Edoardo \surnameLanari \givennameLuis \surnameScoccola \subjectprimarymsc202018N50, 18N40 \subjectsecondarymsc202055N31, 55U10, 55U35, 62R40 \arxivreference2010.05378
Rectification of interleavings and a persistent Whitehead theorem
Abstract
The homotopy interleaving distance, a distance between persistent spaces, was introduced by Blumberg and Lesnick and shown to be universal, in the sense that it is the largest homotopy-invariant distance for which sublevel-set filtrations of close-by real-valued functions are close-by. There are other ways of constructing homotopy-invariant distances, but not much is known about the relationships between these choices. We show that other natural distances differ from the homotopy interleaving distance in at most a multiplicative constant, and prove versions of the persistent Whitehead theorem, a conjecture of Blumberg and Lesnick that relates morphisms that induce interleavings in persistent homotopy groups to stronger homotopy-invariant notions of interleaving.
1 Introduction
Context.
Many of the main theoretical tools of Topological Data Analysis (TDA) come in the form of stability theorems. One of the best known stability theorems, due to Cohen-Steiner, Edelsbrunner, and Harer ([7]), implies that if are sufficiently tame functions, such as piecewise linear functions on the geometric realization of a finite simplicial complex, then
Here, denotes the -dimensional persistence diagram of . This consists of a multiset of points of the extended plane that captures the isomorphism type of the th persistent homology of the sublevel-sets of , that is, of the functor obtained by composing the sublevel-set filtration with the th homology functor , where denotes the poset of real numbers and denotes the category of vector spaces over some fixed field. The distance is the bottleneck distance, a combinatorial way of comparing persistence diagrams.
This result was later refined in [4] to the algebraic stability theorem, which says that for sufficiently tame functors, one has
where, as before, denotes the persistence diagram of , which describes the isomorphism type of , and denotes the interleaving distance, a distance between functors for any fixed category , which we recall below.
Stability theorems imply that pipelines like the following, popular in TDA, are robust to perturbations of the input data and can be used for inference purposes:
For example, the algebraic stability theorem tells us that the last step is stable, if we endow persistent vector spaces () with the interleaving distance and persistence diagrams with the bottleneck distance, while functoriality implies that the second step is stable, if we also endow persistent spaces () with the interleaving distance ([3]).
Problem statement.
Although useful in some applications, the interleaving distance on is often too fine; for instance, it is easy to see that Vietoris–Rips and other functors are not stable with respect to the Gromov–Hausdorff distance on metric spaces and the interleaving distance on . However, when one composes these functors with a homotopy-invariant functor, such as homology , the composite turns out to be stable ([5]). So, in these cases, one way to make the first step in the pipeline above stable is to force the interleaving distance on to be homotopy-invariant ([2, Section 1.2]). For this reason, many homotopy-invariant adaptations of the interleaving distance on and related categories have been proposed (see, e.g., [15, 2, 8]). In order to describe some of these adaptations, we recall the definition of the interleaving distance .
Let be a category. Given and , let be given by , with the obvious structure morphisms. One says that are -interleaved if there exist natural transformations and such that equals the natural transformation given by the structure morphisms of , and such that equals the natural transformation given by the structure morphisms of . Then .
Blumberg and Lesnick ([2]) define to be -homotopy interleaved if there exist weakly equivalent persistent spaces and such that and are -interleaved, and use homotopy interleavings to define the homotopy interleaving distance, denoted . The homotopy interleaving distance is the (metric) quotient of the interleaving distance by the equivalence relation given by weak equivalence, in the sense that is the largest homotopy-invariant distance that is bounded above by the interleaving distance.
Instead of taking a metric quotient, one can take the categorical quotient of by weak equivalences, and define interleavings directly in the homotopy category, similar to what is done in, e.g., [15, 8, 14]. In order to do this, one notes that the shift functors preserve weak equivalences and thus induce functors . This lets one copy the definition of interleaving, but in the homotopy category, which gives the notions of interleaving in the homotopy category and of interleaving distance in the homotopy category, denoted .
A third option, also introduced in [2], is to compare objects of using interleavings in , called homotopy commutative interleavings, which give rise to the homotopy commutative interleaving distance, denoted .
We have described three homotopy-invariant notions of interleaving in decreasing order of coherence. On one end, homotopy interleavings can be equivalently described as homotopy coherent diagrams of spaces ([2, Section 7]). On the other end, homotopy commutative interleavings correspond to diagrams in the homotopy category of spaces. It is clear that , and that any of the homotopy-invariant interleavings induce interleavings in homotopy groups.
Two questions arise: Are the three distances in some sense equivalent or are they fundamentally different? If a map induces interleavings in homotopy groups, does it follow that the map is part of one of the homotopy-invariant notions of interleaving? A conjectural answer to the second question is given in [2, Conjecture 8.6], where it is conjectured that when and are a kind of persistent CW-complex of finite dimension , if there exists a morphism between them inducing a -interleaving in homotopy groups, then and are -homotopy interleaved, for a constant that only depends on .
Contributions.
