Unbalanced polarized relations
Abstract.
We prove the consistency of the relation where is a strong limit singular cardinal of countable cofinality. This result can be forced at .
Key words and phrases:
Polarized partition relations, Prikry type forcing2010 Mathematics Subject Classification:
03E02, 03E35, 03E550. Introduction
The polarized partition relation says that for every coloring there are and such that and is constantly . If then we shall say that the relation is unbalanced. Lest and we write and then we shall say that the relation is balanced.
An old problem raised by Erdős, Hajnal and Rado in the so-called Giant triple paper is whether under GCH. More generally, the question arises with respect to the relation where is strong limit and , see [9, Questions 1 and 2]. A particular interesting case is the case of an -limit of measurable cardinals, see [5, Question 6].
We suggest a negative answer to these problems. We shall prove that consistently is a strong limit cardinal, yet . In this result it is possible that be a limit of measurable cardinals or a very small cardinal like .
Our notation is mostly standard. We follow [3] with respect to arrows notation. We adopt the conventions of [7] with respect to Prikry type forcing, and in particular we use the Jerusalem forcing notation. We suggest the wonderful monograph [14] for basic results about polarized partition relations, and the Handbook chapter [8] for advanced material concerning polarized relations.
I am very much obliged to the referee of this paper. My original manuscript contained another section with a false proof. The referee pointed to my mistake and I am sincerely grateful.
1. Unbalanced relations
In this section we deal with an unbalanced relation at a strong limit singular cardinal so that . Erdős, Hajnal and Rado proved in [2] that if then for every infinite cardinal . The positive relation is consistent at strong limit singular cardinals, see [6], but this requires . It also holds under AD, where the assumption becomes irrelevant, see [4]. One may wonder, therefore, what is the best positive relation at such cardinals without the assumption , that is under the assumption or just in ZFC. An elegant result of Shelah from [13] says that if is a singular cardinal and a limit of measurable cardinals then for every . Being a theorem of ZFC, it holds even if .
These facts lead to the investigation of the intermediate unbalanced relation . On the one hand, this relation is weaker than . On the other hand, it is stronger than . Due to Shelah’s result, this intermediate relation is particularly interesting at a singular limit of measurable cardinals.
By simple arguments one can show that for every . However, if then as proved in [2]. Consequently, the question is settled for cardinals with uncountable cofinality (both regular and singular). This is the reason for concentrating on singular cardinals with countable cofinality.
It is quite surprising to find out that for strong limit singular cardinals with countable cofinality under the assumption we have , as proved in [2]. Motivated by this peculiar situation in which singular cardinals with countable cofinality demonstrate a stronger positive relation, Erdős, Hajnal and Rado tried to check how large can the small component in the second color be. Assuming GCH they proved that , and later it was shown that GCH can be replaced by only, see [5]. The remaining case is, therefore, at the second color. Jones proved in [9] that under the above assumptions one has for every . Together with the negative result of [5] with respect to , the case of seems to be the last case in this context.
We shall prove that is consistent for a strong limit singular cardinal with countable cofinality under the assumption that . This result can be forced at a limit of measurable cardinals, and also at . Thus we obtain a negative answer to [2, Problem 10] and we conclude that Jones’ result is optimal from ZFC point of view. We also obtain a negative answer to [5, Question 6] and conclude that in some sense Shelah’s result from [13] is optimal.
Suppose that . As mentioned above, we know that . If exemplifies this negative relation and we force to make then the coloring is reinterpreted in the generic extension and it will be polychromatic on old sets of the appropriate size.
The problem is that usually our forcing adds new sets. For example, if is measurable and we force a Prikry sequence into then new sets of size and are added and they might be quite far from old sets of the same size. In particular, maybe is monochromatic on these new sets.
One can try to begin with a singular cardinal whose cofinality is a measurable cardinal, and then to force Prikry into thus making a singular cardinal with countable cofinality as well. If one begins with and is measurable then Prikry forcing into is a bit better since new sets of size contain old sets of the same size and this is sufficient for the negative relation. However, it seems that there is no way to apply a similar argument to sets of size .
Proposition 1.1.
Suppose that is a measurable cardinal and is Prikry forcing through .
-
If and is a new set of size then contains an old subset of size .
-
If and is a new set of size then contains an old subset of size .
-
There exists in the generic extension such that if and is an old set then is bounded in .
Proof.
Choose a -generic set .
For the first statement let be of size and for every let .
Notice that whenever one fixes a single condition .
Since and we see that there is a condition for which .
The fact that is forced to be a subset of concludes the argument.
