Trace formalism for motivic cohomology
-
-
scAbstract. A goal of this paper is to construct trace maps for the six functor formalism of motivic cohomology after Voevodsky, Ayoub, and Cisinski–Déglise. We also construct an -enhancement of such a trace formalism. In the course of the -enhancement, we need to reinterpret the trace formalism in a more functorial manner. This is done by using Suslin–Voevodsky’s relative cycle groups.
scKeywords. Motivic cohomology, Trace map, infinity enhancement
sc2020 Mathematics Subject Classification. 14F42, 18N60
-
-
cOctober 4, 2022Received by the Editors on June 27, 2022.
Accepted on November 18, 2022.
Kavli Institute for the Physics and Mathematics of the Universe (WPI), University of Tokyo, 5-1-5 Kashiwanoha, Kashiwa, Chiba, 277-8583, Japan
sce-mail: tomoyuki.abe@ipmu.jp
This work is supported by JSPS KAKENHI Grant Numbers 16H05993, 18H03667, 20H01790.
© by the author(s) This work is licensed under http://creativecommons.org/licenses/by-sa/4.0/
1. Introduction
Let be a flat morphism of dimension between schemes of finite type over a field . Let be a torsion ring in which the exponential characteristic of is invertible. In [SGA4, Exposé XVIII, Théorème 2.9], the trace map satisfying various functorial properties is constructed. Here, the cohomological functors are taken for the étale topoi. Furthermore, the trace map is characterized by such functorialities. This trace map is fundamentally important, and for example, it is used to construct the cycle class map. In other words, we may view the trace formalism as a device to throw cycle-theoretic information into the cohomological framework. The main goal of this paper is to construct an analogous map for the motivic cohomology of Voevodsky, and its -enhancement. The -enhancement of the trace formalism will serve as an interface between “actual cycle” and “-enhancement of motivic cohomology” in [Abe22b].
Let us explain the method to construct the trace formalism. From now on, we consider the six functor formalism of the motivic cohomology theory with coefficients in , where is the characteristic of our base field . The principle that makes the construction of the trace map work is the observation that the higher homotopies vanish. More precisely, we have
(1.1) |
for . A benefit of this vanishing is that if we take an open subscheme such that is dense for any , then constructing and constructing are equivalent. In [SGA4], this property is used ingeniously to reduce the construction to simpler situations. Another benefit which is more important for us is that the vanishing allows us to construct the map “locally”. Namely, by the vanishing, constructing is equivalent to constructing a morphism of sheaves. In the case of étale cohomology, since it admits proper descent, by de Jong’s alteration theorem, the construction is reduced to the case where is smooth. We note that we commonly use de Jong’s alteration theorem to reduce proving properties to smooth cases, but to reduce constructions to smooth cases needs control of higher homotopies, which requires great amount of effort in general. In the case where is smooth, the construction is easy because we have an isomorphism , where is the structural morphism for and , using the relative Poincaré duality, namely the isomorphism . In the case of étale cohomology, in [SGA4], the relative Poincaré duality theorem is established by using the trace formalism, and the argument we explained here is somewhat circular. However, in the theory of motives, the relative Poincaré duality follows from theorems of Morel–Voevodsky, Ayoub, and Cisinski–Déglise which use completely different methods, and the above argument actually works.
Now, assume we wish to enhance the trace map -categorically. The first question that immediately comes up with is that what it means by “-enhancement” in this situation. To address the question, we need a reinterpretion of the trace map, and to motivate our reinterpretation, let us discuss a defect of traditional formalism. Let be a flat morphism between non-reduced schemes such that is not flat. In this situation, we have the trace map . However, since motivic or étale cohomology is insensitive to nil-immersions, induces a similar map for . This observation gives us an impression that the trace map should be associated with a “cycle” rather than a “scheme”. To realize this idea, we use the relative cycle group of Suslin and Voevodsky. For a morphism , they defined a group denoted by which is a certain subgroup of the group of cycles in equidimensional of dimension over (see [SV]). When is flat of dimension , the cycle is an element of . Using these observations, we show that there exists a morphism for any , such that, when is flat of dimension , the image of is the traditional trace map. The object is often called the Borel–Moore homology, and is denoted by . Note that we are considering it as an object of the derived category (or as a spectrum). The associations and to are functorial with respect to the base changes of and pushforwards along proper morphisms over . These functorialities yield (-)functors from a certain category to the -category of spectra . The -enhancement of the trace map can be formulated as a natural transform between these -functors, and we will show the existence of such an -functor in the last section. This -enhancement of the trace map is one of the crucial ingredients in [Abe22b].
