Rigidity for geometric ideals in uniform Roe algebras
Abstract.
In this paper, we investigate the rigidity problems for geometric ideals in uniform Roe algebras associated to discrete metric spaces of bounded geometry. These ideals were introduced by Chen and Wang, and can be fully characterised in terms of ideals in the associated coarse structures. Our main result is that if two geometric ideals in uniform Roe algebras are stably isomorphic, then the coarse spaces associated to these ideals are coarsely equivalent. We also discuss the case of ghostly ideals and pose some open questions.
Mathematics Subject Classification (2020): 47L20, 46L80, 51F30, 47L40.
Keywords: Uniform Roe algebras, Geometric ideals, Rigidity, Coarse equivalences
1. Introduction
Roe algebras are -algebras associated to metric spaces, which encode the coarse geometry of the underlying spaces. They were introduced by Roe in his pioneering work [16] to study higher indices of differential operators on open manifolds. There is also a uniform version of the Roe algebra, which has found applications in index theory (e.g.,[20]), -algebra theory (e.g., [14]), single operator theory (e.g., [22]) and even mathematical physics (e.g., [9]).
To provide a formal definition, consider a discrete metric space of bounded geometry (see Section 2.2). Thinking of an operator on as an -by- matrix , we say that has finite propagation if . The set of all finite propagation operators forms a -subalgebra of , and its norm closure is called the uniform Roe algebra of and denoted by .
Uniform Roe algebras have nice behaviour in coarse geometry. More precisely, recall that two metric spaces and are coarsely equivalent if there exist a map and functions with such that for any , we have
and there exists such that the -neighbourhood of equals . It is known (see, e.g., [4, Theorem 4]) that if and are coarsely equivalent, then their uniform Roe algebras are stably isomorphic in the sense that (where is the -algebra of compact operators on a separable infinite dimensional Hilbert space ).
Conversely, the rigidity problem concerns whether the coarse geometry of a metric space can be fully determined by the associated uniform Roe algebra, i.e., whether two metric spaces are coarsely equivalent if their uniform Roe algebras are (stably) isomorphic. This problem was initially studied by Špakula and Willett in [21], followed by a series of works in the last decade (e.g., [2, 3, 11]), and recently is completely solved by the profound work [1].
Due to the importance of uniform Roe algebras, Chen and Wang initiated the study of their ideal structures ([6, 7, 23]). They managed to obtain a full description for the ideal structure of the uniform Roe algebra when the underlying space has Yu’s Property A (from [25]). More precisely, they introduced a notion of geometric ideal and provided a detailed picture for these ideals. Let us recall the definition:
Definition A ([6, 23]).
An ideal in the uniform Roe algebra of a discrete metric space of bounded geometry is called geometric if the set of finite propagation operators in is dense in .
To state the characterisations for geometric ideals in [6], it is convenient to consult the notion of coarse spaces (see, e.g., [17, 18]). Recall that a coarse structure on a set is a collection of subsets of which is closed under the formation of subsets, inverses, products and finite unions (see Definition 2.1). For , we can also define the uniform Roe algebra similarly as in the metric space case while replacing finite propagation operators with those whose supports belong to (see Definition 2.5). In the case of a metric space , there is an associated coarse structure which is the smallest one containing the sets for all , and clearly we have .
In [6], the authors discovered that geometric ideals in for a metric space can be described in terms of ideals in the coarse structure . Recall that an ideal in is a coarse structure on which is closed under products by elements in (see Definition 2.6). The geometric ideal in associated to is , and this procedure provides an isomorphism between the lattice of geometric ideals in and the lattice of ideals in ([6, Theorem 6.3]). For convenience, we denote the ideal in associated to a geometric ideal in . Moreover, [6, Theorem 6.3] also shows that ideals in can be described using ideals in (see Definition 2.8). The ideal in associated to an ideal in is , where is the projection onto the first coordinate.
The main focus of this paper is to study the rigidity problem for geometric ideals in uniform Roe algebras of metric spaces. More precisely, we ask the following:
Question B (Rigidity for geometric ideals).
Let be discrete metric spaces of bounded geometry, and be geometric ideals in the uniform Roe algebras and , respectively. If and are (stably) isomorphic, do and have the same structure?
Our first task is to make the phrase “have the same structure” in a more precise way. Readers might wonder whether it is possible to use a similar notion of coarse equivalence as in the metric space case recalled above. This works well if the coarse structures contain the diagonals (see, e.g., Definition 2.4 and the paragraph thereafter). (Note that in [18, Definition 2.3], one requires that a coarse structure always contains the diagonal. While in [6, 19], it is necessary to consider the more general case.) However in the general case, there would be some issue if we only consider a single map (as in Definition 2.4) due to the lack of units in geometric ideals. More precisely, note that a nontrivial geometric ideal in does not bare a unit, and hence the associated ideal does not contain the diagonal.
To overcome this issue, we need to consult the notion of coarse equivalence for general coarse spaces introduced by Skandalis, Tu and Yu:
Definition C ([19, Definition 2.2]).
Let and be coarse spaces. A coarse correspondence from to is a coarse structure on which restricts to on , contains , and is generated by the elements contained in . A coarse equivalence between and is a coarse structure on which is a coarse correspondence from to and from to .
As noted in [19, Proposition 2.3] (see also Proposition 3.6 and Corollary 3.7), Definition C coincides with the notion of coarse equivalence recalled above in the metric space case. However, it seems inconvenient to use directly the language of coarse correspondence to treat the rigidity problem. Hence we unpack Definition C by means of families of maps and prove the following:
Proposition D (Corollary 3.24).
