This paper was converted on www.awesomepapers.org from LaTeX by an anonymous user.
Want to know more? Visit the Converter page.

Unbalanced polarized relations

Shimon Garti Einstein Institute of Mathematics, The Hebrew University of Jerusalem, Jerusalem 91904, Israel shimon.garty@mail.huji.ac.il
Abstract.

We prove the consistency of the relation (μ+μ)(μ+ω1μμ)\binom{\mu^{+}}{\mu}\nrightarrow\binom{\mu^{+}\ \omega_{1}}{\mu\quad\mu} where μ\mu is a strong limit singular cardinal of countable cofinality. This result can be forced at μ=ω\mu=\aleph_{\omega}.

Key words and phrases:
Polarized partition relations, Prikry type forcing
2010 Mathematics Subject Classification:
03E02, 03E35, 03E55

0. Introduction

The polarized partition relation (αβ)(γ0γ1δ0δ1)\binom{\alpha}{\beta}\rightarrow\binom{\gamma_{0}\ \gamma_{1}}{\delta_{0}\ \delta_{1}} says that for every coloring c:α×β2c:\alpha\times\beta\rightarrow 2 there are Aα,BβA\subseteq\alpha,B\subseteq\beta and i{0,1}i\in\{0,1\} such that otp(A)=γi,otp(B)=δi{\rm otp}(A)=\gamma_{i},{\rm otp}(B)=\delta_{i} and c(A×B)c\upharpoonright(A\times B) is constantly ii. If (γ0,δ0)(γ1,δ1)(\gamma_{0},\delta_{0})\neq(\gamma_{1},\delta_{1}) then we shall say that the relation is unbalanced. Lest γ0=γ1=γ\gamma_{0}=\gamma_{1}=\gamma and δ0=δ1=δ\delta_{0}=\delta_{1}=\delta we write (αβ)(γδ)\binom{\alpha}{\beta}\rightarrow\binom{\gamma}{\delta} and then we shall say that the relation is balanced.

An old problem raised by Erdős, Hajnal and Rado in the so-called Giant triple paper is whether (ω+1ω)(ω+1ω1ωω)\binom{\aleph_{\omega+1}}{\aleph_{\omega}}\rightarrow\binom{\aleph_{\omega+1}\ \omega_{1}}{\aleph_{\omega}\quad\aleph_{\omega}} under GCH. More generally, the question arises with respect to the relation (μ+μ)(μ+ω1μμ)\binom{\mu^{+}}{\mu}\rightarrow\binom{\mu^{+}\ \omega_{1}}{\mu\quad\mu} where μ>cf(μ)=ω\mu>{\rm cf}(\mu)=\omega is strong limit and 2μ=μ+2^{\mu}=\mu^{+}, see [9, Questions 1 and 2]. A particular interesting case is the case of an ω\omega-limit of measurable cardinals, see [5, Question 6].

We suggest a negative answer to these problems. We shall prove that consistently μ>cf(μ)=ω,μ\mu>{\rm cf}(\mu)=\omega,\mu is a strong limit cardinal, 2μ=μ+2^{\mu}=\mu^{+} yet (μ+μ)(μ+ω1μμ)\binom{\mu^{+}}{\mu}\nrightarrow\binom{\mu^{+}\ \omega_{1}}{\mu\quad\mu}. In this result it is possible that μ\mu be a limit of measurable cardinals or a very small cardinal like ω\aleph_{\omega}.

Our notation is mostly standard. We follow [3] with respect to arrows notation. We adopt the conventions of [7] with respect to Prikry type forcing, and in particular we use the Jerusalem forcing notation. We suggest the wonderful monograph [14] for basic results about polarized partition relations, and the Handbook chapter [8] for advanced material concerning polarized relations.

I am very much obliged to the referee of this paper. My original manuscript contained another section with a false proof. The referee pointed to my mistake and I am sincerely grateful.

1. Unbalanced relations

In this section we deal with an unbalanced relation at a strong limit singular cardinal μ\mu so that 2μ=μ+2^{\mu}=\mu^{+}. Erdős, Hajnal and Rado proved in [2] that if 2μ=μ+2^{\mu}=\mu^{+} then (μ+μ)(μ+μ)\binom{\mu^{+}}{\mu}\nrightarrow\binom{\mu^{+}}{\mu} for every infinite cardinal μ\mu. The positive relation (μ+μ)(μ+μ)\binom{\mu^{+}}{\mu}\rightarrow\binom{\mu^{+}}{\mu} is consistent at strong limit singular cardinals, see [6], but this requires 2μ>μ+2^{\mu}>\mu^{+}. It also holds under AD, where the assumption 2μ=μ+2^{\mu}=\mu^{+} becomes irrelevant, see [4]. One may wonder, therefore, what is the best positive relation at such cardinals without the assumption 2μ>μ+2^{\mu}>\mu^{+}, that is under the assumption 2μ=μ+2^{\mu}=\mu^{+} or just in ZFC. An elegant result of Shelah from [13] says that if μ\mu is a singular cardinal and a limit of measurable cardinals then (μ+μ)(τμ)\binom{\mu^{+}}{\mu}\rightarrow\binom{\tau}{\mu} for every τμ+\tau\in\mu^{+}. Being a theorem of ZFC, it holds even if 2μ=μ+2^{\mu}=\mu^{+}.