Before concluding the introduction, let us present the organization of this paper. In Section 2, we recall the six functor formalism of the theory of motives after Voevodsky, Ayoub, Cisinski–Déglise. In Section 3, we formulate our main result. To describe the functoriality of and above, it is convenient to use the language of “bivariant theory” after Fulton–MacPherson. We start by recalling such a theory, and we state our main theorem. We conclude this section by showing an analogue of (1.1) in the motivic setting. In Section 4, we construct the trace map in the case where the base scheme is smooth. In Section 5, we construct the trace map in general and show the main result. In Section 6, we establish the -enhancement. We note that, even though we use the language of -categories throughout the paper for convenience and coherence, it is straightforward to formulate and prove the results of Sections 2 to 5 using the language of model categories, as in [CD15, CD19]. Using the language of -categories is more essential in Section 6.
Acknowledgment
The author is grateful to Deepam Patel for numerous discussions, without which this paper would not have been written. He wishes to thank Adeel Kahn for various helpful comments on the paper. Especially, Remark 3.6-(5) is due to him. He also thanks Frédéric Déglise for answering several questions, and Shane Kelly for some discussions. Finally, he wishes to thank the referee for reading the manuscript very carefully, and gave him numerous comments which helped to improve the quality of the paper.
Notation and conventions
We fix a perfect field of characteristic . By -category, we always mean -category, and by category we always mean -category. For a scheme , we denote by the category of schemes separated of finite type over . When , we often denote this by .
2. Review of six functors
2.1.
We will use the language of -categories, but except for §6, this is used just to facilitate the presentation. See the remark at the end of this paragraph for some explanation.
Let be the full subcategory of (cf. [Lur09, Definition 5.5.3.1]) spanned by stable -categories. We have the functor sending to Voevodsky-Morel’s stable homotopy -category (cf. [CD15, §2.1] or [CD19, Example 1.4.3] for model categorical treatment and [Abe22a, §6.7] and references therein for -categorical treatment). Let be a commutative ring. Then Voevodsky defined the motivic Eilenberg-MacLane spectrum , which is an -algebra of . By pulling back, this spectrum yields a spectrum on , and defines an “absolute ring -spectrum” in the sense of [Deg18, Definition 1.1.1]. The absolute ring -spectrum is equipped with an “orientation” in the sense of [Deg18, Definition 2.2.2] by [Deg18, Example 2.2.4]. Under this situation, all the results of [Deg18, Introduction, Theorem 1] can be applied. We do not try to recall the definitions of each terminology, but instead, we sketch what we can get by fixing these data.
We put , the symmetric monoidal -category of -module objects in . Then the assignment to can be promoted to a functor which yields “motivic categories” in the sense of [CD19]. This can be checked from [CD19, Proposition 5.3.1 and Proposition 7.2.18]. We may find a summary of the axioms of what this means in [Abe22a, §6.1], and also references. Among other things, we may use “six functors”. In this -categorical context, we can find a construction of six functor formalism in [Abe22a, §6.8], which follows the idea of [Kha16]. Let . Then is a symmetric monoidal stable -category. Given a morphism in , the functor induces the functor , which we denote by in accordance with the six functor formalism of Grothendieck. The functor admits a right adjoint, which we denote by . We also have the “extraordinary pushforward functor” as well as its right adjoint . We have the natural transform which is an isomorphism when is proper.
The orientation on yields an orientation on in the sense of [CD19, Definition 2.4.12] by [CD19, Example 2.4.40] and [Deg18, §2.2.5]. For , we denote the -th Tate twist by , the -th shift by , and by . We often denote the unit object of by T. By fixing an orientation, we have a canonical isomorphism for any smooth morphism in (cf. [CD19, Theorem 2.4.50]). In fact, the fundamental class constructed in [Deg18, Introduction, Theorem 1] can be seen as a generalization of this isomorphism.
Remark.
If the reader feels uncomfortable with using -categories, it is essentially harmless to replace by the the -category of triangulated categories above. Then, we may regard as a triangulated category. The only exception might be that when we consider descents. In order to consider descents inside the traditional framework, we need to introduce the category of diagrams as in [CD19, §3]. Therefore, strictly speaking, simply considering the functor is not enough for the theory of descent. We leave the details to the interested reader.
2.2.
Let . For , we set
Here, we view as a spectrum. When the coefficient ring is obvious, we abbreviate by . We write for , and call it the Borel-Moore homology. Note that coincides with in [Deg18]. Assume we are given a closed subscheme and denote the complement by . By localization sequence of 6-functor formalism, we have the long exact sequence
2.3.
We introduce the dh-topology as follows.
Definition.
We define dh-topology on to be the topology generated by the following two types of families:
-
(1)
, where is finite surjective flat morphism of constant degree power of ;
-
(2)
cdh-covering.