Two coarse spaces and are coarsely equivalent if and only if there exist coarse families (see Definition 3.14) of maps
such that and for any and .
Having established Proposition D, we manage to answer Question B completely. The following is the main result of this paper (see Section 4 and Section 6 for the missing definitions):
Theorem E.
Let and be discrete metric spaces of bounded geometry, and be geometric ideals in the uniform Roe algebras and , respectively. Consider the following conditions:
-
(1)
and are stably isomorphic;
-
(2)
and are coarsely equivalent;
-
(3)
and are Morita equivalent.
Then we have (1) (2) (3). Additionally if the associated ideals and are countably generated, then the three conditions above are all equivalent.
Note that “(2) (3)” is known to experts, and the key step is to prove “(1) (2)”. The strategy follows from that for [1, Theorem 1.4], which is the standard approach originated in [21]. However, there are technical issues due to the lack of units in geometric ideals. To overcome this, we discover concrete approximate units in geometric ideals (see Lemma 2.12), which have close relations to the coarse geometry of the underlying spaces and the associated ideals. Hence we can approximate a geometric ideal by a net of uniform Roe algebras of subspaces, and therefore manage to consult the proof in the unital case.
At this point, we would also like to highlight that Theorem E is not just an easy combination of results in [3, Section 4] and [1]. Recall that in [3], the rigidity problem was studied for general coarse spaces. Note that there is an extra hypothesis that coarse spaces are small in the sense of [3, Definition 4.2] to prove that rigid isomorphisms induce coarse equivalences. However in the current setting, coarse structures associated to geometric ideals might not be small in general. This obstructs us from directly using the techniques from [3, Section 4]. To overcome the issue, again we make use of the concrete approximate units to reduce to the unital case.
Also note that in a recent work [24], Wang and the second-named author introduced a notion of ghostly ideals and studied the ideal structure of uniform Roe algebras beyond the scope of Property A. We provide some discussions on the rigidity problems for ghostly ideals and pose some open questions.
The paper is organised as follows. In Section 2, we recall necessary background knowledge in coarse geometry and uniform Roe algebras. In Section 3, we study the notion of coarse equivalence for general coarse spaces (Definition C) and prove Proposition D. Section 4 to Section 6 are devoted to the proof for Theorem E. We record the proof for the easy direction “(2) (3)” in Section 4 and prove “(1) (2)” in Section 6. To make the argument in Section 6 more transparent, we prove a weak version of “(1) (2)” in Section 5. Finally, we provide some discussion on ghostly ideals in Section 7.
Acknowledgement
This project began during BJ’s visit to the School of Mathematical Sciences at Fudan University. BJ would like to express his gratitude to Prof. Xiaoman Chen and Yijun Yao for the invitation and coordination, and also to the faculty members for their hospitality and engaging discussions during his stay. We would also like to thank Rufus Willett for his comments after reading an early draft of this paper.
BJ was supported by NSFC12001066 and NSFC12071183. JZ was partly supported by National Key R&D Program of China 2022YFA100700.
2. Preliminaries
2.1. Standard notation
Here we collect the notation used throughout the paper.
For a set , denote the cardinality of and the set of all subsets in . For , denote the characteristic function of , and set for .
For a discrete space , denote the -algebra of bounded functions on with the supremum norm . The support of is defined to be , denoted by . Given a Hilbert space , denote the Hilbert space of square-summable functions from to . When , we denote , which has an orthonormal basis .
Given a Hilbert space , denote the -algebra of all bounded linear operators on , and the -subalgebra of all compact operators on .
2.2. Notions from coarse geometry
Here we collect necessary notions from coarse geometry, and guide readers to [13, 18] for more details.
First recall that for a set and , denote
Also denote the projection onto the first and the second coordinate, respectively. Given and , we say that and are -separated if and .
Definition 2.1.
A (connected) coarse structure on a set is a collection , called entourages, satisfying the following:
-
(1)
For any entourages and , then , and are entourages;
-
(2)
Every finite subset of is an entourage;
-
(3)
Any subset of an entourage is an entourage.
In this case, is called a coarse space. If additionally the diagonal
is an entourage, then (also the pair ) is called unital.
For and , denote the -neighbourhood of by
and
Definition 2.2.
A coarse structure on a set is said to have bounded geometry (or to be uniformly locally finite) if is finite for any entourage . In this case, we also say that the coarse space has bounded geometry.
For a set and a collection , the smallest coarse structure on containing is called the coarse structure generated by .
When is a discrete metric space, there is an associated unital coarse structure (called the bounded coarse structure) generated by all the -entourages defined as for all . In this case, we denote the closed ball by for and , and for and . We say that has bounded geometry if has bounded geometry, i.e., the number is finite for any .
Definition 2.3.
Let be sets, be a map and be a coarse structure on .
-
(1)
Denote , which is a coarse structure on . Here .
-
(2)
If is a coarse structure on , we say that is coarse if . To specify the underlying coarse structures, we also write .
-
(3)
Two coarse maps are said to be close if for any , we have .
Definition 2.4.
Let be a map between unital coarse spaces. We say that is a coarse equivalence if is coarse and there exists a coarse map (called a coarse inverse to ) such that is close to and is close to . In this case, we say that and are coarsely equivalent.
When and come from metric spaces, Definition 2.4 coincides with the one recalled in Section 1. Note that Definition 2.4 also makes sense for the general (non-unital) case, however, it does not work well for the rigidity problems (see Proposition D and Theorem E). It turns out that the suitable setting for the notion of coarse equivalence in the general case is Definition C. To obtain an appropriate picture, we will focus on Definition C in Section 3 based on an alternative version of coarse maps from [19].