Homotopy interleavings compose in any functor category of the form for a cofibrantly generated model category (2.3). This allows us to state some of our results for any cofibrantly generated model category , or for a category of spaces , which can be instantiated to be any of the Quillen equivalent model categories of topological spaces or simplicial sets (2.1). Our first theorem is the following rectification result.
Theorem A.
Let be a cofibrantly generated model category, let , and let . If and are -homotopy commutative interleaved, then they are -homotopy interleaved for every .
It follows that we have . The above rectification result is different from many such results in homotopy theory, where a diagram of a certain shape, in the homotopy category, is lifted to a strict diagram of the same shape. The difference lies in the fact that the shape of the strict diagram we construct is different from the shape of the diagram in the homotopy category. In fact, building on the suggestion in [2] of using Toda brackets to give a lower bound for the above rectification, we show (3.12) that for , if then , so that, in particular, . This means that rectification in the usual sense is not possible in general, and thus standard results are not directly applicable. We also show that A has no analogue for multi-persistent spaces (Section 3.3).
Our second theorem relates morphisms inducing interleavings in homotopy groups to interleavings in the homotopy category. See 5.7 for the notion of persistent CW-complex and 5.2 for the notion of interleaving induced in persistent homotopy groups.
Theorem B.
Fix and . Let be (multi-)persistent spaces that are assumed to be projective cofibrant and -skeletal if , or persistent CW-complexes of dimension if . Let . If there exists a morphism in the homotopy category that induces -interleavings in all homotopy groups, then and are -interleaved in the homotopy category.
Structure of the paper.
In Section 2, we recall and give references for the necessary background. In Section 3, we prove A, we provide a lower bound for the rectification of homotopy commutative interleavings between persistent spaces, and show that A has no analogue for multi-persistent spaces. In Section 4, we characterize projective cofibrant (multi-)persistent simplicial sets as filtered simplicial sets. In Section 5, we prove B.
Acknowledgements.
The first named author gratefully acknowledges the support of Praemium Academiae of M. Markl and RVO:67985840. The second named author thanks Dan Christensen, Rick Jardine, Mike Lesnick, and Alex Rolle for insightful conversations. We thank Alex Rolle for detailed feedback and for suggesting 3.14 to us, Mike Lesnick for suggesting improvements to the constant of A, and the anonymous referee for helpful feedback.
2 Background and conventions
The main purpose of this section is to fix notation and to provide the reader with references. This section can be referred to as needed, but we do recommend going over Section 2.2 as it contains the notions of interleaving relevant to us.
We assume that the reader is comfortable with the language of category theory. Throughout the paper, we will use the term distance to refer to any extended pseudo metric on a (possibly large) set , that is, to any function that is symmetric, satisfies the triangle inequality, and is on the diagonal.
2.1 Spaces and model categories
2.1.1 Spaces
We work model-independently whenever possible. This means that whenever we say space we will mean either topological space or simplicial set. Results stated for spaces will hold for both possible models. The category of spaces will be denoted by .
2.1.2 Model categories
The theory of model categories was introduced in [18]; for a modern and thorough development of this theory we recommend [12] and [11].
We recall that two objects of a model category are said to be weakly equivalent if they are isomorphic in , which happens if and only if they are connected by a zig-zag of weak equivalences in . This is an equivalence relation, which we denote by . When there is risk of confusion, morphisms in will be surrounded by square brackets , to distinguish them from morphisms in .
Two of the main model structures of interest to us are the Quillen model structure on , the category of topological spaces ([12, Chapter 1, Section 2.4]), and the Kan–Quillen model structure on , the category of simplicial sets ([12, Chapter 3]). We recall that the geometric realization functor is left adjoint to the singular functor , and that, together, they form a Quillen equivalence ([12, Chapter 1, Section 1.3], [12, Theorem 3.6.7]). For completeness, we mention that there is a subcategory , the category of compactly-generated weakly Hausdorff topological spaces (called compactly generated spaces in [12, Definition 2.4.21]), that is often used instead of . The Quillen model structure on restricts to a model structure on , and the inclusion is part of a Quillen equivalence ([12, Theorem 2.4.25]). This model structure is, in some respects, better behaved than the Quillen model structure on topological spaces, and is in fact the model of space used in [2]. We will not concern ourselves with these subtleties since, by the observations in 2.1, there is no essential difference between using or when studying homotopy-invariant notions of interleaving.
We will make use of the notion of cofibrantly generated model category ([12, Chapter 2, Section 2.1]). Recall that the Kan–Quillen model structure on simplicial sets is cofibrantly generated, where a set of generating cofibrations consists of the boundary inclusions for ([12, Theorem 3.6.5]). The Quillen model structure on topological spaces is also cofibrantly generated, with a set of generating cofibrations given by ([12, Theorem 2.4.19]).
We conclude by recalling the basic properties of projective model structures. Given a model category and a small category , the projective model structure on the functor category is, when it exists, the model structure whose fibrations (respectively weak equivalences) are those which are pointwise fibrations (respectively weak equivalences) of .
The projective model structure on exists, and is cofibrantly generated, whenever is cofibrantly generated. Moreover, if and are, respectively, generating cofibrations and generating trivial cofibration for the model structure of , then and are, respectively, generating cofibrations and generating trivial cofibrations for the projective model structure, where, given a functor and an object , the functor is defined by ([11, Section 11.6]). For simplicity, we denote by .