We call dh-topology what is called dh-topology in [CD15, §5.2]. Obviously, cdh-topology is coarser than dh-topology, and dh-topology is coarser than dh-topology for any .
Let be an object of . Recall that the theorem of Temkin [T], which is a refinement of Gabber’s prime-to- alteration theorem, states as follows: there exists an alteration whose generic degree is some power of and is smooth. Without Temkin’s theorem, dh-topology might have been useless, but armed with the theorem, we can show the following statement as usual.
Lemma.
For any , there exists a dh-covering such that is a smooth -scheme. We may even take to be proper.
Proof.
Even though the argument is standard, we recall a proof for the sake of completeness. We use the induction on the dimension of . Using Temkin’s theorem, take an alteration whose generic degree is power to and is smooth. By using Gruson-Raynaud’s flattening theorem, we may take a modification with center such that the strict transform of is flat over . By construction is finite surjective flat morphism whose degree is power to , and thus, is a dh-covering. By induction hypothesis, we may find a proper dh-covering such that is smooth. Because is a dh-covering, is also a dh-covering. This covering factors through , so the latter is a dh-covering as well. Thus, we may simply take . ∎
For any , we may find a dh-hypercovering such that is -smooth by standard use of the lemma above and [SGA4, Exposé , Proposition 5.1.3].
2.4.
We have the following dh-descent, which is a straightforward corollary of a dh-descent result by S. Kelly.
Lemma.
Assume . Then any object of satisfies dh-descent. In other words, if we are given a dh-hypercovering and , the canonical morphism in the -category is an equivalence.
Proof.
Let . We wish to show that , and for this, it suffices to show that for any prime (cf. [CD15, proof of Proposition 3.13]). To show this, we must show that for any compact object , we have . We have
We may further compute as
where the and equivalences follow from the compactness of and respectively. By [CD15, Theorem 5.10], admits dh-descent, in particular, dh-descent. Thus, combining with the computations above, we have as desired. ∎
Now, let . Then we have
We write . Assume that for any . Then the complex of -indexed diagrams belongs to , and induces a spectral sequence
(2.1) |
3. Main result and vanishing of higher homotopy
3.1.
Let us recall the definition of bivariant theory after Fulton and MacPherson very briefly.
Definition.
A bivariant theory over is an assignment to each morphism in a -graded Abelian group equipped with three operations:
-
(1)
(Product) For composable morphisms and , we have a homomorphism of graded groups .
-
(2)
(Pushforward) Assume we are given composable morphisms and as in (1). If, furthermore, is proper, we have the homomorphism .
-
(3)
(Pullback) Consider the following Cartesian diagram:
(3.1) Then we have the homomorphism .
These operations are subject to (more or less straightforward) compatibility conditions. Among these compatibility conditions, let us recall the projection formula for the later use. We consider the diagram (3.1) such that is proper, and a morphism . Assume we are given and . Then we have .
Given bivariant theories , , a morphism of theories is a collection of homomorphisms for any morphism in compatible with the operations above. We refer to [FM81, §2.2] for details.(1)(1)(1) In our situation, “confined maps” are “proper morphisms” and any Cartesian squares are “independent squares”.
Definition 3.2.
Let be a bivariant theory over . An -orientation of is an element , where is the degree part. Let be another bivariant theory endowed with an -orientation . A morphism of bivariant theories is said to be compatible with the orientation if .
Remark.
Fulton and MacPherson called an orientation a rule to assign an element of to each in a compatible manner. Since our -orientation can be regarded as a part of this data, we named it after Fulton and MacPherson’s. This has a priori nothing to do with orientation of motivic spectra.
3.3.
Our Borel-Moore homology defines a bivariant theory (in an extended sense because it is bigraded), cf. [Deg18, §1.2.8]. By associating the graded group to , we define the bivariant theory denoted by . This bivariant theory has a canonical orientation as follows. Let be the projection. Then we have a morphism
where the isomorphism is defined using [CD19, Theorem 2.4.50.3] and the canonical identification of with , where is the motivic Thom spectrum defined in [CD19, Definition 2.4.12]. The class of the above morphism in is the canonical orientation of .
3.4.