2.3. Uniform Roe algebras and geometric ideals
Let be a set. Each operator can be written in the matrix form , where . Denote by the operator norm of in . Similarly for an operator , we can also write for .
Given an operator , we define the support of to be
Given , define the -support of to be
When is equipped with a metric , we define the propagation of to be
Definition 2.5.
Let be a coarse space of bounded geometry. The set of all operators in whose supports belong to forms a -algebra, called the algebraic uniform Roe algebra of and denoted by . The uniform Roe algebra of is defined to be the operator norm closure of in , which forms a -algebra and is denoted by .
When is a discrete metric space of bounded geometry, we simply write and .
For a coarse space of bounded geometry and , denote the rank-one operator by . It is clear that . This kind of operators will play an important role when we study the rigidity problems later.
In [6, 23], Chen and Wang introduced the notion of geometric ideals (see Definition A) in uniform Roe algebras and provided a full description for these ideals. Here we only focus on the case of metric spaces, which are the main objects we are interested in for the rigidity problem. (Note that geometric ideals for general coarse spaces were also studied in [6].) In the following, we always assume that is a discrete metric space of bounded geometry and is the associated bounded coarse structure.
Definition 2.6 ([6, Definition 4.1]).
A coarse structure is called an ideal in if for any and , we have and .
Proposition 2.7 ([6, Proposition 4.2]).
Given an ideal in , the uniform Roe algebra is a geometric ideal in . Conversely, given a geometric ideal in , the collection is an ideal in . Moreover, we have and .
We also need the following notion of ideals in space:
Definition 2.8 ([6, Definition 6.1]).
An ideal in is a collection satisfying the following:
-
(1)
If and , then ;
-
(2)
If and , then ;
-
(3)
If , then .
For , we say that is the ideal generated by if is the smallest ideal in containing .
Proposition 2.9 ([6, Proposition 6.2]).
Given an ideal in , the collection is an ideal in . Conversely, given an ideal in , the collection is an ideal in . Moreover, we have and .
Combining Proposition 2.7 and Proposition 2.9, we know that the lattice of geometric ideals in is isomorphic to the lattice of ideals in , which is also isomorphic to the lattice of ideals in . Hence we will drift among these three objects freely in the sequel.
Example 2.10.
As a special case, we consider the ideal of compact operators in the uniform Roe algebra for a discrete metric space . Note that is a geometric ideal, and it is easy to see that consists of all finite subsets of , and consists of all finite subsets of .
Remark 2.11.
We remark that the definition works for any (not necessarily geometric) ideal (see [6]) in the uniform Roe algebra . However, the one-to-one correspondence in Proposition 2.7 only works for geometric ideals. As an easy example, one can consider the ideal consisting of all ghost operators in . (Recall that an operator is a ghost operator if for any , there exists a finite subset such that for any , then .) One can calculate directly that , which consists of all finite subsets in .
Finally, we record an elementary observation which will be used later.
Lemma 2.12.
Let be an ideal in . Then the family is an approximate unit for the ideal .
Proof.
Note that is the direct limit of where is the uniform Roe algebra of the metric space with the induced metric of and is a direct set under inclusion. Since is the unit of , we conclude the proof. ∎
3. Coarse correspondence
In this section, we study the notion of coarse correspondence (Definition C) from [19] and provide a detailed picture for coarse equivalences between general coarse spaces (Proposition D).
Let be a set and . For , denote the restriction of on by
Recall from Definition C that for coarse spaces and , a coarse correspondence from to (or simply from to ) is a coarse structure on the disjoint union satisfying the following:
-
(1)
;
-
(2)
;
-
(3)
is generated by .
The following fact was implicitly stated in the proof of [19, Proposition 2.3]. It follows directly from condition (3) above, and hence we omit the proof.
Lemma 3.1.
Let and be coarse spaces, and be a coarse correspondence from to . Then for any , there exists such that .
We also record the following elementary fact, whose proof is straightforward.
Lemma 3.2.
For a set and , we have for .
3.1. The unital case
It was shown in [19] that for unital coarse spaces, the notion of coarse correspondence can be identified with coarse maps in Definition 2.3(2). Here we recall the outline of the proof, and divide it into several pieces to clarify the dependence on the assumption of unitalness. Some of the results will also be used in the general case.
Let be a set, be a coarse space and be a map. Denote
and
The following result is contained in the proof of [19, Proposition 2.3]. For the reader’s convenience, here we recall the proof.
Lemma 3.3.
Let be a set, be a coarse space and be a map. Then is a coarse structure on and generated by .
Proof.
Consider the map which restricts to on and on . It is easy to see that , and hence is a coarse structure on . For the second statement, it suffices to show that can be generated by . Given , it follows from Lemma 3.2 that for . It is clear that , and hence . Finally, note that , which concludes the proof. ∎
Consequently, we have the following:
Corollary 3.4.
Let and be coarse spaces, and be a map. Then is coarse if and only if is a coarse correspondence. In this case, we say that is the coarse correspondence associated to .
Recall that for a map , the graph of is defined to be
We have the following:
Lemma 3.5.
Let be a set, be a coarse space and be a map. Assume that the set belongs to . Then is generated by and .
Proof.
Since , we have . On the other hand, given , we have . Since , we conclude the proof thanks to Lemma 3.3. ∎
Now we present the following result from [19] that for unital coarse spaces, each coarse correspondence is determined by a coarse map. For the reader’s convenience, here we recall the proof.
