{R})=\mathsf{pr}_{2}(\mathbf{R})=\mathbf{P\text{\bf\L}}_{n}) will be relevant for the natural duality. By Lemma 3.9, this is equivalent to saying only the following relations will be relevant to the natural duality.

Definition 3.13.

Let 𝒮n𝕊(𝐏Łn×𝐏Łn)\mathcal{S}_{n}\subseteq\mathbb{S}(\mathbf{P\text{\bf\L}}_{n}\times\mathbf{P\text{\bf\L}}_{n}) be the collection of all subalgebras 𝐑𝐏Łn×𝐏Łn\mathbf{R}\subseteq\mathbf{P\text{\bf\L}}_{n}\times\mathbf{P\text{\bf\L}}_{n} which satisfy 𝐑\lhd\subseteq\mathbf{R}\subseteq{\leq}.

It is clear by definition that 𝒮n\mathcal{S}_{n} is a bounded sublattice of 𝕊(𝐏Łn×𝐏Łn)\mathbb{S}(\mathbf{P\text{\bf\L}}_{n}\times\mathbf{P\text{\bf\L}}_{n}) with lower bound \lhd and upper bound \leq.

In the next two (technical) lemmas, we show that the set of relations 𝒮n\mathcal{S}_{n} strongly entails 𝕊()\mathbb{S}(\leq) and 𝕊(𝐏Łn)\mathbb{S}(\mathbf{P\text{\bf\L}}_{n}). The first lemma shows that relations 𝐑𝕊()\mathbf{R}\in\mathbb{S}(\leq) with 𝗉𝗋1(𝐑)×𝗉𝗋2(𝐑)𝐏Łn×𝐏Łn\mathsf{pr}_{1}(\mathbf{R})\times\mathsf{pr}_{2}(\mathbf{R})\neq\mathbf{P\text{\bf\L}}_{n}\times\mathbf{P\text{\bf\L}}_{n} are strongly entailed by 𝕊(𝐏Łn)\mathbb{S}(\mathbf{P\text{\bf\L}}_{n}) and 𝒮n\mathcal{S}_{n}.

Lemma 3.14.

Let 𝐑𝐏Łn×𝐏Łn\mathbf{R}\subseteq\mathbf{P\text{\bf\L}}_{n}\times\mathbf{P\text{\bf\L}}_{n} be a subalgebra of the order \leq, which is not the diagonal of a subalgebra of 𝐏Łn\mathbf{P\text{\bf\L}}_{n}, and let 𝐒=𝗉𝗋1(𝐑)×𝗉𝗋2(𝐑)=𝐏Łk×𝐏Łk\mathbf{S}=\mathsf{pr}_{1}(\mathbf{R})\times\mathsf{pr}_{2}(\mathbf{R})=\mathbf{P\text{\bf\L}}_{k}\times\mathbf{P\text{\bf\L}}_{k^{\prime}} for some divisors k,kk,k^{\prime} of nn. Then there exists a subalgebra 𝐑¯𝒮n\overline{\mathbf{R}}\in\mathcal{S}_{n} with 𝐑=𝐑¯𝐒\mathbf{R}=\overline{\mathbf{R}}\cap\mathbf{S}.

Proof.

By Proposition 3.12(1), we know that 𝐑\mathbf{R} can be expressed as union

𝐑=i=0kC(ik,yi),𝐒\mathbf{R}=\bigcup_{i=0}^{k}C_{(\frac{i}{k},y_{i}),\mathbf{S}}

where yiy_{i} is the minimal element of 𝐏Łk\mathbf{P\text{\bf\L}}_{k^{\prime}} with (ik,yi)𝐑(\frac{i}{k},y_{i})\in\mathbf{R}. Let n=kn=k\cdot\ell. We define 𝐑¯\overline{\mathbf{R}} by

𝐑¯=j=0nC(jn,y^j)\overline{\mathbf{R}}=\bigcup_{j=0}^{n}C_{(\frac{j}{n},\hat{y}_{j})}

where we stipulate y^0=0\hat{y}_{0}=0 and

y^j={y1if 1j,y2if +1j2,yk1if (k2)+1j(k1),yk=1if (k1)+1jn.\hat{y}_{j}=\begin{cases}y_{1}&\text{if }1\leq j\leq\ell,\\ y_{2}&\text{if }\ell+1\leq j\leq 2\ell,\\ \vdots&\vdots\\ y_{k-1}&\text{if }(k-2)\ell+1\leq j\leq(k-1)\ell,\\ y_{k}=1&\text{if }(k-1)\ell+1\leq j\leq n.\end{cases}

We show that 𝐑¯\overline{\mathbf{R}} is a subalgebra of 𝐏Łn×𝐏Łn\mathbf{P\text{\bf\L}}_{n}\times\mathbf{P\text{\bf\L}}_{n} using Proposition 3.12(2). That is, for any j1,j2{1,,n1}j_{1},j_{2}\in\{1,\dots,n-1\}, we want to show that (j1n,y^j1)(j2n,y^j2)𝐑¯(\frac{j_{1}}{n},\hat{y}_{j_{1}})\ast(\frac{j_{2}}{n},\hat{y}_{j_{2}})\in\overline{\mathbf{R}} holds for the 𝖬𝖵\mathsf{MV}-operations {,}\ast\in\{\odot,\oplus\}.

Let i1,i2{1,,k}i_{1},i_{2}\in\{1,\dots,k\} be the unique elements satisfying

(i11)<j1i1 and (i21)<j2i2,(i_{1}-1)\ell<j_{1}\leq i_{1}\ell\text{ and }(i_{2}-1)\ell<j_{2}\leq i_{2}\ell,

which by definition means y^j1=yi1\hat{y}_{j_{1}}=y_{i_{1}} and y^j2=yi2\hat{y}_{j_{2}}=y_{i_{2}}. Since 𝐑\mathbf{R} is a subalgebra, we know that (i1k,yi1)(i2k,yi2)𝐑(\frac{i_{1}}{k},y_{i_{1}})\ast(\frac{i_{2}}{k},y_{i_{2}})\in\mathbf{R}, say it is in C(hk,yh),𝐒C_{(\frac{h}{k},y_{h}),\mathbf{S}}. Now because j1ni1n=i1k\frac{j_{1}}{n}\leq\frac{i_{1}\ell}{n}=\frac{i_{1}}{k} and similarly for j2,i2j_{2},i_{2}, we have

j1nj2ni1ki2khk=hn\frac{j_{1}}{n}\ast\frac{j_{2}}{n}\leq\frac{i_{1}}{k}\ast\frac{i_{2}}{k}\leq\frac{h}{k}=\frac{h\ell}{n}

and furthermore

yhyi1yi2=y^j1y^j2.y_{h}\leq y_{i_{1}}\ast y_{i_{2}}=\hat{y}_{j_{1}}\ast\hat{y}_{j_{2}}.

Because y^h=yh\hat{y}_{h\ell}=y_{h}, this shows that (j1n,y^j1)(j2n,y^j2)C(hn,y^h)𝐑¯(\frac{j_{1}}{n},\hat{y}_{j_{1}})\ast(\frac{j_{2}}{n},\hat{y}_{j_{2}})\in C_{(\frac{h\ell}{n},\hat{y}_{h\ell})}\subseteq\overline{\mathbf{R}}, finishing the proof. ∎

Our second lemma shows that the collection 𝕊(𝐏Łn)\mathbb{S}(\mathbf{P\text{\bf\L}}_{n}) is strongly entailed by 𝒮n\mathcal{S}_{n}.

Lemma 3.15.

For every 𝐏Łk𝕊(𝐏Łn)\mathbf{P\text{\bf\L}}_{k}\in\mathbb{S}(\mathbf{P\text{\bf\L}}_{n}), there exists a 𝐑𝒮n\mathbf{R}\in\mathcal{S}_{n} such that 𝐑Δ𝐏Łn=Δ𝐏Łk\mathbf{R}\cap\Delta_{\mathbf{P\text{\bf\L}}_{n}}=\Delta_{\mathbf{P\text{\bf\L}}_{k}} (where Δ𝐀\Delta_{\mathbf{A}} denotes the diagonal of the corresponding algebra 𝐀\mathbf{A}).

Proof.

Let n=kn=k\cdot\ell and 𝐏Łk\mathbf{P\text{\bf\L}}_{k} be given as in Proposition 3.2. We define 𝐑\mathbf{R} by

𝐑=i=0nC(in,yi)\mathbf{R}=\bigcup_{i=0}^{n}C_{(\frac{i}{n},y_{i})}

where we stipulate y0=0y_{0}=0 and

yi={nif 1j,2nif +1j2,(k1)nif (k2)+1j(k1),1if (k1)+1jn.y_{i}=\begin{cases}\frac{\ell}{n}&\text{if }1\leq j\leq\ell,\\ \frac{2\ell}{n}&\text{if }\ell+1\leq j\leq 2\ell,\\ \vdots&\vdots\\ \frac{(k-1)\ell}{n}&\text{if }(k-2)\ell+1\leq j\leq(k-1)\ell,\\ 1&\text{if }(k-1)\ell+1\leq j\leq n.\end{cases}

By definition it is clear that 𝐑Δ𝐏Łn=Δ𝐏Łk\mathbf{R}\cap\Delta_{\mathbf{P\text{\bf\L}}_{n}}=\Delta_{\mathbf{P\text{\bf\L}}_{k}}, so we only have to show that 𝐑\mathbf{R} is a subalgebra. For this, we again use Proposition3.12(2). Let i1,i2{1,,n1}i_{1},i_{2}\in\{1,\dots,n-1\} and let j1,j2j_{1},j_{2} be the unique elements of {1,,k}\{1,\dots,k\} with

(j11)<i1j1 and (j21)<i2j2,(j_{1}-1)\ell<i_{1}\leq j_{1}\ell\text{ and }(j_{2}-1)\ell<i_{2}\leq j_{2}\ell,

which means that yi1=j1ny_{i_{1}}=\frac{j_{1}\ell}{n} and yi2=j2ny_{i_{2}}=\frac{j_{2}\ell}{n}. Furthermore, let j1nj2n=hn\frac{j_{1}\ell}{n}\ast\frac{j_{2}\ell}{n}=\frac{h\ell}{n} (note that such an hh exists because 𝐏Łk\mathbf{P\text{\bf\L}}_{k} is a subalgebra). Then

i1ni2nj1nj2n=hn\frac{i_{1}}{n}\ast\frac{i_{2}}{n}\leq\frac{j_{1}\ell}{n}\ast\frac{j_{2}\ell}{n}=\frac{h\ell}{n}

implies

(i1n,yi2)(i2n,yi2)C(hn,hn)𝐑,(\tfrac{i_{1}}{n},y_{i_{2}})\ast(\tfrac{i_{2}}{n},y_{i_{2}})\in C_{(\frac{h\ell}{n},\frac{h\ell}{n})}\subseteq\mathbf{R},

which finishes the proof. ∎

With these two lemmas at hand, we are ready to state and easily prove the main theorem of this section.