Let us introduce another main player of this paper, , from [SV]. Let be a morphism, and be an integer. Recall that Suslin and Voevodsky(2)(2)(2)In fact, Suslin and Voevodsky used the notation as a presheaf on . Our is the global sections of it. introduced Abelian groups and , or and if no confusion may arise. We do not recall the precise definition of these groups, but content ourselves with giving ideas of how these groups are defined. Both groups are certain subgroups of the free Abelian group generated by integral subscheme of . If we are given an element we may consider the “support” denoted by in an obvious manner. Naively thinking, we wish to define as a subgroup of consisting of such that is equidimensional of dimension over generic points of . However, if we defined in this way, the association to would not be functorial. In order to achieve this functoriality, Suslin and Voevodsky introduces an ingenious compatibility conditions. We do not recall these compatibility conditions, but here is an illuminating example: Let be a closed immersion such that the morphism is flat. Then the associated cycle , called a flat cycle, belongs to . Now, the group is a subgroup of . The element belongs to if and only if the morphism is equidimensional (of relative dimension ). By the compatibility conditions we mentioned above, if we are given a morphism , we have the pullback homomorphism . This enables us to define presheaves on . Then is a cdh-sheaf, and the cdh-sheafification of coincides with . Furthermore, flat cycles generate cdh-locally, and can be thought of as a building pieces (cf. [SV, Theorem 4.2.11]). The following theorem compactly summarizes some aspects of [SV].
Theorem (cf. [SV]).
The assignments and to a morphism can be promoted to a bivariant theories with -orientation.
Proof.
Given any morphism , the pullback homomorphism
is then defined in [SV, right after Lemma 3.3.9]. Given a proper morphism , the pushforward homomorphism
is defined in [SV, Corollary 3.6.3]. Given a sequence of morphisms and integers , the homomorphism
is defined in [SV, Corollary 3.7.5]. We may endow with -orientation by taking . The compatibility conditions for these operations have also been proven in [SV]. ∎
3.5.
Our main theorem is as follows.
Theorem.
Recall that the base field is a perfect field of characteristic , and let . Then, there exists a unique map of bivariant theories compatible with -orientation:
A proof of this theorem is given at the end of Section 5. Let us introduce a notation. Let be a flat morphism of relative dimension . Then is an element of . If we are given as above, we have . This element is denoted by .
Remark 3.6.
-
(1)
Our theorem produces trace maps only for motivic Eilenberg-MacLane spectrum, and the reader might think that our theorem is too restrictive. However, this is not the case since the motivic Eilenberg-MacLane spectrum is universal among “absolute -spectrum with orientation which is -linear and whose associated formal group law is additive” by [Deg18, Remark 2.2.15]. More precisely, if we are given such an absolute -spectrum , we have a unique map . Associated to this map, we may consider the composition , where the last object is the Borel-Moore homology associated with , and we get trace maps for .
-
(2)
Choose to be the -adic étale absolute spectrum for . By construction above, we have , where is the -adic Borel-Moore homology. If is a flat morphism of dimension , the image of by this morphism is denoted by . This element of , considered as a morphism , coincides with the trace map defined in [SGA4, Exposé XVIII, Thórème 2.9]. Thus, the morphism can be seen as a generalization of the trace map of loc. cit., at least when the base field is perfect.
- (3)
-
(4)
The theorem also holds in the case where and . Furthermore, in the case where and if we assume the existence of the resolution of singularities, we may, in fact, take in the theorem. The proof works with obvious changes, and the detail is left to the reader.
-
(5)
The theorem, in fact, holds for any field , not necessarily perfect. In fact, let be the perfection. The compact support cohomology is compatible with arbitrary base change. Thus, by [EK20, Corollary 2.1.5], or alternatively [CD15, Proposition 8.1], the pullback homomorphism is an isomorphism since . Using this isomorphism, the trace map for , constructed above, induces the trace map for as well.
3.7.
Before going to the next section, let us show the most important property to construct the trace map, namely the vanishing of suitable higher homotopies. For a morphism , we put .
Proposition.
For a morphism in and an integer such that , we have
in one of the following cases:
-
(1)
for any and any ,
-
(2)
when and for any .
Proof.
First, assume that . We claim that
if or and . Assume is smooth of equidimension . Then we know that , where is the motivic cohomology and the last isomorphism follows by [CD19, Example 11.2.3]. Thus the claim follows(3)(3)(3) In fact, this holds also for by [Har77, III 2.5, II Ex. 1.16 (a)]. because for . In general, we proceed by the induction on the dimension of . We may assume is reduced. There exists such that is smooth and since is assumed perfect. We have the exact sequence
Assume . Then for any since and the induction hypothesis. Thus , and the claim follows by the smooth case we have already treated. We next assume that is smooth over . We may assume that is of equidimension . Let be the structural morphism. Then we have
Since , we get the vanishing by the case.
Finally, we treat the general case. We take a dh-hypercovering so that is smooth. Let . Then by dh-descent spectral sequence (2.1), we have
If for , then for . Thus, we get the claim by applying this to and . ∎
Remark.