Proposition 3.6 ([19, Proposition 2.3]).
Let and be coarse spaces, and be a coarse correspondence. Assume that is unital. Then there exists a unique (up to closeness) coarse map such that .
Proof.
By Lemma 3.1 and the assumption that is unital, there exists such that . It is easy to see that contains for some map . Note that . Hence it follows from Lemma 3.5 that .
On the other hand, given , we have . Since , then we obtain . Hence , which implies that is coarse thanks to Corollary 3.4.
Finally, if for coarse maps , then . Hence and are close. ∎
The following result shows that the notion of coarse equivalence from Definition C coincides with the one from Definition 2.4 for unital coarse spaces.
Corollary 3.7.
Let and be unital coarse spaces.
-
(1)
Let be a coarse equivalence with a coarse inverse . Then we have , which is a coarse correspondence both from to and from to . In this case, we have .
-
(2)
Let be a coarse correspondence from to and to . Let be a coarse map from Proposition 3.6 such that , and similarly be a coarse map such that . Then is a coarse equivalence with a coarse inverse .
Proof.
(1) is straightforward, and hence we omit the proof. For (2), it suffices to note that and similarly, . Hence we obtain the result. ∎
3.2. The general case
Now we move to the general case. Firstly, let us introduce the following notion:
Definition 3.8.
Let be a set and . We say that is admissible if the following holds:
-
(1)
Every finite subset of belongs to ;
-
(2)
For any and , then ;
-
(3)
For any , then .
The example of admissible collection we are interested in comes from coarse structures:
Definition 3.9.
Let be a coarse space. The collection
is called associated to , also denoted by , if the coarse structure is clear from the context.
Clearly associated to a coarse space is always admissible. When is a discrete metric space and is an ideal (in the sense of Definition 2.6), the definition for above coincides with the one in Proposition 2.9. In particular, any ideal in (in the sense of Definition 2.8) is admissible.
The following is straightforward, and hence we omit the proof.
Lemma 3.10.
Let be a coarse space, and be the associated collection. For , we have that if and only if the set belongs to .
To study the non-unital case, we need to consider a family of maps instead of a single map:
Definition 3.11.
Let be a set, be an admissible collection in and be a coarse space.
-
(1)
We say that a family of maps is admissible if for any , the set belongs to .
-
(2)
For an admissible family , denote
We also need to consider the relation of closeness between families:
Definition 3.12.
Let be a set, be an admissible collection in and be a coarse space. Two admissible families and are called close if for any , the set belongs to .
Lemma 3.13.
Let be a set and be an admissible collection in . Let be a coarse space, and be an admissible family. Then
-
(1)
For any , we have .
-
(2)
is a coarse structure on .
Proof.
(1). Since is admissible, the set for any . Hence we obtain .
(2). Given , assume that there exist such that and for . Take , then we have and . Note that for . Hence we have
for , which implies that . Also note that
The rest is trivial, and hence we omit the details. ∎
Now we introduce the notion of coarse family, which is the replacement of coarse maps in the general case.
Definition 3.14.
Let be coarse spaces and be an admissible collection in . A family of admissible maps is called coarse if .
It is clear from the definition that for a coarse family , we have . Note that we do not require in general.
Definition 3.15.
Let be a set and be an admissible collection in . Let be a coarse space and be an admissible family. Denote
and
We record the following elementary observation, whose proof is straightforward and hence omitted.
Lemma 3.16.
Given and as in Definition 3.15, we have the following:
-
(1)
For any , there exist and such that .
-
(2)
For and , if for and , then .
The following result is analogous to Lemma 3.3.
Lemma 3.17.
Given and as in Definition 3.15, then is a coarse structure on generated by .
Proof.
Firstly, we show that is a coarse structure on . Consider the admissible collection in . For any with and , define a map which restricts to on and on . Given with and for , we have
which belongs to due to Lemma 3.10. Hence is admissible.
Moreover, belongs to if and only if there exists with and such that and , which is equivalent to that thanks to Lemma 3.16. Hence we conclude that , which is a coarse structure on due to Lemma 3.13(2).
The rest of the proof is similar to that for Lemma 3.3, and hence we omit the details. ∎
Consequently, we obtain the following:
Corollary 3.18.
Let be coarse spaces, be an admissible collection in and be a family of admissible maps. Then is coarse if and only if is a coarse correspondence. In this case, we say that is the coarse correspondence associated to .
Similar to Lemma 3.5, we have the following:
Lemma 3.19.
Given and as in Definition 3.15, then is generated by and .
Proof.
Note that for any , we have and hence . Now given , there exists such that and . Hence we have , where . Therefore we conclude the proof thanks to Lemma 3.17. ∎
Now we are in the position to provide a detailed picture for coarse correspondence in the general case. This is a crucial step to achieve Proposition D.
Proposition 3.20.
Let be coarse spaces, and be a coarse correspondence from to . Then there exist an admissible collection and an admissible family of maps such that . Moreover, such a family is unique up to closeness.
Proof.
Set , which is clearly admissible. For any , Lemma 3.10 shows that . By Lemma 3.1, there exists such that . Hence there exists a map such that . For , we have
which implies that the family is admissible. Applying Lemma 3.19, we obtain that .
Conversely, we claim that . In fact, for any , note that and . For any , Lemma 3.1 implies that there exists such that , and hence . This concludes the claim. Now given , the claim implies that there exists such that . Then . Hence we obtain that .
The last statement is easy to prove, and hence we omit the details. ∎
Finally, we consider the notion of coarse equivalence from Definition C. Recall that a coarse equivalence between two coarse spaces and is a coarse correspondence from both to and to . We say that and are coarsely equivalent if there exists a coarse equivalence between and .