We are especially interested in the projective model structure when the indexing category is a poset . In this case, if and , then is the functor that takes the value on every , and has as value the initial object of when . The non-trivial structure morphisms of this functor are the identity of .
Note that we have a functor by the universal property of .
2.2 Interleavings and interleavings up to homotopy
2.2.1 Strict interleavings
We denote the poset of real numbers with their standard order by , and for , we let be the set of -tuples of real numbers with the product order. We set , so that if and only if for all . We denote the element by .
Fix a category and a natural number . An -persistent object of is any functor of the form . We often refer to -persistent objects simply as persistent objects or as multi-persistent objects when we want to stress the fact that is not necessarily . Fix persistent objects , , and . We use the following conventions.
-
•
For a natural transformation, denote the -component of by .
-
•
Assume . The structure morphism will be denoted by .
-
•
The -shift to the left of is the functor defined by , with structure morphisms . Shifting to the left gives a functor . Dually, there is a -shift to the right functor defined by mapping to the persistent object , with values given by .
-
•
Natural transformations will be referred to as -morphisms, and will often be denoted by . Since we have natural bijections , we can treat a -morphism as or as .
-
•
Assume and let . We can compose the -component of with , giving . Together, these components define the shift from to of , which is a -morphism denoted .
-
•
Note that an -morphism can be composed with a -morphism , yielding an -morphism . This composition is associative and unital, and is natural with respect to shifts of morphisms.
-
•
An -interleaving between and consists of an -morphism together with a -morphism such that and . By -interleaving we mean a -interleaving.
-
•
If and form an -interleaving, we write .
Let . Note that an -interleaving between and can be composed with any -interleaving between and , yielding an -interleaving. The fact that interleavings compose implies that, when , the formula
defines an extended pseudo metric . This is the interleaving distance on the class of objects of the category . This notion of distance can be extended to objects of the functor category ([15]), but we will not make use of this extension.
2.2.2 Interleavings up to homotopy
If one is comparing objects of a category of functors of the form , for a model category, it makes sense to want to find a homotopy-invariant notion of interleaving. In this paper, we consider the following three homotopy-invariant relaxations of the notion of interleaving. Let be a cofibrantly generated model category and endow with the projective model structure. Let and let .
-
1.
Following [2], we say that and are -homotopy interleaved if there exist and such that and are -interleaved.
-
2.
Note that the shift functor maps weak equivalences to weak equivalences. This implies that all the notions in Section 2.2.1 have analogues in the category . We say that and are -interleaved in the homotopy category if they are -interleaved as objects of .
-
3.
Finally, as also done in [2], we say that and are -homotopy commutative interleaved if their images are -interleaved.
An -homotopy interleaving gives rise to an -interleaving in the homotopy category, which, in turn, gives rise to an -homotopy commutative interleaving.
For each of the three homotopy-invariant notions of interleaving introduced above, we have a corresponding extended pseudo metric on the collection of objects of the category . Let . Following [2], we define the homotopy interleaving distance as
The fact that the homotopy interleaving distance satisfies the triangle inequality follows from 2.3. The interleaving distance in the homotopy category is
Again following [2], the homotopy commutative interleaving distance is defined as
Remark 2.1.
Note that if is a Quillen equivalence between cofibrantly generated model categories, then the induced Quillen equivalence ([11, Theorem 11.6.5]) between the projective model structures respects interleavings, in the sense that shifts commute with both the left and right adjoints. This implies that, for any of the three homotopy-invariant notions of interleaving described above, we have that two functors on one side of the adjunction are -interleaved if and only if their images (along the derived adjunction) on the other side are -interleaved. In particular, if , the two adjoints give an isometry between and independently of whether we use , , or .
2.2.3 Composability of homotopy interleavings
In this short section, we give a simplified proof of a generalization of the fact that homotopy interleavings can be composed, originally proved in [2, Section 4]. This is generalized further in [20, Theorem 4.1.4].
Lemma 2.2.
Let admit pullbacks. Fix , objects , elements , an -interleaving , and a map . The pullback of along , denoted , is part of an -interleaving .
Proof.
We start by depicting the pullback square in the statement:
Consider the morphisms and . Since , the universal property of gives us a map , or equivalently, a map . By construction, . To prove that , or equivalently that , apply the functor to the pullback square above, and use the uniqueness part of its universal property. ∎
Proposition 2.3 (cf. [2, Section 4]).
Let be cofibrantly generated, fix , let , and let . If and are -homotopy interleaved and and are -homotopy interleaved, then and are -homotopy interleaved.
Proof.
Given interleavings and with , , and , we must construct an interleaving with and .
Since is cofibrantly generated, the projective model structure on exists, and, by applying a functorial fibrant replacement pointwise, we get a functorial fibrant replacement . By construction, the fibrant replacement commutes with so, in particular, it preserves interleavings. With this in mind, we can assume that and are fibrant, which implies, and this is a general fact, that we have and trivial fibrations and . Using 2.2, we can pull back the interleavings we were given along the trivial fibrations, as follows:
Since trivial fibrations are stable under pullback, we have that and , and since interleavings compose, we have that and are -interleaved, as required. ∎
We remark that the idea of using pullbacks to prove a triangle inequality appears in [17].