Consider the case where may not be invertible in . If is smooth, then the proposition holds. If we further assume the resolution of singularities, the proposition also holds for any .
4. Construction of the trace map when the base is smooth
Let be a flat morphism. When is smooth, we will construct a map which is supposed to be the same as in this section.
4.1.
For a scheme , we often denote by . Let be (any) separated morphism of finite type such that is smooth equidimensional, and put . In this case, let us construct a morphism , which we will show to be equal to when is flat.
Let us start to construct . Considering componentwise, it suffices to construct the morphism when is connected. For any separated scheme of finite type over , we have the canonical isomorphism
by [Jin16, Corollary 3.9]. We have
where the first isomorphism follows since for any equidimensional smooth morphism of relative dimension . Let be the irreducible components, and let be the subset of such that . Let be the generic point of . The element in corresponding via the isomorphism above to the element on the right hand side is defined to be .
Let us end this paragraph with a simple observation. Let be an open dense subscheme. Then the restriction map is an isomorphism. Indeed, we have , where is the set of irreducible components of of dimension by the computation above. Since and are the same, we get the claim.
4.2.
By the setup 2.1, we may apply [Deg18, Introduction, Theorem 1]. In particular, for a morphism between smooth schemes we have the fundamental class . When , we sometimes denote by . As we expect, we have the following comparison.
Lemma.
Assume is a morphism between smooth equidimensional schemes. Then in .
Proof.
Assume . In this case, is smooth. Then by [Deg18, Theorem 2.5.3], the fundamental class is equal to the one constructed in [Deg18, Proposition 2.3.11], which is nothing but the one we constructed above by [Jin16, Proposition 3.12]. Let us treat the general case. For a -scheme , denote by the structural morphism. Unwinding the definition, our is the unique dotted map so that the following diagram on the right is commutative:
Here, denotes the morphism given by taking adjoint to . Equivalently, is the unique dotted map so that the diagram above on the left is commutative. Thus, it suffices to check that the diagram replacing the dotted arrow by commutes. From what we have checked, for any smooth scheme . Thus, the desired commutativity follows by the associativity property of fundamental class (cf. [Deg18, Introduction, Theorem 1.2]). ∎
Lemma 4.3.
-
(1)
Assume we are given morphisms such that and are smooth and equidimensional. Let the composition be . We have in .
-
(2)
Consider the Cartesian diagram (3.1). Assume further that and are smooth equidimensional and is flat. The map sends to .
-
(3)
Consider a proper morphism and a morphism such that is smooth and equidimensional. Put . Then the map sends to when and otherwise.
Proof.
Let us check the claim (1) of the lemma. By construction of , we may assume that is reduced. By §4.1, we may shrink by its dense open subscheme since remains the same. Thus, we may assume that is smooth as well. In this case, we get the compatibility by Lemma Lemma and [Deg18, Introduction, Theorem 1.2]. The final claim (3) is just a reformulation of [Jin16, Proposition 3.11]. Let us check the claim (2) of the lemma. Since , are smooth, we may factor into a regular immersion followed by a smooth morphism. Thus, it suffices to check the case where is a regular immersion and a smooth morphism separately. In both cases, consider the following diagram:
The map is the unique straight dotted arrow redering the left small square diagram commutes, and is the unique bent dotted arrow rendering the outer largest diagram commutes. Since is flat, is transversal to in the sense of [Deg18, Example 3.1.2]. This implies that by [Deg18, Introduction, Theorem 1.3]. By taking the adjoint, this implies that the right square is commutative. Since , are assumed to be smooth, we have and by the previous lemma. Since , , are gci morphism, the bottom semicircular diagram is commutative by [Deg18, Introduction, Theorem 1.2]. In order to check the equality in the claim, it remains to check that the -marked diagram commutes.
When is smooth, the verification is easy, so we leave it to the reader. Assume is a regular immersion. In [Jin16, Definition 2.31], Jin defines a morphism where . By construction, this is defined as the composition
Applying [Deg18, Introduction, Theorem 1.3], this is the same as . Now, since in by the flatness of , [Jin16, Proposition 3.15] implies that the following diagram on the left commutes:
Taking the adjunction, the verification is reduced to the commutativity of the right diagram above. This follows by the following commutative diagram:
Here, are the morphisms induced by the projection formula (or more precisely [Deg18, (1.2.8.a)]), and we conclude the proof. ∎
Lemma 4.4.
Assume we have a morphism of bivariant theories in Theorem 3.5. Then for a flat morphism such that is smooth and equidimensional, we must have an equality .
Proof.
First, consider the case where . Since preserves the product structure, must send the unit element to . By [Jin16, Proposition 3.12], is equal to as well, and the claim follows in this case. When is an open immersion, we may argue similarly.