Theorem 3.16.

Let n1n\geq 1. The discrete relational structure

𝐏Ł~n={0,1n,,n1n,1},𝒮n,𝒯dis\utilde{\mathbf{P\text{\bf\L}}}_{n}=\langle\{0,\tfrac{1}{n},\dots,\tfrac{n-1}{n},1\},\mathcal{S}_{n},\mathcal{T}_{\mathrm{dis}}\rangle

yields a strong duality for 𝖯𝖬𝖵n\mathsf{PMV}_{n}.

Proof.

By the discussion after Lemma 3.8, we know that the structure given in Equation (2), that is {0,1n,,n1n,1},𝕊(𝐏Łn)𝕊(),𝒯dis\langle\{0,\tfrac{1}{n},\dots,\tfrac{n-1}{n},1\},\mathbb{S}(\mathbf{P\text{\bf\L}}_{n})\cup\mathbb{S}(\leq),\mathcal{T}_{\mathrm{dis}}\rangle, yields a strong duality for 𝖯𝖬𝖵n\mathsf{PMV}_{n}. By Lemma 3.14, we know that every 𝐑𝕊()\mathbf{R}\in\mathbb{S}(\leq) is an intersection of (and thus strongly entailed by) a product of subalgebras of 𝐏Łn\mathbf{P\text{\bf\L}}_{n} and a relation from 𝒮n\mathcal{S}_{n}. By Lemma 3.15 subalgebras of 𝐏Łn\mathbf{P\text{\bf\L}}_{n} are strongly entailed by 𝒮n\mathcal{S}_{n} as well. ∎

In light of Proposition 3.12, it is fairly straightforward to find the lattice 𝒮n\mathcal{S}_{n} in a systematic way. Indeed, in Appendix A we provide an easy algorithm to compute this lattice. Also note that, to obtain an optimal duality (see [8, Chapters 8 and 9]), we could simplify the above structure further by only including meet-irreducible elements of 𝒮n\mathcal{S}_{n} (this follows from [8, Theorem 9.2.6]). However, since it won’t make a significant difference in this paper, we keep working with the alter ego from Theorem 3.16.

Definition 3.17.

For all n1n\geq 1, let 𝒳n\mathcal{X}_{n} be the topological quasi-variety 𝕀𝕊c+(𝐏Ł~n)\mathbb{I}\mathbb{S}_{c}\mathbb{P}^{+}(\utilde{\mathbf{P\text{\bf\L}}}_{n}) generated by the structure from Theorem 3.16. Furthermore, let 𝖣n:𝖯𝖬𝖵n𝒳n\mathsf{D}_{n}\colon\mathsf{PMV}_{n}\to\mathcal{X}_{n} and 𝖤n:𝒳n𝖯𝖬𝖵n\mathsf{E}_{n}\colon\mathcal{X}_{n}\to\mathsf{PMV}_{n} be the (hom-)functors establishing the corresponding dual equivalence.

Note that these dualities can be seen as many-valued generalizations of Priestley duality, which is recovered in the case where n=1n=1.

In the following, we collect some consequences of Theorem 3.16 which can be immediately derived from the general theory of natural dualities.

Corollary 3.18.

The categories 𝖯𝖬𝖵n\mathsf{PMV}_{n} and 𝒳n\mathcal{X}_{n} have the following properties.

  1. (1)

    𝐏Łn\mathbf{P\text{\bf\L}}_{n} is injective in 𝖯𝖬𝖵n\mathsf{PMV}_{n} and 𝐏Ł~n\utilde{\mathbf{P\text{\bf\L}}}_{n} is injective in 𝒳n\mathcal{X}_{n}.

  2. (2)

    The injectives in 𝖯𝖬𝖵n\mathsf{PMV}_{n} are exactly the Boolean powers 𝐏Łn[𝐁]\mathbf{P\text{\bf\L}}_{n}[\mathbf{B}], where 𝐁\mathbf{B} is a non-trivial complete Boolean algebra.

  3. (3)

    𝖯𝖬𝖵n\mathsf{PMV}_{n} has the amalgamation property.

  4. (4)

    A morphism φ:𝐗1𝐗2\varphi\colon\mathbf{X}_{1}\to\mathbf{X}_{2} in 𝒳n\mathcal{X}_{n} is an embedding (a surjection) if and only if 𝖤n(φ)\mathsf{E}_{n}(\varphi) is a surjection (an embedding). A homomorphism h:𝐀1𝐀2h\colon\mathbf{A}_{1}\to\mathbf{A}_{2} in 𝖯𝖬𝖵n\mathsf{PMV}_{n} is an embedding (a surjection) if and only if 𝖣n(h)\mathsf{D}_{n}(h) is a surjection (an embedding).

  5. (5)

    The congruence lattice of 𝐀𝖯𝖬𝖵n\mathbf{A}\in\mathsf{PMV}_{n} is dually isomorphic to the lattice of closed substructures of 𝖣n(𝐀)\mathsf{D}_{n}(\mathbf{A}).

  6. (6)

    Coproducts in 𝒳n\mathcal{X}_{n} are given by direct union (i.e., the duality is logarithmic).

Proof.

The second part of statement (1) follows from the definition of strong duality, the first part follows from [8, Lemma 3.2.10] and the fact that 𝐏Ł~n\utilde{\mathbf{P\text{\bf\L}}}_{n} is a total structure. Statement (2) follows from [8, Theorem 5.5.15] because all relations 𝐑𝒮n\mathbf{R}\in\mathcal{S}_{n} avoid binary products. Statement (3) follows from [8, Lemma 5.3.4]. Statement (4) follows from (1) and [8, Lemmas 3.2.6 and 3.2.8]. Statement (5) follows from [8, Theorem 3.2.1]. Lastly, statement (6) follows from [8, Theorem 6.3.3]. ∎

This corollary already demonstrates how useful these dualities are. In the next section, we investigate it further to derive more results about the varieties 𝖯𝖬𝖵n\mathsf{PMV}_{n}.

4. Further explorations of the dualities

In this section, we delve deeper into various aspects of the natural dualities established in the previous section. In Subsection 4.1, we give a concrete axiomatization of the category 𝒳2\mathcal{X}_{2} dual to the variety 𝖯𝖬𝖵2\mathsf{PMV}_{2} generated by the three-element positive 𝖬𝖵\mathsf{MV}-chain. In Subsection 4.2, we explore the relationship between the natural duality for 𝖯𝖬𝖵n\mathsf{PMV}_{n} and Priestley duality. Lastly, in Subsection 4.3, we give complete characterizations of algebraically and existentially closed algebras in 𝖯𝖬𝖵n\mathsf{PMV}_{n}.

4.1. The dual category for the three-element positive MV-chain.

Among the finitely-valued Łukasiewicz logics, arguably the most popular is the three-valued logic corresponding to the variety 𝖬𝖵2\mathsf{MV}_{2} generated by the three-element 𝖬𝖵\mathsf{MV}-chain Ł2\text{\bf\L}_{2}. In this section, we focus on the variety 𝖯𝖬𝖵2\mathsf{PMV}_{2} generated by the positive three-element 𝖬𝖵\mathsf{MV}-chain 𝐏Ł2\mathbf{P\text{\bf\L}}_{2}. More specifically, we provide an explicit description of the category 𝒳2\mathcal{X}_{2} dual to 𝖯𝖬𝖵2\mathsf{PMV}_{2}.

Theorem 4.1.

A structured Stone space 𝐗=X,𝐗,𝐗,𝒯\mathbf{X}=\langle X,\lhd^{\mathbf{X}},\leq^{\mathbf{X}},\mathcal{T}\rangle with binary relations 𝐗\lhd^{\mathbf{X}} and 𝐗\leq^{\mathbf{X}} closed in X2X^{2} is a member of 𝒳2\mathcal{X}_{2} if and only if it satisfies the following axioms.

  1. (a)

    x𝐗yx𝐗yx\lhd^{\mathbf{X}}y\Rightarrow x\leq^{\mathbf{X}}y.

  2. (b)

    (X,𝐗,𝒯)(X,\leq^{\mathbf{X}},\mathcal{T}) is a Priestley space, that is, 𝐗\leq^{\mathbf{X}} is a partial order and if x𝐗yx\not\leq^{\mathbf{X}}y, then there exists a clopen upset UU containing xx but not yy.

  3. (c)

    If x𝐗yx\ntriangleleft^{\mathbf{X}}y but x𝐗yx\leq^{\mathbf{X}}y, then there exist a clopen upset UU and a clopen downset DD with the following properties

    • xDx\notin D and yUy\notin U,

    • For all z,zXz,z^{\prime}\in X, if z𝐗zz\lhd^{\mathbf{X}}z^{\prime} then zDz\in D or zUz^{\prime}\in U.

Proof.

First we show that every member 𝐗=X,𝐗,𝐗,𝒯\mathbf{X}=\langle X,\lhd^{\mathbf{X}},\leq^{\mathbf{X}},\mathcal{T}\rangle of 𝒳2\mathcal{X}_{2} satisfies (a)-(c). The formula (a) is quasi-atomic and holds in 𝐏Łn\mathbf{P\text{\bf\L}}_{n}, therefore, by the Preservation Theorem [8, Theorem 1.4.3], it also holds for all members of 𝒳2\mathcal{X}_{2}.