For the second part suppose that is a new set of size , and without loss of generality , using some one-to-one mapping from into and working with the range of this mapping. Since in the generic extension and , one can find a subset of of the same size which is bounded in , say . Let be any condition which forces . For each let be the formula . For every choose a condition so that and decides . Let , so belongs to the normal ultrafilter which we use in our forcing. But now the single condition determines the elements of and hence as required.
Lastly, choose in the ground model an increasing sequence of regular cardinals such that . Let be a Prikry sequence into . Set , so . If and is unbounded in then for infinitely many . Hence one can recover an infinite subsequence of from by collecting the indices of for every . By the genericity criterion of Mathias from [12] we see that , thus we are done.
The strategy of using an old coloring is apparently ineffective in the light of the last part of the above proposition. However, it can be used at non strong limit cardinals.
Claim 1.2.
Assume that:
-
and .
-
is measurable and .
-
There exists some so that and .
Then one can force and so one obtains as well.
Proof.
Let be Prikry forcing through and let be -generic.
Fix, in the ground model, a coloring which exemplifies the negative relation .
By abuse of notation let us denote by .
Assume that and in . By Proposition 1.1 one can find and . By we know that and then . Similarly, if and then one can choose and from the ground model. It follows that , so we are done.
Assumptions in the spirit of the above claim can be forced by adding many Cohen sets to some relatively small cardinal. This idea is applicable to non strong limit cardinals, and an interesting example will be proved anon. We mention here [2, Problem 14], which asks whether .
Claim 1.3.
It is consistent that , but and even .
Proof.
Begin with such that is measurable and .
Choose such that .
Let be and let be -generic.
By [1, Theorem 7.4] we have in .
Working in , let be Prikry forcing through (notice that remains measurable in ). Let be -generic. The argument in the proof of Claim 1.2 gives in .
Moreover, suppose that and . By monotonicity we have in , and since we see that as well. Another application of monotonicity yields in , as desired. The same argument gives the negative relation if one chooses with , so the proof is accomplished.
Observe that is satisfied in the generic extension, and for every specific one can force as in the above claim while retaining by choosing . However, the above idea seems to be inapplicable if one considers strong limit cardinals. In particular, the following claim shows that negative assumptions in the ground model with respect to some as needed for the above proof are impossible.
Claim 1.4.
Suppose that is a strong limit cardinal and . Then .
Proof.
Suppose that .
Let and let be an increasing sequence of cardinals such that .
For every and each define:
Let . By [9, Lemma 1] either there is some such that or there exists such that is a -uniform filter base.
Lest the first option obtains we have a -monochromatic product of size , stipulating . If the second option holds, choose for every an ordinal such that . Since we may assume, without loss of generality, that for every and some fixed . Since and is strong limit we see that . Hence without loss of generality there is a fixed such that and for every . Verify that is -monochromatic and conclude that as desired.
Although we cannot use old colorings in the context of strong limit cardinals, we can still exploit the density arguments for sets of size . The following is the main result of this section:
Theorem 1.5.
It is consistent that is a strong limit singular cardinal of countable cofinality, and .
Proof.
Let be a measurable cardinal, assume that and let be Prikry forcing into .
We claim that in the generic extension by .
Choose a generic subset .
We shall define a coloring in .
As a first step we enumerate by . Now for each we enumerate in such a way that the order-type will be , say . If then we use repetitions. Similarly, for each we list the ordinals of by an enumeration of order-type , say . We emphasize that this enumeration of the ordinals of is done already in the ground model.
As a second step we choose for every and each an ordinal with the goal of setting . We do this, however, with some control. Fix and choose for each an ordinal so that . Notice that we remove a small set from and , so the choice is possible. Define:
We must show that has no -monochromatic product of size and no -monochromatic product of size .
For the first mission suppose that and . Let be such that and let be such that . Let , so . By definition, and hence is not -monochromatic.
For the second mission assume that and . Assume toward contradiction that is -monochromatic. Choose such that and . Define . Notice that and since . In particular, is bounded in , so let . Define . Observe that since and for every we have . We shall prove that thus arriving at a contradiction since .
Firstly we observe that if and and then . To see this recall that , so if then we required in the choice of the s that . Secondly, choose some and recall that for every . It follows that for each there exists a unique ordinal such that . We claim that there must be some for which . Suppose not, and choose such that . Let be so that . By the definition of we see that , so by our assumption. Since both and we see that and by the above observation we have . Since is infinite, if we choose an increasing sequence of elements of we produce an infinite decreasing sequence of ordinals , which is an absurd.
Therefore, for each we choose such that and . It follows now from the definition of the set that and hence , so we are done.