These facts lead to the investigation of the intermediate unbalanced relation (μ+μ)(μ+τμμ)\binom{\mu^{+}}{\mu}\rightarrow\binom{\mu^{+}\ \tau}{\mu\quad\mu}. On the one hand, this relation is weaker than (μ+μ)(μ+μ)\binom{\mu^{+}}{\mu}\rightarrow\binom{\mu^{+}}{\mu}. On the other hand, it is stronger than (μ+μ)(τμ)\binom{\mu^{+}}{\mu}\rightarrow\binom{\tau}{\mu}. Due to Shelah’s result, this intermediate relation is particularly interesting at a singular limit of measurable cardinals.

By simple arguments one can show that (μ+μ)(μ+nμμ)\binom{\mu^{+}}{\mu}\rightarrow\binom{\mu^{+}\ n}{\mu\quad\mu} for every nωn\in\omega. However, if μcf(μ)>ω\mu\geq{\rm cf}(\mu)>\omega then (μ+μ)(μ+ωμμ)\binom{\mu^{+}}{\mu}\nrightarrow\binom{\mu^{+}\ \omega}{\mu\quad\mu} as proved in [2]. Consequently, the question is settled for cardinals with uncountable cofinality (both regular and singular). This is the reason for concentrating on singular cardinals with countable cofinality.

It is quite surprising to find out that for strong limit singular cardinals with countable cofinality under the assumption 2μ=μ+2^{\mu}=\mu^{+} we have (μ+μ)(μ+ωμμ)\binom{\mu^{+}}{\mu}\rightarrow\binom{\mu^{+}\ \omega}{\mu\quad\mu}, as proved in [2]. Motivated by this peculiar situation in which singular cardinals with countable cofinality demonstrate a stronger positive relation, Erdős, Hajnal and Rado tried to check how large can the small component in the second color be. Assuming GCH they proved that (μ+μ)(μ+ω2μμ)\binom{\mu^{+}}{\mu}\nrightarrow\binom{\mu^{+}\ \omega_{2}}{\mu\quad\mu}, and later it was shown that GCH can be replaced by 2μ=μ+2^{\mu}=\mu^{+} only, see [5]. The remaining case is, therefore, ω1\omega_{1} at the second color. Jones proved in [9] that under the above assumptions one has (μ+μ)(μ+τμμ)\binom{\mu^{+}}{\mu}\rightarrow\binom{\mu^{+}\ \tau}{\mu\quad\mu} for every τω1\tau\in\omega_{1}. Together with the negative result of [5] with respect to ω2\omega_{2}, the case of ω1\omega_{1} seems to be the last case in this context.

We shall prove that (μ+μ)(μ+ω1μμ)\binom{\mu^{+}}{\mu}\nrightarrow\binom{\mu^{+}\ \omega_{1}}{\mu\quad\mu} is consistent for a strong limit singular cardinal μ\mu with countable cofinality under the assumption that 2μ=μ+2^{\mu}=\mu^{+}. This result can be forced at a limit of measurable cardinals, and also at ω\aleph_{\omega}. Thus we obtain a negative answer to [2, Problem 10] and we conclude that Jones’ result is optimal from ZFC point of view. We also obtain a negative answer to [5, Question 6] and conclude that in some sense Shelah’s result from [13] is optimal.

Suppose that μcf(μ)>ω\mu\geq{\rm cf}(\mu)>\omega. As mentioned above, we know that (μ+μ)(μ+ω1μμ)\binom{\mu^{+}}{\mu}\nrightarrow\binom{\mu^{+}\ \omega_{1}}{\mu\quad\mu}. If c:μ+×μ2c:\mu^{+}\times\mu\rightarrow 2 exemplifies this negative relation and we force to make cf(μ)=ω{\rm cf}(\mu)=\omega then the coloring cc is reinterpreted in the generic extension and it will be polychromatic on old sets of the appropriate size.

The problem is that usually our forcing adds new sets. For example, if μ\mu is measurable and we force a Prikry sequence into μ\mu then new sets of size μ\mu and μ+\mu^{+} are added and they might be quite far from old sets of the same size. In particular, maybe cc is monochromatic on these new sets.