To see condition (b) that (X,𝐗,𝒯)(X,\leq^{\mathbf{X}},\mathcal{T}) is a Priestley space, assume that x𝐗yx\not\leq\mathbf{X}y. By the Separation Theorem [8, Theorem 1.4.4], there exists a 𝒳2\mathcal{X}_{2}-morphism φ:𝐗𝐏Ł~2\varphi\colon\mathbf{X}\to\utilde{\mathbf{P\text{\bf\L}}}_{2} with φ(x)>φ(y)\varphi(x)>\varphi(y). If φ(x)=1\varphi(x)=1, choose U=φ1({1})U=\varphi^{-1}(\{1\}) and if φ(x)=12\varphi(x)=\frac{1}{2}, choose U=φ1{12}φ1({1})U=\varphi^{-1}{\{\frac{1}{2}\}}\cup\varphi^{-1}(\{1\}). In both cases, UU is a clopen (because 𝐏Ł2\mathbf{P\text{\bf\L}}_{2} carries the discrete topology and φ\varphi is continuous) upset (because φ\varphi is order-preserving) which contains xx but not yy.

To see (c), assume x𝐗yx\ntriangleleft^{\mathbf{X}}y but x𝐗yx\leq^{\mathbf{X}}y. Then, again by the Separation Theorem, there exists a morphism φ:𝐗𝐏Ł~2\varphi\colon\mathbf{X}\to\utilde{\mathbf{P\text{\bf\L}}}_{2} with φ(x)φ(y)\varphi(x)\ntriangleleft\varphi(y) but φ(x)φ(y)\varphi(x)\leq\varphi(y). Since ={(12,12)}\lhd={\leq}{\setminus}\{(\frac{1}{2},\frac{1}{2})\}, this implies φ(x)=φ(y)=12\varphi(x)=\varphi(y)=\frac{1}{2}. The clopen upset U=φ1({1})U=\varphi^{-1}(\{1\}) and the clopen downset D=φ1({0})D=\varphi^{-1}(\{0\}) satisfy the two subconditions of (c), the first one since φ(x)=φ(y)=12\varphi(x)=\varphi(y)=\frac{1}{2} and the second one since z𝐗zz\lhd\mathbf{X}z^{\prime} and φ(z)=φ(z)=12\varphi(z)=\varphi(z^{\prime})=\frac{1}{2} would yield a contradiction φ(z)φ(z)\varphi(z)\ntriangleleft\varphi(z^{\prime}) to φ\varphi being a morphism.

For the converse, assuming that 𝐗=(X,𝐗,𝐗,𝒯)\mathbf{X}=(X,\lhd^{\mathbf{X}},\leq^{\mathbf{X}},\mathcal{T}) satisfies (a)-(c), we want to show that it is a member of 𝒳2\mathcal{X}_{2}. We apply the Separation Theorem again.

Suppose x𝐗yx\not\leq^{\mathbf{X}}y. Using that (X,𝐗,𝒯)(X,\leq^{\mathbf{X}},\mathcal{T}) is a Priestley space, we can find a clopen upset UU which contains xx but not yy. We define a continuous map φ:X{0,12,1}\varphi\colon X\to\{0,\frac{1}{2},1\} by φ(z)=1\varphi(z)=1 if zUz\in U and f(z)=0f(z)=0 otherwise. This clearly is order-preserving, and it also preserves \lhd, because \lhd is a subset of \leq by (a) and, in 𝐏Ł~2\utilde{\mathbf{P\text{\bf\L}}}_{2} the relations \lhd and \leq coincide on the subset {0,1}\{0,1\}. Clearly this morphism satisfies φ(x)φ(y)\varphi(x)\not\leq\varphi(y).

In particular, the above covers the case where xyx\neq y and the case where x𝐗yx\ntriangleleft^{\mathbf{X}}y and x𝐗yx\not\leq^{\mathbf{X}}y hold. Now assume x𝐗yx\ntriangleleft^{\mathbf{X}}{y} but x𝐗yx\leq^{\mathbf{X}}y. Take a clopen upset UU and a clopen downset DD as given in (c). Replacing UU by the clopen upset U:=UDU^{\prime}:=U{\setminus}D, the properties of (c) are still satisfied, since z𝐗zz\lhd^{\mathbf{X}}z^{\prime} and zDz\notin D imply zUz^{\prime}\in U, and zDz^{\prime}\in D would yield the contradiction zDz\in D, so zUz^{\prime}\in U^{\prime}. Let the continuous map φ:X{0,12,1}\varphi\colon X\to\{0,\frac{1}{2},1\} be defined via

φ(z)={0if zD,1if zU,12if zX(DU).\varphi(z)=\begin{cases}0&\text{if }z\in D,\\ 1&\text{if }z\in U^{\prime},\\ \frac{1}{2}&\text{if }z\in X{\setminus}(D\cup U^{\prime}).\end{cases}

This is a well-defined continuous map since DD, UU^{\prime} and X(DC)X{\setminus}(D\cup C) forms a clopen partition of XX. Furthermore, since xDx\notin D (which implies yDy\notin D) and yUy\notin U (which implies xUx\notin U) implies φ(x)=φ(y)=12\varphi(x)=\varphi(y)=\frac{1}{2} (i.e., φ(x)φ(y)\varphi(x)\ntriangleleft\varphi(y)), it remains to be shown that φ\varphi preserves \leq and \lhd. Order-preservation follows immediately from the fact that UU is an upset and DD is a downset. Now suppose z𝐗zz\lhd^{\mathbf{X}}z^{\prime}. Then zDz\in D, which implies φ(z)=0\varphi(z)=0 holds, or zUz^{\prime}\in U^{\prime}, which implies φ(z)=1\varphi(z^{\prime})=1 holds. In both cases, φ(z)φ(z)\varphi(z)\lhd\varphi(z^{\prime}) is assured. ∎

In the next subsection, we give a similar but more ‘implicit’ axiomatization of the categories 𝒳n\mathcal{X}_{n} for n>2n>2 as well. Since (as we’ve already seen in the case n=2n=2) all structures 𝐗𝒳n\mathbf{X}\in\mathcal{X}_{n} have underlying Priestley spaces, we then proceed to explore various functors relating our natural dualities to Priestley duality.

4.2. The relationship to Priestley duality

We continue to denote the functors establishing the duality from Theorem 3.16 by 𝖣n:𝖯𝖬𝖵n𝒳n\mathsf{D}_{n}\colon\mathsf{PMV}_{n}\to\mathcal{X}_{n} and 𝖤n:𝒳n𝖯𝖬𝖵n\mathsf{E}_{n}\colon\mathcal{X}_{n}\to\mathsf{PMV}_{n}. In particular, for n=1n=1 this coincides with Priestley duality between the variety of distributive lattices 𝖣𝖫=𝖯𝖬𝖵1\mathsf{DL}=\mathsf{PMV}_{1} and the category of Priestley spaces 𝖯𝗋𝗂𝖾𝗌𝗍=𝒳1\mathsf{Priest}=\mathcal{X}_{1}. In this case, we simply use 𝖣:𝖣𝖫𝖯𝗋𝗂𝖾𝗌𝗍\mathsf{D}\colon\mathsf{DL}\to\mathsf{Priest} and 𝖤:𝖯𝗋𝗂𝖾𝗌𝗍𝖣𝖫\mathsf{E}\colon\mathsf{Priest}\to\mathsf{DL} instead of 𝖣1\mathsf{D}_{1} and 𝖤1\mathsf{E}_{1}.

In this subsection, we show that there are functors 𝔖:𝖯𝖬𝖵n𝖣𝖫\mathfrak{S}\colon\mathsf{PMV}_{n}\to\mathsf{DL} taking the distributive skeleton and 𝔓:𝖣𝖫𝖯𝖬𝖵n\mathfrak{P}\colon\mathsf{DL}\to\mathsf{PMV}_{n} taking a Priestley power with 𝔖\mathfrak{S} being left-adjoint to 𝔓\mathfrak{P}. This is similar to the adjunction between the Boolean skeleton functor 𝖬𝖵n𝖡𝖠\mathsf{MV}_{n}\to\mathsf{BA} and the Boolean power functor 𝖡𝖠𝖬𝖵n\mathsf{BA}\to\mathsf{MV}_{n} (which exists for any variety generated by a semi-primal lattice extension) from [17, Section 4].

While, in theory, the Separation Theorem [8, Theorem 1.4.3] always gives an ‘implicit’ description of the dual categories, the reader can imagine that for n>2n>2, it gets increasingly complicated to come up with more ‘explicit’ descriptions of the categories 𝒳n\mathcal{X}_{n} similar to Theorem 4.1. Therefore, in these cases we content ourselves with the following.

Proposition 4.2.

A structured Stone space 𝐗=X,(𝐑𝐗𝐑𝒮n),𝒯\mathbf{X}=\langle X,(\mathbf{R}^{\mathbf{X}}\mid\mathbf{R}\in\mathcal{S}_{n}),\mathcal{T}\rangle with closed binary relations 𝐑𝐗\mathbf{R}^{\mathbf{X}} is a member of 𝒳n\mathcal{X}_{n} if and only if it satisfies the following:

  1. (a)

    x𝐑1𝐗yx𝐑2𝐗yx\mathbf{R}_{1}^{\mathbf{X}}y\Rightarrow x\mathbf{R}_{2}^{\mathbf{X}}y for all 𝐑1𝐑2\mathbf{R}_{1}\subseteq\mathbf{R}_{2} in 𝒮n\mathcal{S}_{n}.

  2. (b)

    X,𝐗,𝒯\langle X,\leq^{\mathbf{X}},\mathcal{T}\rangle is a Priestley space.

  3. (c)

    For all 𝐑𝒮n{}\mathbf{R}\in\mathcal{S}_{n}{\setminus}\{\leq\}, if (x,y)𝐑𝐗(x,y)\notin\mathbf{R}^{\mathbf{X}}, then there is a structure-preserving continuous map φ:𝐗𝐏Ł~n\varphi\colon\mathbf{X}\to\utilde{\mathbf{P\text{\bf\L}}}_{n} with (φ(x),φ(y))𝐑(\varphi(x),\varphi(y))\notin\mathbf{R}.

Proof.