3 Interleavings in and in
This section is concerned with the rectification of homotopy commutative interleavings into homotopy interleavings. In Section 3.1, we prove A, which allows one to construct, for any , a -homotopy interleaving out of a -homotopy commutative interleaving, when working with -persistent objects of any cofibrantly generated model category . We think of this result as giving a multiplicative upper bound of for this rectification. In Section 3.2, we give a multiplicative lower bound of for the rectification, when is the category of spaces. In Section 3.3, we show that A has no analogue for multi-persistent spaces.
3.1 Upper bound
Let denote the posets of integers and real numbers respectively. The inclusion induces a restriction functor for any category . Given , let be given by precomposed with the functor , where is the largest integer bounded above by . Note that, given , one has a notion of -interleaving between functors , and that preserves these interleavings.
We start with a few simplifications. Given , let be given by . The following lemma allows us to work with integer-valued interleavings instead of -interleavings, and its proof is immediate.
Lemma 3.1.
Let and let . Then are -interleaved if and only if and are -interleaved.∎
The following lemma allows us to work with -indexed persistent objects instead of -indexed ones. Here, by homotopy interleaving between -indexed functors we mean the obvious adaptation of the notion of homotopy interleaving to -indexed functors with values in a model category.
Lemma 3.2.
Let be cofibrantly generated. Let and let . If are -homotopy interleaved, then and are -homotopy interleaved.
Proof.
Note that is -interleaved with , as, for all , we have . Since preserves interleavings and weak equivalences, it is enough to show that homotopy interleavings between -indexed functors with values in a cofibrantly generated model category compose, which is a straightforward adaptation of 2.3 to -indexed functors. ∎
The next straightforward lemma gives us a special replacement of an object of the category , with a model category, that will be useful when lifting structure from to .
Lemma 3.3.
Given a model category and , there exists and a weak equivalence , such that the following properties are satisfied:
-
•
is cofibrant in for every ;
-
•
for every , the structure morphism is a cofibration in .
Dually, we can replace by a pointwise fibrant whose “negative” maps are fibrations.
The following lemma will allow us to lift interleavings in to homotopy interleavings in .
Lemma 3.4.
Let be a model category. The functor is essentially surjective, conservative, and full. In particular, if become isomorphic in , then they are weakly equivalent.
Proof.
It is clear that the functor is essentially surjective and full, so we only prove the last property. Assume given together with a map . Thanks to 3.3, we can assume that (respectively ) is pointwise cofibrant (respectively fibrant) in , and that all the non-negative (respectively negative) structural maps in (respectively ) are cofibrations (respectively fibrations). The map can therefore be represented as a family of homotopy classes of maps of . We construct a preimage of under inductively, starting with a choice of representatives for the homotopy classes . The squares
commute up to homotopy, and since and are, respectively, a cofibration and a fibration, we can deform and into homotopic maps and , which render the above squares commutative. Inductively, we can iterate this procedure to find the desired preimage of under . ∎
The next result is the main rectification step involved in lifting interleavings in to homotopy interleavings in .
Proposition 3.5.
Let be a model category and let . Let . If and are -interleaved in , then and are -homotopy interleaved in .
Proof.
We start by giving the proof for the case , as in this case the main idea is more clear. We will use the following constructions. Let be the functor that maps even numbers to themselves and an odd number to . Similarly, let be the functor that maps odd numbers to themselves and an even number to .
Note that, for every , we have that is -interleaved with and with , and that and are -interleaved.
Now assume given a -interleaving between and in , that is, assume that there are morphisms and in rendering the following diagram commutative:
Consider the object given by one of the two diagonal zig-zags of the diagram above, namely, let
Using 3.4, construct such that .
Now, by construction, we have that , so from 3.4 it follows that . Similarly, we have . Since is -interleaved with , is -interleaved with , and is -interleaved with , 2.3 implies that and are -homotopy interleaved, concluding the proof for the case .
The proof for general is analogous, replacing the functor with given by , the functor with given by , and with
where denotes the largest integer such that . ∎
We are now ready to prove the main result of this section.
Theorem A.
Let be a cofibrantly generated model category, let , and let . If and are -homotopy commutative interleaved, then they are -homotopy interleaved for every .
Proof.
Let and let be large enough so that . By 3.1, we may assume that are -homotopy commutative interleaved and that we must show that they are -homotopy interleaved. Since , 3.2 reduces the problem to showing that and are -homotopy interleaved in , knowing that they are -homotopy commutative interleaved. 3.5 now finishes the proof. ∎
3.2 Lower bound
A implies that we have as distances on , for and for every cofibrantly generated model category . One could wonder if the constant can be improved. In this section we show that, when , we have . We do this by characterizing three-object persistent spaces which are -homotopy interleaved with a trivial persistent space in terms of the vanishing of a Toda bracket. The idea of using Toda brackets to prove that is suggested in [2, Example 7.3].