The above theorem was proved using Prikry forcing, and this is probably the simplest way to carry out the argument. But the method itself is a bit more general, and in particular applies to a wider collection of forcing notions. If forces countable cofinality to where in the ground model and every new set of size contains an old set of size then a similar proof works. Consequently, one can use other Prikry-type forcing notions. An answer to [2, Problems 10 and 14] can be given now using Magidor’s method from [10] and [11] to singularize a measurable cardinal with interleaved collapses.
Corollary 1.6.
It is consistent that where is strong limit and . Similarly, is consistent at under the same assumptions.
The following remark which sheds some light on the role of in the above statements. The general idea behind the proof of the main result it to begin with a negative relation at , to force a desired property of (here it is countable cofinality) in such a way that the negative relation is preserved. Thus we commence with a measurable cardinal with so in the ground model, and we force Prikry in order to singularize while keeping the negative relation.
But under the above assumption we know that as well in the ground model. When we force with Prikry forcing we secure the negative relation but we also get the positive relation in the generic extension. One may wonder what is the difference between and in this context, and at least one aspect of the answer becomes clearer. New sets of size in the Prikry extension contain old sets of the same size. Contrariwise, new -sequences cannot be approximated by infinite sets from the ground model. This fact explains the peculiarity of singular cardinals with countable cofinality with respect to the unbalanced relation discussed in this paper.
We conclude with a couple of open problems. The first one is about the possibility of the positive direction.
Question 1.7.
Is it consistent that the positive relation holds under GCH where ?
For the second question let us indicate that large cardinals are not necessary in order to force under the above assumptions. For example, if one forces with Namba forcing over the constructible universe then every singular cardinal so that will satisfy in the generic extension. However, by assuming the existence of large cardinals one can force a universe in which every singular strong limit cardinal with countable cofinality is ex-measurable, and then holds globally at every such cardinal. We do not know whether large cardinals are indispensable for this result:
Question 1.8.
Can one force without large cardinals that GCH holds, and whenever ?
References
- [1] James E. Baumgartner, Almost-disjoint sets, the dense set problem and the partition calculus, Ann. Math. Logic 9 (1976), no. 4, 401–439. MR 401472
- [2] P. Erdős, A. Hajnal, and R. Rado, Partition relations for cardinal numbers, Acta Math. Acad. Sci. Hungar. 16 (1965), 93–196. MR MR0202613 (34 #2475)
- [3] Paul Erdős, András Hajnal, Attila Máté, and Richard Rado, Combinatorial set theory: partition relations for cardinals, Studies in Logic and the Foundations of Mathematics, vol. 106, North-Holland Publishing Co., Amsterdam, 1984. MR MR795592 (87g:04002)
- [4] Shimon Garti, Polarized relations at singulars over successors, Discrete Math. 343 (2020), no. 9, 111961, 9. MR 4101445
- [5] Shimon Garti, Menachem Magidor, and Saharon Shelah, Infinite monochromatic paths and a theorem of Erdos-Hajnal-Rado, Electron. J. Combin. 27 (2020), no. 2, 11 pages.
- [6] Shimon Garti and Saharon Shelah, A strong polarized relation, J. Symbolic Logic 77 (2012), no. 3, 766–776. MR 2987137
- [7] Moti Gitik, Prikry-type forcings, Handbook of set theory. Vols. 1, 2, 3, Springer, Dordrecht, 2010, pp. 1351–1447. MR 2768695
- [8] András Hajnal and Jean A. Larson, Partition relations, Handbook of set theory. Vols. 1, 2, 3, Springer, Dordrecht, 2010, pp. 129–213. MR 2768681
- [9] Albin L. Jones, A polarized partition relation for cardinals of countable cofinality, Proc. Amer. Math. Soc. 136 (2008), no. 4, 1445–1449. MR 2367118
- [10] Menachem Magidor, On the singular cardinals problem. I, Israel J. Math. 28 (1977), no. 1-2, 1–31. MR 491183
- [11] by same author, On the singular cardinals problem. II, Ann. of Math. (2) 106 (1977), no. 3, 517–547. MR 491184
- [12] A. R. D. Mathias, On sequences generic in the sense of Prikry, J. Austral. Math. Soc. 15 (1973), 409–414. MR 0332482
- [13] Saharon Shelah, A polarized partition relation and failure of GCH at singular strong limit, Fund. Math. 155 (1998), no. 2, 153–160. MR 1606515
- [14] Neil H. Williams, Combinatorial set theory, Studies in Logic and the Foundations of Mathematics, vol. 91, North-Holland Publishing Co., Amsterdam, 1977. MR 3075383