Every member 𝐗\mathbf{X} of 𝒳n\mathcal{X}_{n} satisfies the quasi-atomic formulas from (a). Furthermore, both (b) and (c) are immediate consequences of the Separation Theorem. To see that X,𝐗,𝒯\langle X,\leq^{\mathbf{X}},\mathcal{T}\rangle is a Priestley space), assume x𝐗yx\not\leq^{\mathbf{X}}y. By the Separation Theorem there is a morphism φ:𝐗𝐏Ł~n\varphi\colon\mathbf{X}\to\utilde{\mathbf{P\text{\bf\L}}}_{n} with φ(x)φ(y)\varphi(x)\not\leq\varphi(y). Let φ(x)=in\varphi(x)=\frac{i}{n}. Then U=φ1({1n})φ1({i+1n})φ1({n1n})φ1({1})U=\varphi^{-1}(\{\frac{1}{n}\})\cup\varphi^{-1}(\{\frac{i+1}{n}\})\cup\dots\cup\varphi^{-1}(\{\frac{n-1}{n}\})\cup\varphi^{-1}(\{1\}) is a clopen upset which contains xx but not yy. The converse is also a straightforward application of the Separation Theorem. ∎

Therefore, there always is a forgetful functor 𝖴:𝒳n𝖯𝗋𝗂𝖾𝗌𝗍\mathsf{U}\colon\mathcal{X}_{n}\to\mathsf{Priest} sending an object of 𝒳n\mathcal{X}_{n} to its underlying Priestley space and a 𝒳n\mathcal{X}_{n}-morphism to itself. In the following, we show that the dual of 𝖴\mathsf{U} is given by the distributive skeleton functor 𝔖:𝖯𝖬𝖵n𝖣𝖫\mathfrak{S}\colon\mathsf{PMV}_{n}\to\mathsf{DL}. This is similar to the Boolean skeleton functor 𝖬𝖵n𝖡𝖠\mathsf{MV}_{n}\to\mathsf{BA}, which is dual to the corresponding forgetful functor from the category dual to 𝖬𝖵n\mathsf{MV}_{n} to 𝖲𝗍𝗈𝗇𝖾\mathsf{Stone} [17, Subsection 4.2]. The distributive skeleton of a 𝖯𝖬𝖵n\mathsf{PMV}_{n} algebra is defined completely analogous to the Boolean skeleton of an 𝖬𝖵n\mathsf{MV}_{n} algebra (see, e.g., [7, Section 1.5].

Definition 4.3.

Let 𝐀𝖯𝖬𝖵n\mathbf{A}\in\mathsf{PMV}_{n}. The distributive skeleton of 𝐀\mathbf{A} is the bounded distributive lattice

𝔖(𝐀)=𝔖(A),,,0,1\mathfrak{S}({\mathbf{A}})=\langle\mathfrak{S}(A),\wedge,\vee,0,1\rangle

defined on the carrier set 𝔖(A)={aAaa=a}\mathfrak{S}(A)=\{a\in A\mid a\oplus a=a\}, with the operations ,\wedge,\vee and constants 0,10,1 inherited from 𝐀\mathbf{A}.

To turn this into a functor 𝔖:𝖯𝖬𝖵n𝖣𝖫\mathfrak{S}\colon\mathsf{PMV}_{n}\to\mathsf{DL}, for a homomorphism h:𝐀𝐀h\colon\mathbf{A}\to\mathbf{A}^{\prime} between 𝖯𝖬𝖵n\mathsf{PMV}_{n}-algebras, simply define the homomorphism 𝔖h:𝔖(𝐀)𝔖(𝐀)\mathfrak{S}h\colon\mathfrak{S}(\mathbf{A})\to\mathfrak{S}(\mathbf{A}^{\prime}) by restriction 𝔖h=h𝔖(𝐀)\mathfrak{S}h=h{\mid}_{\mathfrak{S}(\mathbf{A})}.

Theorem 4.4.

The functor 𝔖:𝖯𝖬𝖵n𝖣𝖫\mathfrak{S}\colon\mathsf{PMV}_{n}\to\mathsf{DL} is dual to the functor 𝖴:𝒳n𝖯𝗋𝗂𝖾𝗌𝗍\mathsf{U}\colon\mathcal{X}_{n}\to\mathsf{Priest}, that is, 𝖣𝔖\mathsf{D}\mathfrak{S} is naturally isomorphic to 𝖴𝖣n\mathsf{U}\mathsf{D}_{n}.

Proof.

By definition, natural in the choice of 𝐀𝖯𝖬𝖵n\mathbf{A}\in\mathsf{PMV}_{n}, we want to find an order-preserving homeomorphism

Φ𝐀:(𝖯𝖬𝖵n(𝐀,𝐏Łn),)(𝖣𝖫(𝔖(𝐀),𝟐),),\Phi_{\mathbf{A}}\colon(\mathsf{PMV}_{n}(\mathbf{A},\mathbf{P\text{\bf\L}}_{n}),\leq)\to(\mathsf{DL}(\mathfrak{S}(\mathbf{A}),\mathbf{2}),\leq),

where 𝟐\mathbf{2} denotes the two-element distributive lattice. We claim that

Φ𝐀(u)=u𝔖(𝐀)\Phi_{\mathbf{A}}(u)=u{\mid}_{\mathfrak{S}(\mathbf{A})}

has these desired properties.

To see that Φ𝐀\Phi_{\mathbf{A}} is injective, suppose that uuu\neq u^{\prime} are two distinct homomorphisms 𝐀𝐏Łn\mathbf{A}\to\mathbf{P\text{\bf\L}}_{n}. Let a𝐀a\in\mathbf{A} be such that u(a)u(a)u(a)\neq u^{\prime}(a), without loss of generality say u(a)<u(a)u(a)<u^{\prime}(a). Then, for d=u(a)d=u^{\prime}(a), we have u(τd(a))=τd(u(a))=0u(\tau_{d}(a))=\tau_{d}(u(a))=0 and u(τd(a))=τd(u(a))=1u^{\prime}(\tau_{d}(a))=\tau_{d}(u^{\prime}(a))=1. Since τd(a)𝔖(𝐀)\tau_{d}(a)\in\mathfrak{S}(\mathbf{A}) holds, this shows that Φ(u)Φ(u)\Phi(u)\neq\Phi(u^{\prime}).

Now we show that Φ\Phi is surjective. Let p:𝔖(𝐀)𝟐p\colon\mathfrak{S}(\mathbf{A})\to\mathbf{2} be a homomorphism. We construct a homomorphism up:𝐀𝐏Łnu_{p}\colon\mathbf{A}\to\mathbf{P\text{\bf\L}}_{n} with Φ𝐀(up)=p\Phi_{\mathbf{A}}(u_{p})=p. Given a𝐀a\in\mathbf{A}, define

up(a)={dp(τd(a))=1}.u_{p}(a)=\bigvee\{d\mid p(\tau_{d}(a))=1\}.

Clearly upu_{p} preserves 0 and 11. Now let a1,a2𝐀a_{1},a_{2}\in\mathbf{A}, let up(a1)=d1u_{p}(a_{1})=d_{1} and up(a2)=d2u_{p}(a_{2})=d_{2}. We want to show that, for {,,,}\ast\in\{\wedge,\vee,\odot,\oplus\}, up(a1a2)=d1d2u_{p}(a_{1}\ast a_{2})=d_{1}\ast d_{2}. In other words, we want to show that p(τd1d2(a1a2))=1p(\tau_{d_{1}\ast d_{2}}(a_{1}\ast a_{2}))=1 and p(τd(a1a2))=0p(\tau_{d^{\prime}}(a_{1}\ast a_{2}))=0 for all d>d1d2d^{\prime}>d_{1}\ast d_{2}. Since \ast is order-preserving we know that 𝐏Łn\mathbf{P\text{\bf\L}}_{n} satisfies

τd1(x1)τd2(x2)τd1d2(x1x2).\tau_{d_{1}}(x_{1})\wedge\tau_{d_{2}}(x_{2})\leq\tau_{d_{1}\ast d_{2}}(x_{1}\ast x_{2}).

Since this can be expressed as an equation, it also holds in 𝐀\mathbf{A}. Therefore, we get

1=p(τd1(a1)τd2(a2))p(τd1d2(a1a2)).1=p(\tau_{d_{1}}(a_{1})\ast\tau_{d_{2}}(a_{2}))\leq p(\tau_{d_{1}\ast d_{2}}(a_{1}\ast a_{2})).

Now let d>d1d2d^{\prime}>d_{1}\ast d_{2}. Then, since d1d21d_{1}\ast d_{2}\neq 1, we can choose minimal d1>d1d_{1}^{\prime}>d_{1} and d2d2d_{2}^{\prime}\geq d_{2} with d1d2dd_{1}^{\prime}\ast d_{2}^{\prime}\geq d^{\prime}. By minimality, 𝐏Łn\mathbf{P\text{\bf\L}}_{n} satisfies the equation corresponding to

τd1(x1)τd2(x2)τd(x1x2)τd1(x1),\tau_{d_{1}}(x_{1})\wedge\tau_{d_{2}}(x_{2})\wedge\tau_{d^{\prime}}(x_{1}\ast x_{2})\leq\tau_{d_{1}^{\prime}}(x_{1}),

which is therefore also satisfied in 𝐀\mathbf{A}. But now, if we assume that p(τd(a1a2))=1p(\tau_{d^{\prime}}(a_{1}\ast a_{2}))=1, then

1=p(τd1(a1)τd2(a2)τd(a1a2))p(τd1(a1))1=p(\tau_{d_{1}}(a_{1})\wedge\tau_{d_{2}}(a_{2})\wedge\tau_{d^{\prime}}(a_{1}\ast a_{2}))\leq p(\tau_{d_{1}^{\prime}}(a_{1}))

implies p(τd1(a1))=1p(\tau_{d^{\prime}_{1}}(a_{1}))=1, which is a contradiction to up(a1)=d1u_{p}(a_{1})=d_{1}. Therefore, upu_{p} is a homomorphism. The restriction of upu_{p} to 𝔖(𝐀)\mathfrak{S}(\mathbf{A}) is equal to pp because a𝔖(𝐀)a\in\mathfrak{S}(\mathbf{A}) is equivalent to τd(a)=a\tau_{d}(a)=a for all d𝐏Łn{0}d\in\mathbf{P\text{\bf\L}}_{n}{\setminus}\{0\}.