The Toda bracket is an operation on composable triples of homotopy classes of pointed maps, and was originally defined to compute homotopy groups of spheres ([21]). We are interested in the use of Toda brackets as an algebraic obstruction to the rectification of diagrams. We now describe the fundamental procedure involved in the definition of Toda brackets, and the few properties that we are interested in (see, e.g., [1]).
Let denote the category of pointed spaces. For concreteness, in the arguments of this section we use . Let denote the category freely generated by the graph . A diagram , which is given by and homotopy classes of pointed maps , , and , is a bracket sequence if and are equal to the null map, that is, to the homotopy class of the constant pointed map.
Let be a bracket sequence and let be such that , which exists by 3.4. We can, and do, assume that takes values in CW-complexes. Consider the following diagram of pointed spaces and pointed maps:
Since is a bracket sequence, we know that there exist (pointed) homotopies filling the squares in the diagram above. For a pointed space, let denote its reduced cone. Each pair of such homotopies gives us pointed maps and such that and , where is the inclusion into the cone. In particular, we have a commutative square
(3.1) |
which, by noticing that the pushout of the top and left morphisms is a model for the reduced suspension of , gives us an element of , where denotes homotopy classes of pointed maps.
Definition 3.6.
Let be a bracket sequence. Consider the subset of consisting of all elements that can be obtained using the procedure above. This is the Toda bracket of . We say that the Toda bracket vanishes if it contains the null map.
It is well-known (see, e.g., [1, Section 1]) that the non-vanishing of a Toda bracket is an obstruction to the rectification of the bracket sequence, in the following sense.
Proposition 3.7.
The Toda bracket of a bracket sequence vanishes if and only if there exists with and with and equal to the null map.∎
Although Toda brackets are defined for diagrams of pointed spaces, one can extend them to unpointed spaces, provided the spaces are simply connected. This is what we do now. A simply connected space is a non-empty, connected space whose fundamental groupoid is trivial. Let and denote the categories of simply connected spaces and of pointed, simply connected spaces, respectively. We have the following well-known fact and corollary.
Lemma 3.8.
The forgetful functor is an equivalence of categories.∎
Corollary 3.9.
If is such that the composite of consecutive maps of are null-homotopic, then is a bracket sequence.
Let be such that . Then is a bracket sequence if and only if is; in that case, the Toda bracket of vanishes if and only if the Toda bracket of does. ∎
3.9 implies that, for , there is a well-defined notion of being a bracket sequence, namely that any lift is a bracket sequence; in that case, we say that the Toda bracket of vanishes if the Toda bracket of does.
Let be given by extending to the right with the singleton space and to the left with the empty space. Let be the constant singleton space.
Proposition 3.10.
Let , then
-
1.
is -interleaved with if and only if is a bracket sequence;
-
2.
if is -interleaved with , then is -homotopy interleaved with if and only if the Toda bracket of vanishes.
Proof.
Statement 1 follows directly from 3.9. For 2, note that if the Toda bracket of vanishes, then, by 3.7, there exists such that and such that the composite of consecutive maps of are null maps. In particular, is -interleaved with , and, since , we have that by 3.4, so and are -homotopy interleaved.
For the converse of 2, assume that and are -homotopy interleaved. It follows that there exists a commutative diagram of pointed spaces and pointed maps
with and contractible and such that , as diagrams of unpointed spaces. It suffices to show that the Toda bracket of vanishes. For this, note that, using the diagonal morphism , we can find maps and such that . In particular, in this case, there is a diagonal filler for the square (3.1) and thus the induced map is null-homotopic, as required. ∎
The following lemma is clear.
Lemma 3.11.
Let . If are -interleaved for some , then are -interleaved.∎
We are now ready to prove the lower bound.
Proposition 3.12.
Let . If then .
Proof.
By 3.11 and 3.10, it suffices to find a bracket sequence valued in simply connected spaces such that its Toda bracket does not vanish. Examples of this are given in [21]. A classical example, referenced in [2], is with the first and last maps degree maps, and the middle map the suspension of the Hopf map. ∎
Remark 3.13.
3.12 implies in particular that . As mentioned in the introduction, we know that we have , so it is natural to wonder whether we have or , or both. We leave these as open questions.
3.3 Impossibility of rectification in higher dimensions
In this section, we show that A has no analogue for multi-persistent spaces; we thank Alex Rolle for pointing this out to us. We prove this for and remark that a similar argument works for .
Proposition 3.14.
If , there is no constant such that for all , if are -homotopy commutative interleaved, then they are -homotopy interleaved.
Let denote the subposet of spanned by , so that a functor from to a category corresponds to a commutative square in . We will use the following well-known fact, which says that a homotopy commutative diagram can have different, non-equivalent lifts. For a specific instance see, e.g., [10].
Lemma 3.15.
There exist such that and such that .∎
Proof of 3.14.
Given a diagram , consider the bi-persistent space such that whenever or are negative, whenever , and is the singleton space whenever and . Let . Note that if and are -homotopy interleaved, then we have .
To prove the result, it is enough to show that there exist bi-persistent spaces that are -homotopy commutative interleaved, i.e., such that , which are not -homotopy interleaved for any . In order to do this, we can let and be as in 3.15 and take and . ∎
4 Projective cofibrant persistent simplicial sets
The purpose of this section is to characterize projective cofibrant persistent simplicial sets as filtered simplicial sets (4.5). We work with simplicial sets indexed by an arbitrary poset .