One can try to begin with a singular cardinal μ\mu whose cofinality κ\kappa is a measurable cardinal, and then to force Prikry into κ\kappa thus making μ\mu a singular cardinal with countable cofinality as well. If one begins with μ>cf(μ)=κ\mu>{\rm cf}(\mu)=\kappa and κ\kappa is measurable then Prikry forcing into κ\kappa is a bit better since new sets of size μ+\mu^{+} contain old sets of the same size and this is sufficient for the negative relation. However, it seems that there is no way to apply a similar argument to sets of size μ\mu.

Proposition 1.1.

Suppose that μ>cf(μ)=κ,κ\mu>{\rm cf}(\mu)=\kappa,\kappa is a measurable cardinal and \mathbb{P} is Prikry forcing through κ\kappa.

  1. ()(\aleph)

    If 2κ<θ=cf(θ)2^{\kappa}<\theta={\rm cf}(\theta) and AA is a new set of size θ\theta then AA contains an old subset of size θ\theta.

  2. ()(\beth)

    If ω<cf(θ)θ<κ\omega<{\rm cf}(\theta)\leq\theta<\kappa and AA is a new set of size θ\theta then AA contains an old subset of size θ\theta.

  3. ()(\gimel)

    There exists A[μ]μA\in[\mu]^{\mu} in the generic extension such that if BAB\subseteq A and BB is an old set then BB is bounded in μ\mu.

Proof.
Choose a VV-generic set GG\subseteq\mathbb{P}. For the first statement let AV[G]A\in V[G] be of size θ\theta and for every pGp\in G let Ap={αOrd:pαˇA ~ }A_{p}=\{\alpha\in{\rm Ord}:p\Vdash\check{\alpha}\in\mathchoice{\oalign{$\displaystyle A$\crcr\vbox to0.86108pt{\hbox{$\displaystyle{\tilde{\mkern-3.0mu}\mkern 3.0mu}{}$}\vss}}}{\oalign{$\textstyle A$\crcr\vbox to0.86108pt{\hbox{$\textstyle{\tilde{\mkern-3.0mu}\mkern 3.0mu}{}$}\vss}}}{\oalign{$\scriptstyle A$\crcr\vbox to0.86108pt{\hbox{$\scriptstyle{\tilde{\mkern-3.0mu}\mkern 3.0mu}{}$}\vss}}}{\oalign{$\scriptscriptstyle A$\crcr\vbox to0.86108pt{\hbox{$\scriptscriptstyle{\tilde{\mkern-3.0mu}\mkern 3.0mu}{}$}\vss}}}\}. Notice that ApVA_{p}\in V whenever one fixes a single condition pp. Since A={Ap:pG}A=\bigcup\{A_{p}:p\in G\} and |G|2κ<θ=cf(θ)|G|\leq 2^{\kappa}<\theta={\rm cf}(\theta) we see that there is a condition pGp\in G for which |Ap|=θ|A_{p}|=\theta. The fact that ApA_{p} is forced to be a subset of AA concludes the argument.

For the second part suppose that AA is a new set of size θ\theta, and without loss of generality AκA\subseteq\kappa, using some one-to-one mapping from AA into κ\kappa and working with the range of this mapping. Since cf(κ)=ω{\rm cf}(\kappa)=\omega in the generic extension and |A|>ω|A|>\omega, one can find a subset BB of AA of the same size which is bounded in κ\kappa, say sup(B)=ρ<κ\sup(B)=\rho<\kappa. Let p=(sp,Ap)p=(s^{p},A^{p}) be any condition which forces BAB\subseteq A. For each αρ\alpha\in\rho let φα\varphi_{\alpha} be the formula αˇB ~ \check{\alpha}\in\mathchoice{\oalign{$\displaystyle B$\crcr\vbox to0.86108pt{\hbox{$\displaystyle{\tilde{\mkern-3.0mu}\mkern 3.0mu}{}$}\vss}}}{\oalign{$\textstyle B$\crcr\vbox to0.86108pt{\hbox{$\textstyle{\tilde{\mkern-3.0mu}\mkern 3.0mu}{}$}\vss}}}{\oalign{$\scriptstyle B$\crcr\vbox to0.86108pt{\hbox{$\scriptstyle{\tilde{\mkern-3.0mu}\mkern 3.0mu}{}$}\vss}}}{\oalign{$\scriptscriptstyle B$\crcr\vbox to0.86108pt{\hbox{$\scriptscriptstyle{\tilde{\mkern-3.0mu}\mkern 3.0mu}{}$}\vss}}}. For every αρ\alpha\in\rho choose a condition qα=(sp,Aα)q_{\alpha}=(s^{p},A^{\alpha}) so that pqαp\leq^{*}q_{\alpha} and qαq_{\alpha} decides φα\varphi_{\alpha}. Let E={Aα:αρ}E=\bigcap\{A^{\alpha}:\alpha\in\rho\}, so EE belongs to the normal ultrafilter which we use in our forcing. But now the single condition (sp,E)(s^{p},E) determines the elements of BB and hence BVB\in V as required.