Now, let be a finite étale morphism such that is smooth and equidimensional of dimension . We may assume and are integral, and the degree of is . By , is sent to in by definition of . This implies that where . On the other hand, we have the following commutative diagram by [Jin16, Proposition 3.11]:
This implies that, since is torsion free, the left vertical map is injective, and so is the right vertical map. Thus is characterized by the property that , and it suffices to check that . By definition, , and the commutative diagram again implies that . Thus in this case.
Consider the case where . We may assume that is integral, and we may shrink by its open dense subscheme since does not change by §4.1. Then we may assume that can be factored into where the first morphism is étale. By shrinking further, we may assume we have the factorization of where is finite étale. Since the trace map is assumed to preserve -orientation, we must have where by [Jin16, Proposition 3.12]. Thus, by Lemma 4.3-(1), we have .
Finally, let us treat the general case. Let be an open dense subscheme such that is smooth over . Let be the dimension of . We have an isomorphism , again, by §4.1. By construction, this morphism sends to . In view of Lemma Lemma, this is equal to . Now, we have
where the equality follows by what we have already proven, the by the transitivity of the trace map, the by what we have already proven, and the by Lemma 4.3-(1). Thus, we conclude the proof. ∎
5. Construction of the trace map
In this section, we prove the main result.
5.1.
Let be a morphism. To a morphism , we associate
which defines a presheaf of spectra on . We denote by the Abelian presheaf on . Here, is taken as a presheaf and do not consider any topology.
Lemma 5.2.
-
(1)
The spectra-valued presheaf on is a spectra-valued sheaf on the -topos , where denotes the dh-site and denotes the hypercompletion.
-
(2)
Let us assume that . We the have , and for . Here, is the functor in the -topos , in other words, the dh-sheafification of .
Proof.
Let us show the claim (1) of the lemma. Let be a dh-hypercovering of . We must show that the canonical map
is an equivalence in . By Lemma 2.4 applied to , we have the equivalence . By applying , taking into account that commutes with arbitrary limit by the existence of a left adjoint, we have an equivalence . Thus, the claim follows by definition. Let us show the claim (2) of the lemma. The Abelian sheaf is the dh-sheafification of the Abelian presheaf associating to . Since , this vanishes if by Proposition Proposition. Furthermore, since is left exact, 1 and the vanishing for imply that is already a dh-sheaf on , and the claim follows. ∎
5.3.
Let be a morphism. Let us recall the Abelian group for an integer from [SV, §3.2]. This is the set of closed subschemes in which are flat over . We denote by the free -module generated by .
Now, assume that is smooth. For a (flat) morphism in , we constructed in §4.1 when is equidimensional. Even if is not equidimensional, by considering componentwise, we define the element . By associating to the image of via the map , we have the map . This yields the map . Now, let be the submodule consisting of elements such that the associated cycle (cf. the paragraph before Theorem 4.2.11 in [SV]).(4)(4)(4) In [Kel13, §2.1], Kelly pointed out a problem in the definition of the map of [SV] used in the definition of above. Note that we may employ Kelly’s definition of to define , but we get the same ideal, and it does not affect our arguments. Since only depends on the underlying subset and its length, the above constructed map factors through , and defines a map
Lemma 5.4.
Let be a morphism between smooth -schemes. Then we have the following commutative diagram of Abelian groups
5.5.
Let be a morphism. Let be the presheaf of Abelian groups on which sends to , and be the presheaf which sends to . Consider the (geometric) morphism of sites . Then we have
(5.1) |
where the isomorphism follows by [SV, Theorem 4.2.11], the last isomorphism follows since is an h-sheaf by [SV, Theorem 4.2.2] and, in particular, a dh-sheaf.
Now, a dh-hypercovering is said to be good if is smooth for any . Let be the (ordinary) category of dh-hypercoverings of (cf. [SGA4, Exposé V, §7.3.1]). Denote by the full subcategory of consisting of good dh-covers. Recall that is filtered (cf. [SGA4, Exposé V, Théorème 7.3.2]). For any , we can take and a morphism by [SGA4, Exposé , Proposition 5.1.3] and 2.3, which implies that is cofinal in (cf. [SGA4, Exposé I, Proposition 8.1.3]). Put . Thus we have the isomorphisms
where the isomorphism holds by [SGA4, Exposé V, Théorème 7.4.1] and (5.1).
Let be the category of simplicial Abelian groups. Consider the functors
defined by sending to and respectively. By Lemma 5.4, we have the map of functors . Now, assume:
for any .
By Lemma 5.2-(2), we also have the descent isomorphism of Abelian groups. Combining everything together, we have a map
Lemma 5.6.