Definition 4.1.
A -filtered simplicial set (filtered simplicial set when there is no risk of confusion) is a simplicial set equipped with functions , satisfying:
-
•
for every , , and boundary map ;
-
•
for every , , and degeneracy map .
When there is no risk of ambiguity, we denote the filtered simplicial set simply by .
Definition 4.2.
Given a filtered simplicial set define a persistent simplicial set such that for we have , with faces and degeneracies given by restricting the ones of .
By a standard abuse of language, We say that a persistent simplicial set is a filtered simplicial set if it is isomorphic to , for a filtered simplicial set.
The following result is a characterization of filtered simplicial sets among persistent simplicial sets by means of easily verified point-set conditions.
Lemma 4.3.
A persistent simplicial set is a filtered simplicial set if and only if the following conditions are satisfied:
-
1.
The structure morphism is a monomorphism for every in . In particular, up to isomorphism, we may, and do, assume that is a subsimplicial set of .
-
2.
For every simplex , the set has a minimum.
Proof.
The proof of the following lemma a straightforward application of Lemma 4.3. We use the term cell attachment to indicate any pushout of a generating cofibration .
Lemma 4.4.
-
1.
A retract of a filtered simplicial set is filtered.
-
2.
If the domain of a cell attachment is a filtered simplicial set, then the codomain is too.
-
3.
Let be a limit ordinal and let be a diagram of persistent simplicial sets, where for each we have that the map is a cell attachment. If is a filtered simplicial set for every , then is a filtered simplicial set.∎
The recognition principle for projective cofibrant persistent simplicial sets is now a consequence of 4.4 and the fact that the cofibrant objects in a cofibrantly generated model category are precisely the retracts of transfinite compositions of cell attachments ([12, Proposition 2.1.18(b)]).
Proposition 4.5.
A persistent simplicial set is filtered if and only if it is projective cofibrant.∎
In practice, many of the persistent spaces relevant to Topological Data Analysis are filtered simplicial sets.
Example 4.6.
The Vietoris–Rips complex associated to a metric space , usually defined to be a persistent simplicial complex, can be turned into a persistent simplicial set by choosing a total order on . It follows directly from its definition that this persistent simplicial set is filtered. Other examples of this form include the Čech complex and the filtrations of [6].
An example of a filtered multi-persistent simplicial set is the following. Given a metric space together with a real-valued function , one can construct a bi-filtered simplicial set as follows. For each , consider and let be the Vietoris–Rips complex of at scale .
We remark that persistent simplicial sets whose structure maps are monomorphism are not necessarily filtered. This happens in practice when the same simplex “appears at different times”, that is, when condition 2 in 4.3 is not satisfied. Examples of this include the degree-Rips bi-filtration ([16]), and Vietoris–Rips applied to the kernel density filtration of [19].
5 Interleaving in and in homotopy groups
In this section, we prove B. We start by defining the notions of persistent homotopy groups of a persistent space, and of morphism inducing an interleaving in persistent homotopy groups. The notion of persistent homotopy group we use is essentially the same as that of Jardine ([13]).
We model the th homotopy group of a pointed space by the set of pointed homotopy classes of pointed maps from the th dimensional sphere into .
Definition 5.1.
Let . The persistent set is defined by . Let , , and . The th persistent homotopy group of based at is the persistent group that is trivial at , and that is at .
Note that is functorial for every .
Definition 5.2.
Let . Assume given a homotopy class of morphisms . Let be a cofibrant replacement, let be a fibrant replacement, and let be a representative of . We say that induces an -interleaving in homotopy groups if the induced map is part of an -interleaving of persistent sets, and if for every , every , and every , the induced map is part of an -interleaving of persistent groups.
It is clear that the definition above is independent of the choices of representatives.
A standard result in classical homotopy theory is that a fibration of Kan complexes inducing an isomorphism in all homotopy groups has the right lifting property with respect to cofibrations ([9, Theorem I.7.10]). An analogous, persistent, result (5.13), says that, for a fibration of fibrant objects inducing a -interleaving in homotopy groups, the lift exists up to a shift, which depends on both and on a certain “length” associated to the cofibration. To make this precise, we introduce the notion of -dimensional extension.
Definition 5.3.
Let and let . A map is a -dimensional extension (of ) if there exists a set , a family of tuples of real numbers , and commutative squares of the form depicted on the left below, that together give rise to the pushout square on the right below. Here, stands for if , and for if .
A single dimensional extension is an -dimensional extension for some .
Definition 5.4.
Let be a projective cofibration of and let . We say that is an -cofibration if it factors as the composite of maps , with an -dimensional extension for some . We say that is -cofibrant if the map is an -cofibration.
The next lemma, which follows directly from 4.5, gives a rich family of examples of -cofibrant persistent simplicial sets. Recall that a simplicial set is -skeletal if all its simplices in dimensions above are degenerate.
Lemma 5.5.
Let and let . If is projective cofibrant and pointwise -skeletal, then it is -cofibrant.∎
Example 5.6.