Now we would like to apply Proposition 3.20 to unpack Definition C using families of maps, and our main target is to prove Proposition D. To make it more clear, we divide into two parts.
Corollary 3.21.
Let be coarse spaces, and be a coarse equivalence between them. Then there exist coarse families and such that and satisfy the following:
(3.1) |
and
(3.2) |
In this case, we have and .
The proof is similar to that for Corollary 3.7 using Proposition 3.20 instead, and hence we omit the proof.
Corollary 3.22.
Proof.
Firstly, we show that . Since is a coarse family, we have . Conversely given , there exists such that and . Take , which belongs to by Lemma 3.13. Then being coarse implies:
Hence
which concludes that . Similarly, we have .
Definition 3.23.
Consequently, Corollary 3.21 and Corollary 3.22 can be rewritten in the following form, which concludes Proposition D.
Corollary 3.24.
Finally, we discuss the condition of bounded geometry, which will be used in the next section.
Lemma 3.25.
Let and be coarse spaces of bounded geometry, and be a coarse equivalence between them. Then also has bounded geometry as a coarse structure on .
Proof.
For , and , denote
It suffices to show that for , the number and are finite. Note that
Hence we have
Note that and . Hence we conclude the proof since and have bounded geometry. ∎
4. Coarse equivalences induce Morita equivalences
In this section, we recall the known result that a coarse equivalence between coarse spaces induces a Morita equivalence between the associated uniform Roe algebras. As a special case, we obtain the proof for Theorem E “(2) (3)”. Here we provide a detailed proof since similar idea will be used later to treat ghostly ideals (see Section 7).
Firstly, let us recall the following notion of Morita equivalence for -algebras due to Rieffel ([15], see also [8, Definition 2.5.2]).
Definition 4.1.
Let and be -algebras. An - imprimitivity bimodule is a Banach space that carries the structure of both a right Hilbert -module with -inner product and a left Hilbert -module with -inner product satisfying the following:
-
(1)
Both inner products on are full, i.e., and ;
-
(2)
for all ;
-
(3)
The actions of and on commutes.
Say that and are Morita equivalent if such an - imprimitivity bimodule exists.
Also recall from Section 1 that two -algebras and are stably isomorphic if is -isomorphic to , where is a separable infinite dimensional Hilbert space. It was proved in [5] (see also [10, Chapter 7]) that if and are -unital (i.e., they admit countable approximate units), then and are Morita equivalent if and only if they are stably isomorphic.
Let us restate Theorem E “(2) (3)” in a more general form as follows:
Proposition 4.2.
Let and be coarse spaces of bounded geometry which are coarsely equivalent. Then the uniform Roe algebras and are Morita equivalent. Additionally if and are unital, then and are stably isomorphic.
This can be proved essentially by combining [19, Corollary 3.6] and [12, Theorem 2.8] (where second countability is assumed) using the notion of Morita equivalence for groupoids. Also note that the metric space case was proved directly in [4, Theorem 4]. For the reader’s convenience, here we provide a direct proof for the general case.
Proof of Proposition 4.2.
Let be a coarse equivalence between and , which is a coarse structure on . For simplicity, denote and . Define to be the norm closure of
in , which is a left -module as well as a right -module under composition of operators. Also define the inner products
and
It is straightforward to check that is a right Hilbert -module as well as a left Hilbert -module with commuting actions of and on . Moreover, we have
for all .
It remains to show that both inner products are full. Given , denote . It follows from Lemma 3.1 that there exists such that . Hence contains a graph of a map . Thanks to Lemma 3.25, we can apply [18, Lemma 4.10] to write as a finite union of for where each is an injective map. Moreover, we can further assume that are mutually disjoint.
For each , we set , which is regarded as a bounded operator from to . Note that , and hence . Moreover, for each , we have . Hence
which concludes that the inner -product is full. Similarly, we obtain that the inner -product is also full. Hence is an - imprimitivity bimodule, which concludes that and are Morita equivalent. ∎
5. Rigidity for geometric ideals
In this section and the next, we focus on the rigidity problem for geometric ideals and prove Theorem E “(1) (2)”, which is the main task of this paper. To make the proof more transparent, we prove a weak version in this section. The proof is relatively easier, while contains almost all the necessary ingredients to treat the general case.
Recall that for an ideal in the uniform Roe algebra of a discrete metric space of bounded geometry, the associated coarse structure is from Proposition 2.7. We aim to prove the following:
Theorem 5.1.
Let be discrete metric spaces of bounded geometry, and be geometric ideals in the uniform Roe algebras and , respectively. Assume that and are isomorphic. Then the coarse spaces and are coarsely equivalent.
The proof of Theorem 5.1 is divided into two parts. We follow the outline of [1], while requiring more techniques to overcome the issue of lacking units.
Throughout the rest of this section, let be discrete metric spaces of bounded geometry, and be geometric ideals in the uniform Roe algebras and , respectively. Denote the associated ideal in by , and the associated ideal in by (from Proposition 2.7 and 2.9). Similarly, denote and . Also let be an isomorphism.
5.1. Rigid isomorphisms for geometric ideals
Firstly, recall that the isomorphism can always be spatially implemented. The proof is similar to that for [21, Lemma 3.1] based on the representation theory for compact operators together with the fact that finite subsets are entourages, and hence we omit the details.
Lemma 5.2.
There exists a unitary such that for any .