Thus we showed that Φ𝐀\Phi_{\mathbf{A}} is bijective. It is also continuous, and therefore a homeomorphism, since a subbasis of the topology on 𝖣1𝔖(𝐀)\mathsf{D}_{1}\mathfrak{S}(\mathbf{A}) is given by the sets of the form [a:e]={p:𝔖(𝐀)𝟐p(a)=e}[a:e]=\{p\colon\mathfrak{S}(\mathbf{A})\to\mathbf{2}\mid p(a)=e\} where aa ranges over 𝔖(𝐀)\mathfrak{S}(\mathbf{A}) and ee ranges over 𝟐\mathbf{2}. The preimage Φ1([a:e])\Phi^{-1}([a:e]) is exactly the corresponding subbase element [a:e]={h:𝐀𝐏Łnh(a)=e}[a:e]=\{h\colon\mathbf{A}\to\mathbf{P\text{\bf\L}}_{n}\mid h(a)=e\} of the topology on 𝖴𝖣n(𝐀)\mathsf{U}\mathsf{D}_{n}(\mathbf{A}). The fact that Φ𝐀\Phi_{\mathbf{A}} is order-preserving follows directly from its definition, so it only remains to show that Φ\Phi defines a natural transformation 𝖴𝖣n𝖣1𝔖\mathsf{U}\mathsf{D}_{n}\Rightarrow\mathsf{D}_{1}\mathfrak{S}. Let h:𝐀𝐀h\colon\mathbf{A}\to\mathbf{A}^{\prime} be a homomorphism. We need to show that the square

𝖯𝖬𝖵n(𝐀,𝐏Łn){\mathsf{PMV}_{n}(\mathbf{A^{\prime}},\mathbf{P\text{\bf\L}}_{n})}𝖣𝖫(𝔖(𝐀),𝟐){\mathsf{DL}(\mathfrak{S}(\mathbf{A^{\prime}}),\mathbf{2})}𝖯𝖬𝖵n(𝐀,𝐏Łn){\mathsf{PMV}_{n}(\mathbf{A},\mathbf{P\text{\bf\L}}_{n})}𝖣𝖫(𝔖(𝐀),𝟐){\mathsf{DL}(\mathfrak{S}(\mathbf{A^{\prime}}),\mathbf{2})}Φ𝐀\scriptstyle{\Phi_{\mathbf{A}^{\prime}}}𝖴𝖣nh\scriptstyle{\mathsf{UD}_{n}h}𝖣1𝔖h\scriptstyle{\mathsf{D}_{1}\mathfrak{S}h}Φ𝐀\scriptstyle{\Phi_{\mathbf{A}}}

commutes. By definition, for a homomorphism u:𝐀𝐏Łnu\colon\mathbf{A}^{\prime}\to\mathbf{P\text{\bf\L}}_{n} we have

Φ𝐀𝖴𝖣nh(u)=Φ𝐀(uh)=(uh)𝔖(𝐀)\Phi_{\mathbf{A}}\circ\mathsf{U}\mathsf{D}_{n}h(u)=\Phi_{\mathbf{A}}(u\circ h)=(u\circ h){\mid}_{\mathfrak{S}(\mathbf{A})}

and

𝖣1𝔖hΦ𝐀(u)=𝖣𝟣𝔖h(u𝔖𝐀)=u𝔖(𝐀)h𝔖(𝐀),\mathsf{D}_{1}\mathfrak{S}h\circ\Phi_{\mathbf{A}^{\prime}}(u)=\mathsf{D_{1}}\mathfrak{S}h(u{\mid}_{\mathfrak{S}}{\mathbf{A^{\prime}}})=u{\mid}_{\mathfrak{S}(\mathbf{A^{\prime}})}\circ h{\mid}_{\mathfrak{S}(\mathbf{A})},

which makes it easy to see that these two coincide, finishing the proof. ∎

The Boolean skeleton functor 𝖬𝖵n𝖡𝖠\mathsf{MV}_{n}\to\mathsf{BA} has a right-adjoint [17, Subsection 4.3], which takes a Boolean algebra 𝐁\mathbf{B} to the Boolean power Łn[𝐁]\text{\bf\L}_{n}[\mathbf{B}] (see, e.g., [4, 5] for information about Boolean powers). In the following we show that, similarly, the distributive skeleton functor has a right-adjoint, which takes the Priestley power defined as follows.

Definition 4.5.

Let 𝐋𝖣𝖫\mathbf{L}\in\mathsf{DL} be a distributive lattice and let 𝐌\mathbf{M} be a finite ordered algebra. The Priestley power, 𝐌[𝐋]\mathbf{M}[\mathbf{L}], is given by the collection

𝐌[𝐋]=𝖯𝗋𝗂𝖾𝗌𝗍(𝖣(𝐋),(M,,𝒯dis))\mathbf{M}[\mathbf{L}]=\mathsf{Priest}(\mathsf{D}(\mathbf{L}),(M,\leq,\mathcal{T}_{\mathrm{dis}}))

of continuous order-preserving maps from the dual of 𝐋\mathbf{L} to the discrete Priestley space (M,,𝒯dis)(M,\leq,\mathcal{T}_{\mathrm{dis}}).

A more constructive defintion of Priestley powers is given and shown to be equivalent to the above definition in [18] (where they are called distributive extensions). We also emphasize that our notion of Priestley power differs from the one established in [15].

Similarly to the Boolean power (but with the constraint that all operations of 𝐌\mathbf{M} need to be order-preserving), we get the following.

Lemma 4.6.

Let 𝐌\mathbf{M} be a finite ordered algebra, all of whose operations are order-preserving. Then, for every distributive lattice 𝐋𝖣𝖫\mathbf{L}\in\mathsf{DL}, the Priestley power 𝐌[𝐋]\mathbf{M}[\mathbf{L}] with component-wise operations is a subalgebra of 𝐌𝖣(𝐋)\mathbf{M}^{\mathsf{D}(\mathbf{L})}.

Proof.

Let ff be an nn-ary operation of 𝐌\mathbf{M} and let α1,,αn𝐌[𝐋]\alpha_{1},\dots,\alpha_{n}\in\mathbf{M}[\mathbf{L}]. We need to show that α:𝖣(𝐋)M\alpha\colon\mathsf{D}(\mathbf{L})\to M defined by α(x)=f(α1(x),,αn(x))\alpha(x)=f(\alpha_{1}(x),\dots,\alpha_{n}(x)) is continuous and order-preserving. Order-preservation is easy, since if xyx\leq y we know that αi(x)αi(y)\alpha_{i}(x)\leq\alpha_{i}(y) for all ii and since ff is order-preserving we have

α(x)=f(α1(x),,αn(x))f(α1(y),,αn(y))α(y).\alpha(x)=f(\alpha_{1}(x),\dots,\alpha_{n}(x))\leq f(\alpha_{1}(y),\dots,\alpha_{n}(y))\leq\alpha(y).

To see that α\alpha is continuous, we show that α1({m})\alpha^{-1}(\{m\}) is clopen for every mMm\in M. Let NMnN\subseteq M^{n} be the finite set of tuples (m1,,mn)(m_{1},\dots,m_{n}) with f(m1,,mn)=mf(m_{1},\dots,m_{n})=m. Then we have

α1({m})=(m1,,mn)Nα11({m1})αn1({mn}),\alpha^{-1}(\{m\})=\bigcup_{(m_{1},\dots,m_{n})\in N}\alpha_{1}^{-1}(\{m_{1}\})\cap\dots\cap\alpha_{n}^{-1}(\{m_{n}\}),

which is clopen because NN is finite and all αi\alpha_{i} are continuous. ∎

Therefore, it is easily seen that the following Priestly power functor 𝔓:𝖣𝖫𝖯𝖬𝖵n\mathfrak{P}\colon\mathsf{DL}\to\mathsf{PMV}_{n} is well-defined. For a distributive lattice 𝐋𝖣𝖫\mathbf{L}\in\mathsf{DL} let 𝔓(𝐋)=𝐏Łn[𝐋]\mathfrak{P}(\mathbf{L})=\mathbf{P\text{\bf\L}}_{n}[\mathbf{L}] be the Priestley power, and for a homomorphism h:𝐋1𝐋2h\colon\mathbf{L}_{1}\to\mathbf{L}_{2} let 𝔓h:𝔓(𝐋1)𝔓(𝐋2)\mathfrak{P}h\colon\mathfrak{P}(\mathbf{L}_{1})\to\mathfrak{P}(\mathbf{L}_{2}) be defined by αα𝖣h\alpha\mapsto\alpha\circ\mathsf{D}h. We now show by duality that this functor is right-adjoint to the distributive skeleton functor.

Theorem 4.7.

The Priestley power functor 𝔓:𝖣𝖫𝖯𝖬𝖵n\mathfrak{P}\colon\mathsf{DL}\to\mathsf{PMV}_{n} is right-adjoint to the distributive skeleton functor 𝔖:𝖯𝖬𝖵n𝖣𝖫\mathfrak{S}\colon\mathsf{PMV}_{n}\to\mathsf{DL}.

Proof.

Our proof strategy consists of the following two steps. We first define a functor 𝖯:𝖯𝗋𝗂𝖾𝗌𝗍𝒳n\mathsf{P}\colon\mathsf{Priest}\to\mathcal{X}_{n} and show that it is left-adjoint to the forgetful functor 𝖴n\mathsf{U}_{n}. Then we show that 𝔓\mathfrak{P} is the dual of 𝖯\mathsf{P}. By Theorem 4.4 and the uniqueness of an adjoint up to natural isomorphism, the theorem follows.