The Vietoris–Rips complex of a metric space , as defined in 4.6, is -cofibrant if the underlying set of has finite cardinality .
If one is interested in persistent (co)homology of some bounded degree , then one can restrict computations to the -skeleton of a Vietoris–Rips complex, which is -cofibrant.
A result analogous to 5.5, but for persistent topological spaces, does not hold, as cells are not necessarily attached in order of dimension. This motivates the following definition.
Definition 5.7.
Let . A persistent topological space is an -dimensional persistent CW-complex if the map can be factored as a composite of maps , with an -dimensional extension.
Example 5.8.
The geometric realization of any -cofibrant persistent simplicial set is an -dimensional persistent CW-complex.
Lemma 5.9.
Every -dimensional persistent CW-complex is -cofibrant.∎
We now make precise the notion of lifting property up to a shift.
Definition 5.10.
Let and be morphisms in and let . We say that has the right -lifting property with respect to if for all morphisms and making the square on the left below commute, there exists a diagonal -morphism rendering the diagram commutative. Below, the diagram on the left is shorthand for the one on the right.
We now prove 5.12, an adaptation of a result of Jardine, which says that fibrations inducing interleavings in homotopy groups have a shifted right lifting property, as defined above. The main difference is that we work in the multi-persistent setting. We use simplicial notation and observe that the corresponding statement for persistent topological spaces follows from the simplicial one by using the singular complex-realization adjunction. We recall a standard, technical lemma whose proof is given within that of, e.g., [9, Theorem I.7.10].
Lemma 5.11.
Suppose given a commutative square of simplicial sets
(5.1) |
where is a Kan fibration between Kan complexes. If there is commutative diagram like the one on the left below, for which the lifting problem on the right admits a solution, then the initial square (5.1) admits a solution.
Lemma 5.12 (cf. [13, Lemma 14]).
Let , and let induce a -interleaving in homotopy groups. If and are projective fibrant and is a projective fibration, then has the right -lifting property with respect to boundary inclusions , for every and every .
Proof.
Suppose given a commutative diagram as on the left below, which corresponds to the one on the right:
(5.2) |
We must find a -lift for the diagram on the right. The proof strategy is to appeal to 5.11 to simplify , then prove that at the cost of a -shift we can further reduce to a constant map, and then show that the simplified lifting problem can be solved at the cost of another -shift. So we end up with a -lift, as in the statement. We proceed by proving the claims in opposite order.
We start by showing that (5.2) can be solved up to a -shift whenever is constant. Let us assume that is of the form for some . Since, then, represents an element , there exists a map whose restriction to is constant on , and such that there is a homotopy relative to . We can thus consider
where is a diagonal filler for the right-hand side square, which exists since the middle vertical map is a trivial cofibration of simplicial sets and is a Kan fibration by assumption. The composite map is a lift for (5.2).
We now assume that is of a specific, simplified form, and prove that, up to a -shift, we can reduce the lifting problem (5.2) to the case in which is constant. Let us assume that for every , and set . We have that represents an element , with the property that . Since induces a -interleaving in homotopy groups, we have that , witnessed by a homotopy , constant on . If we set for every and , we get a map . We can now extend to a homotopy . Now observe that the following lifting problem is such that , so, thanks to 5.11, we have reduced this case to the case in which is constant.
To conclude, we must show that we can reduce the original lifting problem (5.2) to one in which all but the th faces of are constant on a point . Let be the homotopy that contracts the simplicial horn onto its vertex , which determines a diagram
with , with the inclusion of the horn into the boundary. We can now extend the map to a homotopy . Similarly, we extend the map to a homotopy . It now suffices to consider the diagram
observing that satisfies for , and appeal to 5.11. ∎
Corollary 5.13.
Let and let induce a -interleaving in homotopy groups. If and are projective fibrant and is a projective fibration, then has the right -lifting property with respect to -cofibrations, for all .
Proof.
By assumption, induces a -interleaving in all homotopy groups. Now, an -cofibration can be written as a composite of single dimensional extensions, and any shift of a single dimensional extension is again a single dimensional extension, so it is enough to show that has the right -lifting property with respect to single dimensional extensions.
A single dimensional extension is the pushout of a coproduct , so it is enough to show that has the right -lifting property with respect to coproducts of that form, which follows from 5.12 and the universal property of coproducts. ∎
We are ready to prove B.
Theorem B.
Let be persistent spaces that are assumed to be projective cofibrant and -skeletal if , or persistent CW-complexes of dimension at most if . Let . If there exists a morphism in the homotopy category that induces -interleavings in all homotopy groups, then and are -interleaved in the homotopy category.
Proof.
By 5.5 and 5.9, and are -cofibrant. Let be as in the statement. Since is a morphism in the homotopy category, we begin by choosing a convenient representative of it. We let be a projective fibration between projective fibrant objects such that there exist trivial cofibrations and with , in .
Note that induces a -interleaving in homotopy groups, between and . Since is -cofibrant, 5.13 guarantees that we can find a -lift of against . We can then use the fact that is a trivial cofibration, and that is fibrant, to construct the following lift
We will show that and form a -interleaving in the homotopy category between and .