In [3], the authors introduced a notion of rigid isomorphism which plays a key role to attack the rigidity problem. The idea can be traced back to the work [21]. We introduce the following to deal with the non-unital case.
Definition 5.3.
With the same notation as above, the isomorphism is called a rigid isomorphism if can be spatially implemented by a unitary satisfying:
and
In this case, we say that and are rigidly isomorphic.
The first step to attack the rigidity problem is the following (comparing [3, Theorem 4.12]):
Proposition 5.4.
With the same notation as above, assume that and is rigidly isomorphic. Then the coarse spaces and are coarsely equivalent.
To prove Proposition 5.4, we need some preparations.
Definition 5.5 ([3, Definition 4.3]).
Let be a discrete metric of bounded geometry, and . An operator is called --approximable if there exists with propagation at most such that .
The following key “equi-approximability lemma” was originally obtained in [3, Section 4] (see also [1, Lemma 1.9]), which will be used frequently in the sequel.
Lemma 5.6.
Let be a discrete metric of bounded geometry, and be a sequence of operators such that - converges to an element in for all . Then for all , there exists such that - is --approximable for all .
We also need the following lemma, which is analogous to [3, Lemma 4.11]. As explained in Section 1, it is unclear whether the coarse structures and are small in the sense of [3, Definition 4.2]. This obstructs us from using the results in [3, Section 4] directly, and hence more techniques are required.
Lemma 5.7.
With the notation as above, for any and , the following set
belongs to .
Proof.
Suppose otherwise. Then there exist and such that . Hence for any , we have . Note that subsets of any entourage are entourages (see Definition 2.1(3)), so we have . Therefore, we can find and such that and while . Ordering by inclusion, it follows from [3, Lemma 4.10] that there exist cofinal , and a map such that
-
(1)
and for all ;
-
(2)
and for all .
Since elements in are distinct, then is countable. For , condition (1) and having bounded geometry imply that - with support in . Hence -- belongs to since is -continuous. Applying Lemma 5.6, for there exists such that - is --approximable for all . In particular, we have
(5.1) |
for all and with .
By Proposition 2.9, we can assume that for some . Since is an approximate unit for due to Lemma 2.12, there exist such that
Thus, we have
Setting , it is clear that . For all which are -separated, then . Hence
where the penultimate inequality comes from (5.1). Since is cofinal in , we can assume that .
Then we have
On the other hand, a direct calculation shows that
which leads to a contradiction. ∎
Now we are in the position to prove Proposition 5.4.
Proof of Proposition 5.4.
Let be a unitary operator which spatially implements the rigid isomorphism . Hence:
-
•
for any , there exist and such that
-
•
for any , there exist and such that
We aim to show that the families and provide a coarse equivalence between and in the sense of Definition 3.23, and hence conclude the proof thanks to Corollary 3.24.
Firstly, we show that the families and are coarse. For , consider the set , which is contained in . By Lemma 5.7, the set belongs to . Hence is admissible.
Given , we can assume that for some thanks to Proposition 2.9. Then for any , it follows from the definition that . In other words, we obtain , where the latter belongs to due to Lemma 5.7. Hence we have , which concludes that the family is coarse. Similarly, we obtain that the family is also coarse. Moreover by Lemma 3.13, we have for any , and for any .
5.2. From isomorphisms to rigid isomorphisms
Now we prove that any isomorphism between geometric ideals is always a rigid isomorphism, and hence conclude the proof for Theorem 5.1. We will follow the outline of the proof for [1, Theorem 1.2] with the following extra piece:
Lemma 5.8.
With that notation as above, for any and , there exist such that .
Proof.
By Lemma 2.12, is an approximate unit for . Hence, is an approximate unit for , which concludes the proof. ∎
Proposition 5.9.
With the same notation as above, assume that and are isomorphic. Then they are rigidly isomorphic.
Proof.
Fixing and , take as in Lemma 5.8. Consider , which is a sequence of orthogonal projections in and satisfies the condition in Lemma 5.6. Hence, there is such that
is --approximable for any .
Set . It follows from Lemma 5.8 that for any , we have
(5.2) |
Taking , we denote
Let be the canonical orthogonal projection. Define by
Then we have for all .
Since belongs to the convex hull of the range of and has real dimension at most , [1, Lemma 2.1] implies that there exists such that
(5.3) |
Moreover,
(5.4) | ||||
Since and are --approximable, the convex combination is also --approximable. Hence we have
(5.5) |
Using the fact that together with (5.3)-(5.5), we obtain
Hence [1, Lemma 3.1] implies that . Moreover, note that
Hence combining (5.2), we obtain .
Taking , we have . Set , then is non-empty for any . Hence we obtain
Finally, note that
Hence is a rigid isomorphism. ∎
6. Rigidity for stable geometric ideals
Now we move to the case of stable isomorphism and finish the proof of Theorem E “(1) (2)”. Recall that given a coarse space of bounded geometry, the stable uniform Roe algebra of is defined to be
where is a separable infinite dimensional Hilbert space. Note that can be regarded as a -subalgebra of . Similar to the case of the uniform Roe algebra, there is a dense -subalgebra in under this viewpoint. More precisely, an operator belongs to if and only if its support (similar to the definition in Section 2.3) belongs to and there exists a finite-dimensional subspace such that each matrix entry belongs to .
Hence Theorem E “(1) (2)” can be rewritten as follows:
Theorem 6.1.
Let be discrete metric spaces of bounded geometry, and be geometric ideals in the uniform Roe algebras and , respectively. Assume that the stable geometric ideals and are isomorphic. Then the coarse spaces and are coarsely equivalent.