𝒳n\textstyle{\mathcal{X}_{n}\ignorespaces\ignorespaces\ignorespaces\ignorespaces\ignorespaces\ignorespaces\ignorespaces\ignorespaces\ignorespaces\ignorespaces\ignorespaces\ignorespaces\ignorespaces\ignorespaces\ignorespaces}𝖤n\scriptstyle{\mathsf{E}_{n}}𝖯\scriptstyle{\mathsf{P}}\scriptstyle{\phantom{.}\dashv}𝖴\scriptstyle{\mathsf{U}}𝖯𝖬𝖵n\textstyle{\mathsf{PMV}_{n}\ignorespaces\ignorespaces\ignorespaces\ignorespaces\ignorespaces\ignorespaces\ignorespaces\ignorespaces\ignorespaces\ignorespaces\ignorespaces\ignorespaces\ignorespaces\ignorespaces\ignorespaces}𝖣n\scriptstyle{\mathsf{D}_{n}}𝔓\scriptstyle{\mathfrak{P}}𝔖\scriptstyle{\mathfrak{S}}\scriptstyle{\vdash\phantom{.}}𝖯𝗋𝗂𝖾𝗌𝗍\textstyle{\mathsf{Priest}\ignorespaces\ignorespaces\ignorespaces\ignorespaces\ignorespaces}𝖤\scriptstyle{\mathsf{E}}𝖣𝖫\textstyle{\mathsf{DL}\ignorespaces\ignorespaces\ignorespaces\ignorespaces\ignorespaces}𝖣\scriptstyle{\mathsf{D}}

Let 𝖯:𝖯𝗋𝗂𝖾𝗌𝗍𝒳n\mathsf{P}\colon\mathsf{Priest}\to\mathcal{X}_{n} be defined as follows. For a Priestley space X,\langle X,\leq\rangle , define 𝖯(X,)\mathsf{P}(X,\leq) to be the structured topological space X,,(𝐑𝐗=𝐑𝒮n{})\langle X,\leq,(\mathbf{R}^{\mathbf{X}}=\emptyset\mid\mathbf{R}\in\mathcal{S}_{n}{\setminus}\{\leq\})\rangle, which is a well-defined member of 𝒳n\mathcal{X}_{n} by Proposition 4.2. Furthermore, define 𝖯φ=φ\mathsf{P}\varphi=\varphi on morphisms. It is easy to see that 𝖯\mathsf{P} is left-adjoint to 𝖴\mathsf{U}, since for every Priestley space X,\langle X,\leq\rangle and structure 𝐘𝒳n\mathbf{Y}\in\mathcal{X}_{n} because, by definition of 𝖯\mathsf{P}, morphisms in 𝒳n(𝖯(X,),𝐘)\mathcal{X}_{n}(\mathsf{P}(X,\leq),\mathbf{Y}) clearly coincide with continuous order-preserving maps XYX\to Y, that is, morphisms in 𝖯𝗋𝗂𝖾𝗌𝗍(X,,𝖴(𝖸))\mathsf{Priest}(\langle X,\leq\rangle,\mathsf{U}(\mathsf{Y})).

We now show that 𝖯\mathsf{P} is dual to 𝔓\mathfrak{P}, more specifically, we show that there is a natural isomorphism 𝖤n𝖯𝔓𝖤\mathsf{E}_{n}\mathsf{P}\cong\mathfrak{P}\mathsf{E}. For this, we simply note that, for a Priestley space X,\langle X,\leq\rangle, we have the following natural isomorphisms

𝖤n𝖯(X,)\displaystyle\mathsf{E}_{n}\mathsf{P}(X,\leq) =𝒳n(𝖯(X,),𝐏𝐋~n)\displaystyle=\mathcal{X}_{n}(\mathsf{P}(X,\leq),\utilde{\mathbf{PL}}_{n})\cong
𝖯𝗋𝗂𝖾𝗌𝗍(X,,𝖴(𝐏Ł~n))\displaystyle\cong\mathsf{Priest}(\langle X,\leq\rangle,\mathsf{U}(\utilde{\mathbf{P\text{\bf\L}}}_{n}))\cong
𝖯𝗋𝗂𝖾𝗌𝗍(𝖣𝖤(X,),𝖴(𝐏Ł~n))=𝔓𝖤(X,),\displaystyle\cong\mathsf{Priest}(\mathsf{DE}(X,\leq),\mathsf{U}(\utilde{\mathbf{P\text{\bf\L}}}_{n}))=\mathfrak{P}\mathsf{E}(X,\leq),

where we used 𝖯𝖴\mathsf{P}\dashv\mathsf{U} established above and the definition of the Priestley power 𝔓(𝐋)=𝖯𝗋𝗂𝖾𝗌𝗍(𝖣(𝐋),𝖴(𝐏Ł~n))\mathfrak{P}(\mathbf{L})=\mathsf{Priest}(\mathsf{D}(\mathbf{L}),\mathsf{U}(\utilde{\mathbf{P\text{\bf\L}}}_{n})). This finishes the proof. ∎

One simple consequence of (the proof of) Theorem4.7 is the following.

Corollary 4.8.

Every algebra 𝐀𝖯𝖬𝖵n\mathbf{A}\in\mathsf{PMV}_{n} is a subalgebra of a Priestley power. More specifically, there is an embedding 𝐀𝔓𝔖(𝐀)\mathbf{A}\hookrightarrow\mathfrak{P}\mathfrak{S}(\mathbf{A}).

Proof.

Let 𝖯\mathsf{P} be the dual of 𝔓\mathfrak{P} as in the proof of Theorem 4.7. It is easy to see that the counit of the adjunction 𝖯𝖴\mathsf{P}\dashv\mathsf{U} is the identity map idxid_{x} as a morphism 𝖯𝖴(𝐗)𝐗\mathsf{P}\mathsf{U}(\mathbf{X})\to\mathbf{X} on every component. Therefore, it is a component-wise epimorphism in 𝒳n\mathcal{X}_{n}. Dually, this implies that the unit of the adjunction 𝔖𝔓\mathfrak{S}\dashv\mathfrak{P} is a component-wise monomorphism, and therefore yields an embedding 𝐀𝔓𝔖(𝐀)\mathbf{A}\hookrightarrow\mathfrak{P}\mathfrak{S}(\mathbf{A}) for every 𝖯𝖬𝖵n\mathsf{PMV}_{n}-algebra 𝐀𝖯𝖬𝖵n\mathbf{A}\in\mathsf{PMV}_{n} as desired. ∎

In the last subsection, we describe the algebraically and existentially closed members of 𝖯𝖬𝖵n\mathsf{PMV}_{n} via their duals. For this, Boolean powers (rather than Priestley powers) play an essential role. However, since Boolean powers arise as special cases of Priestley powers, the results of this subsection will prove useful towards this end.

4.3. Algebraically and existentially closed algebras

A standard application of natural dualities is the classification of algebraically closed and existentially closed algebras via their duals (see, e.g., [8, Sections 5.3 and 5.4]). In this subsection, we give full classifications of the algebraically closed and existentially closed members of 𝖯𝖬𝖵n\mathsf{PMV}_{n} via Boolean powers. Note that, for a complemented bounded distributive lattice 𝐁\mathbf{B}, the Priestley power 𝐏Łn[𝐁]\mathbf{P\text{\bf\L}}_{n}[\mathbf{B}] from Definition 4.5 coincides with the usual Boolean power 𝐏Łn[𝐁]\mathbf{P\text{\bf\L}}_{n}[\mathbf{B}]. Since the structure 𝐏Ł~n\utilde{\mathbf{P\text{\bf\L}}}_{n} is total, we can use the AC-EC Theorem [8, Theorem 5.3.5.] to characterize algebraically and existentially closed members of 𝖯𝖬𝖵n\mathsf{PMV}_{n}.

Before we state this theorem, we recall that 𝐗𝒳n\mathbf{X}\in\mathcal{X}_{n} has the dual finite homomorphism property (FHP)(\text{FHP})^{\ast} if, for all finite 𝐘,𝐙𝒳n\mathbf{Y},\mathbf{Z}\in\mathcal{X}_{n} and surjective morphisms φ:𝐗𝐙\varphi\colon\mathbf{X}\to\mathbf{Z}, ψ:𝐘𝐙\psi\colon\mathbf{Y}\to\mathbf{Z}, there exists a morphism λ:𝐗𝐘\lambda\colon\mathbf{X}\to\mathbf{Y} such that φ=ψλ\varphi=\psi\circ\lambda.

(FHP)\text{(FHP})^{\ast} 𝐗{\mathbf{X}}𝐙{\mathbf{Z}}𝐘{\mathbf{Y}}φ\scriptstyle{\varphi}λ\scriptstyle{\exists\lambda}ψ\scriptstyle{\psi}

The dual finite embedding property (FEP)(\text{FEP})^{\ast} is the similar same, except that λ\lambda is also required to be surjective.

Theorem 4.9.

[8] Let 𝐀𝖯𝖬𝖵n\mathbf{A}\in\mathsf{PMV}_{n}.

  1. (1)

    𝐀\mathbf{A} is algebraically closed if and only if 𝖣n(𝐀)\mathsf{D}_{n}(\mathbf{A}) has the dual finite homomorphism property (FHP)(\text{FHP})^{\ast}.

  2. (2)

    𝐀\mathbf{A} is existentially closed if and only if 𝖣n(𝐀)\mathsf{D}_{n}(\mathbf{A}) has the finite embedding property (FEP)(\text{FEP})^{\ast}.

We now show that algebraically and existentially closed members of 𝖯𝖬𝖵n\mathsf{PMV}_{n} stem from Boolean algebras in the following sense.

Theorem 4.10.

Let 𝐀𝖯𝖬𝖵n\mathbf{A}\in\mathsf{PMV}_{n}.

  1. (1)

    𝐀\mathbf{A} is algebraically closed if and only if 𝐀\mathbf{A} is isomorphic to a Boolean power 𝐏Łn[𝐁]\mathbf{P\text{\bf\L}}_{n}[\mathbf{B}], where 𝐁𝖡𝖠\mathbf{B}\in\mathsf{BA} is an arbitrary Boolean algebra.

  2. (2)

    𝐀\mathbf{A} is existentially closed if and only if 𝐀\mathbf{A} is isomorphic to a Boolean power 𝐏Łn[𝐁]\mathbf{P\text{\bf\L}}_{n}[\mathbf{B}], where 𝐁𝖡𝖠\mathbf{B}\in\mathsf{BA} is an atomless Boolean algebra.

Proof.