On the one hand, note that, by construction, we have , so, since is an isomorphism, it follows that , and thus that
On the other hand, since is cofibrant and is fibrant, it follows from the previous paragraph that is homotopic to . Let be a homotopy between these maps, which gives the following commutative diagram
where the left vertical map is the inclusion of into the cylinder. We claim that, since is -cofibrant, the inclusion into the cylinder is a -cofibration. Indeed, a cell decomposition of this map is obtained by attaching an -cell for each -cell in the decomposition of . Now, by 5.13, we can find a -lift of the diagram, which shows that
Since the left hand side is equal to , and is an isomorphism, it follows that . ∎
Remark 5.14.
Together, A and B imply a version of the persistent Whitehead conjecture, which we recall as 5.15. Our result is, in a sense, stronger than the one conjectured, since B, which addresses part of the conjecture, applies to arbitrary multi-persistent spaces. In another respect, our result is slightly weaker, as the conjecture is stated for cofibrant, pointwise CW-complexes, which does not necessarily imply being a persistent CW-complex in our sense. We believe that this is not an issue, as many of the cofibrant, pointwise CW-complexes persistent topological spaces that appear in applications are in fact persistent CW-complexes, as they are usually the geometric realization of a filtered simplicial complex.
Conjecture 5.15 ([2, Conjecture 8.6]).
Suppose we are given connected, cofibrant , with each and CW-complexes of dimension at most , and inducing a -interleaving in all homotopy groups. Then, there is a constant , depending only on , such that
-
(i)
induces a -interleaving in the homotopy category ;
-
(ii)
and are -homotopy interleaved.
References
- [1] David Blanc, Mark W. Johnson and James M. Turner “A constructive approach to higher homotopy operations” In Homotopy theory: tools and applications 729, Contemp. Math. Amer. Math. Soc., Providence, RI, 2019, pp. 21–74
- [2] Andrew J. Blumberg and Michael Lesnick “Universality of the Homotopy Interleaving Distance”, 2017 arXiv:1705.01690
- [3] Peter Bubenik and Jonathan A. Scott “Categorification of Persistent Homology” In Discret. Comput. Geom. 51.3, 2014, pp. 600–627
- [4] Frédéric Chazal et al. “Proximity of Persistence Modules and Their Diagrams” In Proceedings of the Twenty-Fifth Annual Symposium on Computational Geometry, SCG ’09, 2009, pp. 237–246
- [5] Frédéric Chazal et al. “Gromov-Hausdorff Stable Signatures for Shapes Using Persistence” In Proceedings of the Symposium on Geometry Processing, SGP ’09, 2009, pp. 1393–1403
- [6] Samir Chowdhury et al. “New families of stable simplicial filtration functors” In Topology and its Applications 279, 2020, pp. 107254
- [7] David Cohen-Steiner, Herbert Edelsbrunner and John Harer “Stability of persistence diagrams” In Discrete Comput. Geom. 37.1, 2007, pp. 103–120
- [8] Patrizio Frosini, Claudia Landi and Facundo Mémoli “The Persistent Homotopy Type Distance” In Homology, Homotopy and Applications 21, 2017
- [9] Paul G. Goerss and John F. Jardine “Simplicial homotopy theory” 174, Progress in Mathematics Birkhäuser Verlag, Basel, 1999, pp. xvi+510
- [10] Tom Goodwillie “A homotopy commutative diagram that cannot be strictified” (version: 2011-11-27), MathOverflow URL: https://mathoverflow.net/q/81962
- [11] Philip S. Hirschhorn “Model categories and their localizations” 99, Mathematical Surveys and Monographs American Mathematical Society, Providence, RI, 2003, pp. xvi+457
- [12] Mark Hovey “Model categories” 63, Mathematical Surveys and Monographs American Mathematical Society, Providence, RI, 1999, pp. xii+209
- [13] J. F. Jardine “Persistent homotopy theory”, 2020 arXiv:2002.10013
- [14] Masaki Kashiwara and Pierre Schapira “Persistent homology and microlocal sheaf theory” In Journal of Applied and Computational Topology 2.1-2 Springer ScienceBusiness Media LLC, 2018, pp. 83–113
- [15] Michael Lesnick “Multidimensional Interleavings and Applications to Topological Inference”, 2012
- [16] Michael Lesnick and Matthew Wright “Interactive Visualization of 2-D Persistence Modules”, 2015 arXiv:1512.00180
- [17] Facundo Mémoli “A Distance Between Filtered Spaces Via Tripods”, 2017 arXiv:1704.03965
- [18] Daniel G. Quillen “Homotopical algebra”, Lecture Notes in Mathematics, No. 43 Springer-Verlag, Berlin-New York, 1967, pp. iv+156 pp. (not consecutively paged)
- [19] Alexander Rolle and Luis Scoccola “Stable and consistent density-based clustering”, 2020 arXiv:2005.09048
- [20] Luis Scoccola “Locally Persistent Categories And Metric Properties Of Interleaving Distances”, 2020 URL: https://ir.lib.uwo.ca/etd/7119
- [21] Hirosi Toda “Composition methods in homotopy groups of spheres”, Annals of Mathematics Studies, No. 49 Princeton University Press, Princeton, N.J., 1962, pp. v+193