The proof is similar to that for Theorem 5.1 but more technical, which follows the outline of that for [1, Theorem 4.1]. Again throughout the rest of this section, let be discrete metric spaces of bounded geometry, and be geometric ideals in the uniform Roe algebras and , respectively. Denote and . Also let be an isomorphism with the inverse .
Firstly, we have the following analogue of Proposition 5.9.
Proposition 6.2.
With the same notation as above, for any unit vector the following holds:
-
(1)
for any , there exist and a finite-rank projection on such that
-
(2)
for any , there exist and a finite-rank projection on such that
Here is the orthogonal projection from onto .
The proof is similar to that for [1, Theorem 4.1] (with the same idea presented in the proof of Proposition 5.9), and hence we only provide a sketch here.
Sketch of proof for Proposition 6.2.
Note that the set
is an approximate unit for . Hence given and , there exists and a finite dimensional projection on such that
Therefore, we have
This provides a similar condition as in the hypothesis of [1, Lemma 4.3], which allows us to apply the same argument therein to obtain a constant and a map satisfying
Hence we obtain (1), and (2) can be treated similarly. ∎
Now we show that the conditions in Proposition 6.2 imply the required coarse equivalence, analogous to Proposition 5.4.
Proposition 6.3.
To prove Proposition 6.3, first note that there exists a unitary such that for any , which is similar to Lemma 5.2. Analogous to Lemma 5.7, we also need the following lemma:
Lemma 6.4.
With the notation as above, for any and a finite dimensional subspace , the following set
belongs to .
The proof for Lemma 6.4 is similar to that for Lemma 5.7 with minor modifications, and hence we only provide a sketch to explain the difference.
Sketch of proof for Lemma 6.4.
Suppose otherwise. Then there exist and a finite dimensional subspace such that . Therefore for any , we can find , unit vectors and unit vectors such that
for , while . Note that are unit vectors in and is finite dimensional. Hence after a small perturbation, we can assume that the set is finite. Ordering by inclusion, it follows from [3, Lemma 4.10] that there exist cofinal , and a map such that
-
(1)
and for all ;
-
(2)
, , and for all .
The rest is similar to that of Lemma 5.7, and hence we omit the details. ∎
Proof of Proposition 6.3.
As remarked above, there exists a unitary such that for any . Fix a unit vector . Direct calculations show that conditions in Proposition 6.2 can be translated as follows:
-
•
for any , there exist , and a finite-rank projection on such that for any , there exists a unit vector satisfying:
-
•
for any , there exist , and a finite-rank projection on such that for any , there exists a unit vector satisfying:
We aim to show that the families and provide a coarse equivalence between and , and hence conclude the proof thanks to Corollary 3.24.
Firstly, we show that the families and are coarse. For , consider the set , which is contained in . By Lemma 6.4, the set belongs to . Hence is admissible.
Given , we can assume that for some thanks to Proposition 2.9. Then for any , it follows that . Hence we have , which concludes that the family is coarse. Similarly, we obtain that the family is also coarse.
Finally, we study the -unitalness of geometric ideals and prove the last sentence in Theorem E. Recall from [24, Definition 7.15] that an ideal in a metric space is countably generated if there exists a countable subset such that is generated by .
Lemma 6.5.
Let be a discrete metric space of bounded geometry and be a countably generated ideal in . Then the geometric ideal is -unital.
Proof.
Since is countably generated, it follows from [24, Lemma 7.17] that there exists a countable subset of such that . It is then easy to see that is an approximate unit for , i.e., is -unital. ∎
7. Discussions on ghostly ideals
In [24], Wang and the second-named author introduced a notion of ghostly ideals in uniform Roe algebras. Here we provide some discussions on the rigidity problem for ghostly ideals and pose some open questions. Recall the following:
Definition 7.1 ([24]).
Let be a discrete metric space of bounded geometry, and be an ideal in . The associated ghostly ideal of , denoted by , is defined as follows:
Similar to the situation for geometric ideals, we would also like to study isomorphisms between ghostly ideals. More precisely, similar to the discussions in Section 4 to Section 6, we pose the following questions:
Question 7.2.
Let be discrete metric spaces of bounded geometry, and be ideals in and , respectively.
-
(1)
If and are coarsely equivalent (in the sense of Definition C), are and Morita equivalent?
-
(2)
Conversely, if and are isomorphic (or stably isomorphic), are and coarsely equivalent?
Unfortunately, currently we are unable to completely answer either of these questions. We merely manage to provide a partial answer to Question 7.2(1). To state our result, we need some preparations.
Let be a coarse equivalence with a coarse inverse , and be an ideal in . Denote the ideal in generated by the set . Then we have:
Lemma 7.3.
With the same notation as above, we have . Hence in this case, the maps and provide a one-to-one correspondence between ideals in and those in .
Proof.
Firstly, note that for any , which implies that . Conversely, it suffices to show that for any . Given , It follows from [24, Lemma 7.18] that there exist and such that . Hence , which belongs to since is coarse. So we conclude the proof. ∎
As a direct corollary, we obtain the following:
Corollary 7.4.
Let be a coarse equivalence and be an ideal in . Then the family is a coarse equivalence (in the sense of Definition 3.23) between and .
Now we present our partial answer to Question 7.2(1):
Proposition 7.5.
Let be discrete metric spaces of bounded geometry, and be ideals in and , respectively. If is a coarse equivalence with , then and are Morita equivalent.
Remark 7.6.
Proof of Proposition 7.5.