By (the proof of) Theorem 4.7, we know that the duals of Boolean powers 𝐏Łn[𝐁]\mathbf{P\text{\bf\L}}_{n}[\mathbf{B}] in 𝒳n\mathcal{X}_{n} are exactly the structures isomorphic to some 𝐗𝒳n\mathbf{X}\in\mathcal{X}_{n} where 𝐗\leq^{\mathbf{X}} the discrete order and 𝐑𝐗\mathbf{R}^{\mathbf{X}} is empty for all other 𝐑𝒮n\mathbf{R}\in\mathcal{S}_{n}. We first show by contrapositive that if 𝐗\mathbf{X} has the finite homomorphism property, then it needs to be of this form.

Let 𝐗𝒳n\mathbf{X}\in\mathcal{X}_{n} not be of the form described above. If \leq is not discrete, there are distinct x,y𝐗x,y\in\mathbf{X} with x<yx<y. Let UU be an upset of XX containing yy but not xx. Define 𝐙𝒳n\mathbf{Z}\in\mathcal{X}_{n} to consist of two points {a,b}\{a,b\} with order a<ba<b (and all other relations empty), and let 𝐘\mathbf{Y} consist of two points {a,b}\{a^{\prime},b^{\prime}\} with the discrete order (and all other relations empty). Let φ:𝐗𝐙\varphi\colon\mathbf{X}\to\mathbf{Z} be the morphism sending UU to bb and XUX{\setminus}U to aa. Let ψ:𝐘𝐙\psi\colon\mathbf{Y}\to\mathbf{Z} be the morphism sending aa^{\prime} to aa and bb^{\prime} to bb. Now if there was a morphism λ\lambda witnessing (FHP)(\text{FHP})^{\ast}, it would have to satisfy λ(x)=a\lambda(x)=a^{\prime} and λ(y)=b\lambda(y)=b^{\prime}. However, this is impossible since this would mean xyx\leq y and λ(x)λ(y)\lambda(x)\not\leq\lambda(y), contradicting that λ\lambda needs to be order-preserving.

Now assume that 𝐗\mathbf{X} has the discrete order-relation and there is some other relation 𝐑𝐗\mathbf{R}^{\mathbf{X}} which is non-empty. Choose 𝐑\mathbf{R} minimal in 𝒮n\mathcal{S}_{n} such that there is some x𝐗x\in\mathbf{X} with x𝐑𝐗xx\mathbf{R}^{\mathbf{X}}x. Define 𝐙𝒳n\mathbf{Z}\in\mathcal{X}_{n} to consist of one point {a}\{a\} with a𝐑𝐗aa\mathbf{R}^{\mathbf{X}}a and let 𝐘\mathbf{Y} consists of one point {a}\{a^{\prime}\} with a𝐘aa^{\prime}\leq^{\mathbf{Y}}a^{\prime} and all other 𝐑𝐘\mathbf{R}^{\mathbf{Y}} empty. Let φ:𝐗𝐙\varphi\colon\mathbf{X}\to\mathbf{Z} and ψ:𝐘𝐙\psi\colon\mathbf{Y}\to\mathbf{Z} be the unique morphisms. The unique map λ:XZ\lambda\colon X\to Z is not a morphism because otherwise x𝐑𝐗xx\mathbf{R}^{\mathbf{X}}x would imply a𝐑aa^{\prime}\mathbf{R}a^{\prime}. Therefore 𝐗\mathbf{X} does not satisfy (FHP)(\text{FHP})^{\ast}.

Thus we showed that if 𝐀\mathbf{A} is algebraically closed, then it is isomorphic to some Boolean power 𝐏Łn[𝐁]\mathbf{P\text{\bf\L}}_{n}[\mathbf{B}]. For the converse of (1), one has to show that every 𝐗𝒳n\mathbf{X}\in\mathcal{X}_{n} with discrete order and all other relations empty has the finite homomorphism property. For (2), one has to show such an 𝐗\mathbf{X} has the finite embedding property if and only if \leq has no isolated points. However, this is easy, since both of these can be proven completely analogous to [8, Theorem 5.4.1]. ∎

In particular, for n=1n=1 we recover the well-known description of algebraically closed and existentially closed distributive lattices [22] as complemented distributive lattices and atomless complemented distributive lattices.

5. Conclusion

We developed a logarithmic optimal natural duality for the variety 𝖯𝖬𝖵n\mathsf{PMV}_{n} of positive 𝖬𝖵n\mathsf{MV}_{n}-algebras, generated by 𝐏Łn\mathbf{P\text{\bf\L}}_{n}, the negation-free reduct of the finite 𝖬𝖵\mathsf{MV}-chain Łn\text{\bf\L}_{n}. We explored the relationship between this duality and Priestley duality, showing that there is an adjunction between 𝖣𝖫\mathsf{DL} and 𝖯𝖬𝖵n\mathsf{PMV}_{n} given by the distributive skeleton functor 𝔖:𝖯𝖬𝖵n𝖣𝖫\mathfrak{S}\colon\mathsf{PMV}_{n}\to\mathsf{DL} and the Priestley power functor 𝔓:𝖣𝖫𝖯𝖬𝖵n\mathfrak{P}\colon\mathsf{DL}\to\mathsf{PMV}_{n}. Specializing this relationship to Boolean powers, we gave a full characterization of algebraically and existentially closed members of 𝖯𝖬𝖵n\mathsf{PMV}_{n}. In the following, a few open questions, remarks and ideas for further research are collected.

  1. (1)

    As noted in Remark 3.4, the results of Subsection 3.2 up until Lemma 3.9, as well as Lemma 3.5 and Corollary 3.6 from Subsection 3.1 hold not only for 𝐏Łn\mathbf{P\text{\bf\L}}_{n}, but for every lattice-based algebra 𝐃\mathbf{D} in which τd\tau_{d} is term-definable for every d𝐃d\in\mathbf{D}. Furthermore, the existence of these τd\tau_{d} together with a ‘weak form of negation’ is equivalent to semi-primality of a lattice-based algebra [17, Proposition 2.8]. Is there a sensible definition of ‘lattice-semi-primal’ algebras (similar to lattice-primal algebras), such that the results of this paper be seen as a specific instance of a more general result about natural dualities for such lattice-semi-primal algebras?

  2. (2)

    In Corollary 4.8, we showed that every 𝖯𝖬𝖵n\mathsf{PMV}_{n}-algebra can be embedded into the Priestley power of its distributive skeleton, similarly to how every 𝖬𝖵n\mathsf{MV}_{n}-algebra can be embedded into the Boolean power of its Boolean skeleton. Based on this, a category equivalent to 𝖬𝖵n\mathsf{MV}_{n} was described in [9]. This equivalence was explained from the point of view of natural dualities in [20]. Is there a similar categorical equivalence for 𝖯𝖬𝖵n\mathsf{PMV}_{n}? To deal with this question, the more constructive description of Priestley powers from [18] could prove useful.

  3. (3)

    In this paper, the logical aspects of 𝖯𝖬𝖵n\mathsf{PMV}_{n}-algebras were only hinted at. In future work, we plan to explore these aspects further. In particular, we aim to investigate modal extensions of 𝖯𝖬𝖵n\mathsf{PMV}_{n}-algebras to deal with an analogue of Dunn’s positive modal logic [10] in the setting of modal finitely-valued Łukasiewicz logic [13].

Appendix A An algorithm to find the dualizing structure

Making use of Proposition 3.12, here we provide an algorithm to find the lattice 𝒮n\mathcal{S}_{n} from Definition 3.13, in order to systematically determine the alter ego from Theorem 3.16.

By Proposition 3.12, the subalgebras 𝐑\lhd\subseteq\mathbf{R}\subseteq\leq are certain ‘unions of rectangles’ of the form

i=0nC(in,yi)\bigcup_{i=0}^{n}C_{(\frac{i}{n},y_{i})}

where y0yny_{0}\leq\dots\leq y_{n} is an increasing sequence in 𝐏Łn\mathbf{P\text{\bf\L}}_{n} with inyi\frac{i}{n}\leq y_{i}. We will identify this union with the sequence y1,,yn1y_{1},\dots,y_{n-1} (note that y0=0y_{0}=0 and yn=1y_{n}=1 holds for every subalgebra, so we can omit these). For example, the sequence where all yi=1y_{i}=1 corresponds to \lhd and the sequence yi=iny_{i}=\frac{i}{n} corresponds to \leq. However, not every such sequence corresponds to a subalgebra. By Proposition 3.12, the sequences which correspond to subalgebras, which we call good sequences, are the ones which satisfy

(jn,yj)(jn,yj)i=0nC(in,yi) and (jn,yj)(jn,yj)i=0nC(in,yi)(\tfrac{j}{n},y_{j})\odot(\tfrac{j^{\prime}}{n},y_{j^{\prime}})\in\bigcup_{i=0}^{n}C_{(\frac{i}{n},y_{i})}\text{ and }(\tfrac{j}{n},y_{j})\oplus(\tfrac{j^{\prime}}{n},y_{j^{\prime}})\in\bigcup_{i=0}^{n}C_{(\frac{i}{n},y_{i})}

for all j,j{1,,n1}j,j^{\prime}\in\{1,\dots,n-1\}. In fact, similar to the proof of Lemma 3.14, it can be shown that it is sufficient to check this condition only for the ‘corner elements’, that is, at indices ii which satisfy yi<yi+1y_{i}<y_{i+1} (with yn=1y_{n}=1).

Thus, the set 𝒮n\mathcal{S}_{n} is in bijective correspondence with the set of good sequences. Furthermore, the union associated to y1,,yn1y_{1},\dots,y_{n-1} is contained in the union associated to y1,,yn1y_{1}^{\prime},\dots,y_{n-1}^{\prime} if and only if yiyiy_{i}^{\prime}\leq y_{i} holds for i=1,,n1i=1,\dots,n-1. Thus we can also retrieve the lattice structure of 𝒮n\mathcal{S}_{n}. Altogether, we proved that the following algorithm yields the lattice 𝒮n\mathcal{S}_{n}.

Step 1. Generate the set YY of all sequences [y1,,yn][y_{1},\dots,y_{n}] of elements of 𝐏Łn\mathbf{P\text{\bf\L}}_{n} with y1,,yn1y_{1}\leq,\dots,\leq y_{n-1} and inyi\frac{i}{n}\leq y_{i} for all i=1,,n1i=1,\dots,n-1.