-
(1)
Consider the Cartesian diagram (3.1). Assume for any point of , in which case the same property holds for . Then we have .
-
(2)
Let be morphisms and put . We assume that for any , and is proper. Then we have .
Proof.
Let us check the claim (1) of the lemma. Take a good dh hypercovering . Then we are able to find a good dh-hypercovering which fits into the following diagram, not necessarily Cartesian:
Consider the following diagram:
Both external squares are commutative by the functoriality of and , and the middle as well by 4.3-(2). The claim (2) follows immediately from Lemma 4.3-(3). ∎
5.7. Proof of Theorem 3.5
First, let us construct a morphism .
Let be a morphism, and .
Let be the support of , and be the closed immersion.
Then is the image of an element via the morphism .
Since , the dimension of each fiber of is .
Thus, we have already constructed the morphism .
We define ,
where is the pushforward.
This defines a map .
In view of Lemma 5.6-(2), this map is in fact a homomorphism of Abelian groups.
This map is compatible with base change and pushforward by Lemmas 5.6-(1) and 5.6-(2).
The uniqueness of the map follows by Lemma 4.4 and construction.
It remains to show the compatibility with respect to the product structure. Let be morphisms, and , . By definition, we may assume that is smooth, and and are flat over . By projection formula of bivariant theories (cf. §3.1), we may assume that (with reduced induced scheme structure). Then, by the compatibility with pushforward, we may replace by . In this situation, we are allowed to shrink by its open dense subscheme because does not change by §4.1, we may further assume that . Now, for an open immersion , we have restriction morphisms and and we may check easily that these are compatible with . Since is dominant, we may take open dense subschemes and such that , is flat, and is smooth. The compatibility with open immersion allows us to replace by . Since , it suffices to show the claim for , and in this case, we have already treated in Lemma 4.3-(1) together with Lemma 4.4. ∎
6. -enhancement of the trace map
In this section, we upgrade the trace map to the -categorical setting.
6.1.
Let be the category of morphisms in whose morphisms from to consists of diagrams of the form
(6.1) |
where is proper. The composition is defined in an evident manner, and we refer to [Abe22a, §5.2] for the detail. We often denote an object corresponding to in by . For , let be the set of families where is a cdh-covering. The category does not admits pullbacks in general, but each morphism is quarrable, in other words, for any morphism , the pullback exists. Indeed, we can check easily that . Thus, this family defines a pretopology on in the sense of [SGA4, Exposé II, §1.3].
6.2.
By associating the Abelian group to , we have a functor . Then is an Abelian sheaf on . Indeed, we must show the Čech descent with respect to the elements of by [SGA4, Exposé II, §2.2]. This is exactly the contents of [SV, §4.2.9]. We define to be the sheafification of regarded as a spectra-valued presheaf on .
Now, by [ES21, Lemma C.3], we have the following commutative diagram of geometric morphisms of -topoi
(6.2) |
Note that, since local objects (with respect to a localization) are stable under taking limits by definition, is commutes with limits by [ES21, Lemma C.3], which justifies that is a geometric morphism. Moreover, by [Lur18, Proposition 20.6.1.3], the functor is given by composing with . In particular, is the (cdh-)sheafification of .
6.3.
Assume we are given a morphism in as in (6.1). Then we have the morphism of spectra
With this morphism, we can check easily that the association to yields a functor . It is natural to expect that this morphism can be lifted to a functor of -categories . We put the existence as an assumption as follows:
Assume we are given a functor between -categories whose induced functor between homotopy categories coincides with above.
We constructed such a functor in [Abe22a, Example 6.8], and also in [Abe22b, §C.3] using a slightly different method. Now, we have the following -enhancement of the trace map.
Theorem 6.4.
There exists essentially uniquely a morphism of spectra-valued sheaves on for any such that the composition
coincides with the morphism of Theorem 3.5.
Proof.