Let be a coarse equivalence and the associated coarse correspondence. Similar to the proof of Proposition 4.2, we define to be the norm closure of
in , which is a left -module as well as a right -module under composition of operators. Writing and , we set . Also define the inner products
and
It is straightforward to check that is a right Hilbert -module as well as a left Hilbert -module with commuting actions of and on . We will show that provides a Morita equivalence between and .
Firstly, we claim that where . Given with support in and , there exists such that
Hence for , we have
Denote . Then for any and , there exist and such that
Since , there exists such that . Hence we obtain
Therefore by Lemma 7.3 and the assumption that , we obtain that
which implies that and concludes the claim.
Now we claim that . Taking a coarse inverse to , we decompose into a finite union of for such that each is an injective map with mutually disjoint. For each , define , which is regarded as a bounded operator from to . Clearly, we have , and . Hence for and , we have
where the last containment follows from the previous paragraph. By symmetry, we conclude . Consequently, we obtain .
Finally, we remark that it seems that the proof of Proposition 7.5 does not work if we only know that and are coarsely equivalent instead of requiring a global coarse equivalence from to .
References
- [1] Florent P. Baudier, Bruno M. Braga, Ilijas Farah, Ana Khukhro, Alessandro Vignati, and Rufus Willett. Uniform Roe algebras of uniformly locally finite metric spaces are rigid. Invent. Math., 230(3):1071–1100, 2022.
- [2] Bruno M. Braga, Yeong Chyuan Chung, and Kang Li. Coarse Baum-Connes conjecture and rigidity for Roe algebras. J. Funct. Anal., 279(9):108728, 21, 2020.
- [3] Bruno M. Braga and Ilijas Farah. On the rigidity of uniform Roe algebras over uniformly locally finite coarse spaces. Trans. Amer. Math. Soc., 374(2):1007–1040, 2021.
- [4] Jacek Brodzki, Graham A. Niblo, and Nick J. Wright. Property A, partial translation structures, and uniform embeddings in groups. J. Lond. Math. Soc. (2), 76(2):479–497, 2007.
- [5] Lawrence G. Brown, Philip Green, and Marc A. Rieffel. Stable isomorphism and strong Morita equivalence of -algebras. Pacific J. Math., 71(2):349–363, 1977.
- [6] Xiaoman Chen and Qin Wang. Ideal structure of uniform Roe algebras of coarse spaces. J. Funct. Anal., 216(1):191 – 211, 2004.
- [7] Xiaoman Chen and Qin Wang. Ghost ideals in uniform Roe algebras of coarse spaces. Arch. Math. (Basel), 84(6):519–526, 2005.
- [8] Joachim Cuntz, Siegfried Echterhoff, Xin Li, and Guoliang Yu. -theory for group -algebras and semigroup -algebras, volume 47 of Oberwolfach Seminars. Birkhäuser/Springer, Cham, 2017.
- [9] Eske Ellen Ewert and Ralf Meyer. Coarse geometry and topological phases. Comm. Math. Phys., 366(3):1069–1098, 2019.
- [10] E. Christopher Lance. Hilbert -modules, volume 210 of London Mathematical Society Lecture Note Series. Cambridge University Press, Cambridge, 1995.
- [11] Kang Li, Ján Špakula, and Jiawen Zhang. Measured asymptotic expanders and rigidity for Roe algebras. Int. Math. Res. Not., (17):15102–15154, 2023.
- [12] Paul S. Muhly, Jean N. Renault, and Dana P. Williams. Equivalence and isomorphism for groupoid -algebras. J. Operator Theory, 17(1):3–22, 1987.
- [13] Piotr W. Nowak and Guoliang Yu. Large scale geometry. EMS Textbooks in Mathematics. European Mathematical Society (EMS), Zürich, 2012.
- [14] Narutaka Ozawa. Amenable actions and exactness for discrete groups. C. R. Acad. Sci. Paris Sér. I Math., 330(8):691–695, 2000.
- [15] Marc A. Rieffel. Morita equivalence for operator algebras. In Operator algebras and applications, Part 1 (Kingston, Ont., 1980), volume 38 of Proc. Sympos. Pure Math., pages 285–298. Amer. Math. Soc., Providence, RI, 1982.
- [16] John Roe. An index theorem on open manifolds. I, II. J. Differential Geom., 27(1):87–113, 115–136, 1988.
- [17] John Roe. Coarse cohomology and index theory on complete Riemannian manifolds, volume 497. Amer. Math. Soc., 1993.
- [18] John Roe. Lectures on coarse geometry, volume 31 of University Lecture Series. Amer. Math. Soc., Providence, RI, 2003.
- [19] Georges Skandalis, Jean-Louis Tu, and Guoliang Yu. The coarse Baum-Connes conjecture and groupoids. Topology, 41(4):807–834, 2002.
- [20] Ján Špakula. Uniform -homology theory. J. Funct. Anal., 257(1):88–121, 2009.
- [21] Ján Špakula and Rufus Willett. On rigidity of Roe algebras. Adv. Math., 249:289–310, 2013.
- [22] Ján Špakula and Rufus Willett. A metric approach to limit operators. Trans. Amer. Math. Soc., 369(1):263–308, 2017.
- [23] Qin Wang. Remarks on ghost projections and ideals in the Roe algebras of expander sequences. Arch. Math. (Basel), 89(5):459–465, 2007.
- [24] Qin Wang and Jiawen Zhang. Ghostly ideals in uniform Roe algebras. arXiv preprint arXiv:2301.04921, 2023.
- [25] Guoliang Yu. The coarse Baum-Connes conjecture for spaces which admit a uniform embedding into Hilbert space. Invent. Math., 139(1):201–240, 2000.