Step 2. Start with G=G=\emptyset and do the following for every sequence [y1,,yn1]Y[y_{1},\dots,y_{n-1}]\in Y. Let J{1,,n1}J\subseteq\{1,\dots,n-1\} be the collection of all indices ii with yi<yi+1y_{i}<y_{i+1} (where yn:=1y_{n}:=1). Check whether

(jn,yj)(jn,yj)i=0nC(in,yi) and (jn,yj)(jn,yj)i=0nC(in,yi)(\tfrac{j}{n},y_{j})\odot(\tfrac{j^{\prime}}{n},y_{j^{\prime}})\in\bigcup_{i=0}^{n}C_{(\frac{i}{n},y_{i})}\text{ and }(\tfrac{j}{n},y_{j})\oplus(\tfrac{j^{\prime}}{n},y_{j^{\prime}})\in\bigcup_{i=0}^{n}C_{(\frac{i}{n},y_{i})}

holds for all j,jJj,j^{\prime}\in J. Add [y1,,yn1][y_{1},\dots,y_{n-1}] to GG if and only if this holds.

Step 3. Order the set GG obtained after completing Step 2 by

[y1,,yn1][y1,,yn1]yiyi for i=1,,n1.[y_{1},\dots,y_{n-1}]\leq[y_{1}^{\prime},\dots,y^{\prime}_{n-1}]\Leftrightarrow y^{\prime}_{i}\leq y_{i}\text{ for }i=1,\dots,n-1.

This results in G𝒮nG\cong\mathcal{S}_{n} (note that the order on GG is simply the component-wise converse order \geq).

As an example, we compute the set 𝒮4\mathcal{S}_{4} using the above algorithm.

Step 1. The set YY consists of the following 1414 sequences:

[1,1,1],\displaystyle[1,1,1], [34,1,1],\displaystyle[\tfrac{3}{4},1,1], [34,34,1],\displaystyle[\tfrac{3}{4},\tfrac{3}{4},1], [34,34,34],\displaystyle[\tfrac{3}{4},\tfrac{3}{4},\tfrac{3}{4}], [24,1,1],\displaystyle[\tfrac{2}{4},1,1], [24,34,1],\displaystyle[\tfrac{2}{4},\tfrac{3}{4},1], [24,34,34],\displaystyle[\tfrac{2}{4},\tfrac{3}{4},\tfrac{3}{4}],
[24,24,1],\displaystyle[\tfrac{2}{4},\tfrac{2}{4},1], [24,24,34],\displaystyle[\tfrac{2}{4},\tfrac{2}{4},\tfrac{3}{4}], [14,1,1],\displaystyle[\tfrac{1}{4},1,1], [14,34,1],\displaystyle[\tfrac{1}{4},\tfrac{3}{4},1], [14,34,34],\displaystyle[\tfrac{1}{4},\tfrac{3}{4},\tfrac{3}{4}], [14,24,1],\displaystyle[\tfrac{1}{4},\tfrac{2}{4},1], [14,24,34].\displaystyle[\tfrac{1}{4},\tfrac{2}{4},\tfrac{3}{4}].

Step 2. The set GG of good sequences consists of the following 77 sequences:

[1,1,1],\displaystyle[1,1,1], [34,1,1],\displaystyle[\tfrac{3}{4},1,1], [34,34,1],\displaystyle[\tfrac{3}{4},\tfrac{3}{4},1], [24,1,1],\displaystyle[\tfrac{2}{4},1,1], [24,34,1],\displaystyle[\tfrac{2}{4},\tfrac{3}{4},1], [24,24,1],\displaystyle[\tfrac{2}{4},\tfrac{2}{4},1], [14,24,34].\displaystyle[\tfrac{1}{4},\tfrac{2}{4},\tfrac{3}{4}].

The other sequences are not good for the following reasons.

  • The sequences [34,34,34][\tfrac{3}{4},\tfrac{3}{4},\tfrac{3}{4}] and [24,34,34][\tfrac{2}{4},\tfrac{3}{4},\tfrac{3}{4}] are not good because (34,34)(34,34)=(24,24)C(24,24)(\frac{3}{4},\frac{3}{4})\odot(\frac{3}{4},\frac{3}{4})=(\frac{2}{4},\frac{2}{4})\notin C_{(\frac{2}{4},\frac{2}{4})}.

  • The sequence [24,24,34][\frac{2}{4},\frac{2}{4},\frac{3}{4}] is not good because (24,24)(34,34)=(14,14)C(14,24)(\frac{2}{4},\frac{2}{4})\odot(\frac{3}{4},\frac{3}{4})=(\frac{1}{4},\frac{1}{4})\notin C_{(\frac{1}{4},\frac{2}{4})}.

  • The sequences [14,1,1][\tfrac{1}{4},1,1], [14,34,1][\tfrac{1}{4},\tfrac{3}{4},1] and [14,34,34][\tfrac{1}{4},\tfrac{3}{4},\tfrac{3}{4}] are not good because (14,14)(14,14)=(24,24)C(24,34)(\frac{1}{4},\frac{1}{4})\oplus(\frac{1}{4},\frac{1}{4})=(\frac{2}{4},\frac{2}{4})\notin C_{(\frac{2}{4},\frac{3}{4})}.

  • The sequence [24,24,1][\tfrac{2}{4},\tfrac{2}{4},1] is not good because (14,14)(24,24)=(34,34)C(34,1(\frac{1}{4},\frac{1}{4})\oplus(\frac{2}{4},\frac{2}{4})=(\frac{3}{4},\frac{3}{4})\notin C_{(\frac{3}{4},1}.

Step 3. The lattice 𝒮4\mathcal{S}_{4} looks as follows:

[1,1,1][1,1,1][34,1,1][\tfrac{3}{4},1,1][24,1,1][\tfrac{2}{4},1,1][34,34,1][\tfrac{3}{4},\tfrac{3}{4},1][24,34,1][\tfrac{2}{4},\tfrac{3}{4},1][24,24,1][\tfrac{2}{4},\tfrac{2}{4},1][14,24,34][\tfrac{1}{4},\tfrac{2}{4},\tfrac{3}{4}]

To obtain an optimal strong duality for 𝖯𝖬𝖵4\mathsf{PMV}_{4}, we only need to consider the meet-irreductible elements of this lattice, i.e., we remove the relation corresponding to the sequence [34,1,1][\tfrac{3}{4},1,1].

Acknowledgment

The author is supported by the Luxembourg National Research Fund under the project PRIDE17/12246620/GPS.

References

  • [1] Abbadini, M., Jipsen, P., Kroupa, T., Vannucci, S.: A finite axiomatization of positive MV-algebras. Algebra Universalis 83, 1134–1164 (2022)
  • [2] Boicescu, V., Filipoiu, A., Georgescu, G., Rudeanu, S.: Łukasiewicz-Moisil Algebras. Annals of Discrete Mathematics, vol. 49. North-Holland, Amsterdam (1991)
  • [3] Bou, F., Esteva, F., Godo, L., Rodríguez, R.O.: On the Minimum Many-Valued Modal Logic over a Finite Residuated Lattice. Journal of Logic and Computation 21, 739–790 (2011)
  • [4] Burris, S.: Boolean powers. Algebra Universalis 5, 341–360 (1975)
  • [5] Burris, S., Sankappanavar, H.P.: A Course in Universal Algebra. Graduate Texts in Mathematics, vol. 78. Springer, New York (1981)
  • [6] Chang, C.C.: Algebraic analysis of many valued logics. Transactions of the American Mathematical Society 88, 467–490 (1958)
  • [7] Cignoli, R.L.O., D’Ottaviano, I.M.L., Mundici, D.: Algebraic Foundations of Many-Valued Reasoning. Trends in Logic, vol. 7. Springer, Dordrecht (2000)
  • [8] Clark, D.M., Davey, B.A.: Natural Dualities for the Working Algebraist. Cambridge studies in advanced mathematics, vol. 57. Cambridge University Press, Cambridge (1998)
  • [9] Di Nola, A., Lettieri, A.: One chain generated varieties of MV-algebras. Journal of Algebra 225, 667–697 (2000)
  • [10] Dunn, J.M.: Positive modal logic. Studia Logica 55, 301–317 (1995)
  • [11] Foster, A.L., Pixley, A.F.: Semi-categorical algebras. I. Semi-primal algebras. Mathematische Zeitschrift 83, 147–169 (1964)
  • [12] Grigolia, R.: Algebraic analysis of Łukasiewicz-Tarski’s n-valued logical systems. In: Wójcicki, R., Malinowski, G. (eds.) Selected papers on Łukasiewicz sentential calculi, pp. 81–92. Ossolineum, Wrocław (1977)
  • [13] Hansoul, G., Teheux, B.: Extending Łukasiewicz logics with a modality: Algebraic approach to relational semantics. Studia Logica 101, 505–545 (2013)
  • [14] Iorgulescu, A.: Connections between MVn algebras and n-valued Łukasiewicz-Moisil algebras. Part I. Discrete Mathematics 181, 155–177 (1998)
  • [15] Jipsen, P.: Generalizations of Boolean products for lattice-ordered algebras. Annals of Pure and Applied Logic 161, 228–234 (2009)
  • [16] Jónsson, B.: Algebras whose congruence lattices are distributive. Mathematica Scandinavica 21, 110–121 (1967)
  • [17] Kurz, A., Poiger, W., Teheux, B.: New perspectives on semi-primal varieties. Journal of Pure and Applied Algebra 228, 107525 (2024)
  • [18] Lenkehegyi, A.: A direct definition of distributive extensions of partially ordered algebras. Acta Mathematica Hungarica 47, 157–160 (1986)
  • [19] Mundici, D.: Advanced Łukasiewicz calculus and MV-algebras. Trends in Logic, vol. 35. Springer, Dordrecht (2011)
  • [20] Niederkorn, P.: Natural dualities for varieties of MV-algebras, I. Journal of Mathematical Analysis and Applications 255, 58–73 (2001)
  • [21] Ostermann, P.: Many-valued modal propositional calculi. Mathematical Logic Quarterly 34, 343–354 (1988)
  • [22] Schmid, J.: Algebraically and existentially closed distributive lattices. Mathematical Logic Quarterly 25, 525–530 (1979)