Let be the subsheaf so that the value at is . Note that is just a notation and not of some presheaf . We first define the trace map for . Let be the full subcategory of consisting of objects such that . First, let us construct the map after restricting to . We have already constructed the map of spectra-valued presheaves
(6.3) |
Here, the equivalence follows by Lemma 5.2-(2) since we are restricting the functor to . Now, let the category be the full subcategory of spanned by the morphisms in such that belongs to . We have functors where is the evaluation at , and is at . Namely, for above, we have and . By [Lur09, Corollary 2.4.7.12], is a Cartesian fibration. Note that we have the natural transform and this induces the morphism of functors for any functor . From now on, we abbreviate , by , to avoid heavy notations. By (6.3), we have the map of spectra-valued presheaves on . Now, we have the following diagram of -categories
where is either or . Since is a Cartesian fibration, is a coCartesian fibration. Since the -category is presentable, any left Kan extension exists by [Lur09, Proposition 4.3.2.15]. We denote by a left Kan extension of the above diagram. We have the following diagram of spectra-valued presheaves:
Here, the vertical morphisms are defined by taking the adjoint to . We claim that the left vertical map is equivalent. For this, it suffices to show that is in fact a left Kan extension of . Let , and we denote by the fiber of over . Since is a coCartesian fibration, by invoking [Lur09, Proposition 4.3.3.10], it suffices to show that is a left Kan extension of along the canonical map for any . This amounts to showing that the morphism of spectra (namely the colimit is the “derived colimit”)
is an equivalence. Let be the category of closed immersions such that the composition is in . The category is filtered and the inclusion cofinal. Thus, the colimit is t-exact by [Lur18, Proposition 1.3.2.7], and it suffices to show the morphism of Abelian groups is an isomorphism. This follows by definition. Thus we have the map of spectra-valued presheaves.
Finally, let us extend this map to the required map. The -presheaf on is in fact an -sheaf. Indeed, let be the localization morphism. We must show that this morphism is an equivalence. Recall that for an -category , a simplicial set , and a morphism in , is an equivalence if and only if is an equivalence for any vertex of . We believe that this is well-known, but a (fairly) indirectly way to see this is by applying [Lur09, Corollary 5.1.2.3] to the diagram given by . Now, let . Since the verification is pointwise by the recalled fact, it suffices to show that is an equivalence. By (6.2), this morphism can be identified with , which is an equivalence since is already a cdh-sheaf (cf. Lemma 5.2-(1)). Thus, by taking the sheafification to the morphism , we get the morphism . The essential uniqueness follows by construction, and the detail is left to the reader. ∎
References
- [Abe22a] T. Abe, Enhanced bivariant homology theory attached to six functor formalism, J. Topology 15 (2022), 1675–1754.
- [Abe22b] by same author, Ramification theory from homotopical point of view, I, preprint arXiv:2206.02401 (2022).
- [CD15] D.-C. Cisinski and F. Déglise, Integral mixed motives in equal characteristic, Doc. Math. Extra Vol., Alexander S. Merkurjev’s Sixtieth Birthday (2015), 145–194.
- [CD19] by same author, Triangulated categories of mixed motives, Springer Monographs in Math., Cham: Springer, 2019.
- [Deg18] F. Déglise, Bivariant theories in motivic stable homotopy, Doc. Math. 23 (2018), 997–1076.
- [EK20] E. Elmanto and A. Khan, Perfection in motivic homotopy theory, Proc. London Math. Soc. (3) 120 (2020), no. 1, 28–38.
- [ES21] E. Elmanto and J. Shah, Scheiderer motives and equivariant higher topos theory, Adv. Math. 382 (2021), article id. 107651.
- [FM81] W. Fulton and R. MacPherson, Categorical framework for the study of singular spaces, Mem. Am. Mat. Soc. 243 (1981).
- [Har77] R. Hartshorne, Algebraic geometry, Graduate Texts in Mathematics, vol. 52, New York-Heidelberg-Berlin: Springer-Verlag, 1977.
- [Jin16] F. Jin, Borel-Moore motivic homology and weight structure on mixed motives, Math. Z. 283 (2016), no. 3-4, 1149–1183.
- [Kel13] S. Kelly, Triangulated categories of motives in positive characteristic, preprint arXiv:1305.5349 (2013).
- [Kha16] A. Khan, Motivic homotopy theory in derived algebraic geometry, Ph.D. thesis (2016). Available from www.preschema.com/thesis/.
- [Lur09] J. Lurie, Higher topos theory, Annals of Mathematics Studies, vol. 170, Princeton, NJ: Princeton University Press, 2009.
- [Lur18] by same author, Spectral algebraic geometry, preprint (2018). Available from the author’s webpage https://www.math.ias.edu/ lurie/papers/SAG-rootfile.pdf
- [SGA4] A. Grothendieck et al., Théorie des topos et cohomologie étale des schémas. Séminaire de Géométrie Algébrique du Bois-Marie 1963–1964 (SGA 4), Lecture Notes in Mathematics, vol. 269, 270, and 305, Berlin-Heidelberg-New York: Springer-Verlag, 1972–1973
- [SV] A. Suslin and V. Voevodsky, Relative cycles and Chow sheaves, in Cycles, transfers, and motivic homology theories, Ann. Math. Studies, vol. 143, pp. 10–86, Princeton, NJ: Princeton University Press, 2000.
- [T] M. Temkin, Tame distillation and desingularization by -alterations, Ann. Math. 186 (2017), no. 1, 97–126.