Lastly, choose in the ground model an increasing sequence of regular cardinals (μδ:δκ)(\mu_{\delta}:\delta\in\kappa) such that μ=δκμδ\mu=\bigcup_{\delta\in\kappa}\mu_{\delta}. Let (ρi:iω)(\rho_{i}:i\in\omega) be a Prikry sequence into κ\kappa. Set A={[μρi,μρi+):iω}A=\bigcup\{[\mu_{\rho_{i}},\mu_{\rho_{i}}^{+}):i\in\omega\}, so A[μ]μV[G]A\in[\mu]^{\mu}\cap V[G]. If BAB\subseteq A and BB is unbounded in μ\mu then B[μρi,μρi+)B\cap[\mu_{\rho_{i}},\mu_{\rho_{i}}^{+})\neq\varnothing for infinitely many iωi\in\omega. Hence one can recover an infinite subsequence of (ρi:iω)(\rho_{i}:i\in\omega) from BB by collecting the indices of μδ=|β|\mu_{\delta}=|\beta| for every βB\beta\in B. By the genericity criterion of Mathias from [12] we see that BVB\notin V, thus we are done.

1.1\qed_{\ref{propoldsets}}

The strategy of using an old coloring is apparently ineffective in the light of the last part of the above proposition. However, it can be used at non strong limit cardinals.

Claim 1.2.

Assume that:

  1. (a)(a)

    μ>cf(μ)=κ\mu>{\rm cf}(\mu)=\kappa and 2μ=μ+2^{\mu}=\mu^{+}.

  2. (b)(b)

    κ\kappa is measurable and 2κ<μ2^{\kappa}<\mu.

  3. (c)(c)

    There exists some θ<μ\theta<\mu so that κ<θ\kappa<\theta and (μ+μ)(μ+ω1θθ)\binom{\mu^{+}}{\mu}\nrightarrow\binom{\mu^{+}\ \omega_{1}}{\theta\quad\theta}.

Then one can force μ>cf(μ)=ω,2μ=μ+\mu>{\rm cf}(\mu)=\omega,2^{\mu}=\mu^{+} and (μ+μ)(μ+ω1θθ)\binom{\mu^{+}}{\mu}\nrightarrow\binom{\mu^{+}\ \omega_{1}}{\theta\quad\theta} so one obtains (μ+μ)(μ+ω1μμ)\binom{\mu^{+}}{\mu}\nrightarrow\binom{\mu^{+}\ \omega_{1}}{\mu\quad\mu} as well.

Proof.
Let \mathbb{P} be Prikry forcing through κ\kappa and let GG\subseteq\mathbb{P} be VV-generic. Fix, in the ground model, a coloring c:μ+×μ2c:\mu^{+}\times\mu\rightarrow 2 which exemplifies the negative relation (μ+μ)(μ+ω1θθ)\binom{\mu^{+}}{\mu}\nrightarrow\binom{\mu^{+}\ \omega_{1}}{\theta\quad\theta}. By abuse of notation let us denote cGc_{G} by cc.

Assume that A[μ+]μ+A\in[\mu^{+}]^{\mu^{+}} and B[μ]θB\in[\mu]^{\theta} in V[G]V[G]. By Proposition 1.1 one can find a[A]μ+Va\in[A]^{\mu^{+}}\cap V and b[B]θVb\in[B]^{\theta}\cap V. By (c)(c) we know that 1c′′(a×b)1\in c^{\prime\prime}(a\times b) and then 1c′′(A×B)1\in c^{\prime\prime}(A\times B). Similarly, if A[μ+]ω1A\in[\mu^{+}]^{\omega_{1}} and B[μ]θB\in[\mu]^{\theta} then one can choose a[A]ω1a\in[A]^{\omega_{1}} and b[B]θb\in[B]^{\theta} from the ground model. It follows that 0c′′(a×b)c′′(A×B)0\in c^{\prime\prime}(a\times b)\subseteq c^{\prime\prime}(A\times B), so we are done.

1.2\qed_{\ref{clmnonslimit}}

Assumptions in the spirit of the above claim can be forced by adding many Cohen sets to some relatively small cardinal. This idea is applicable to non strong limit cardinals, and an interesting example will be proved anon. We mention here [2, Problem 14], which asks whether (ω+1ω+1)(ω+1ω1ωω)\binom{\aleph_{\omega+1}}{\aleph_{\omega+1}}\rightarrow\binom{\aleph_{\omega+1}\ \omega_{1}}{\aleph_{\omega}\quad\aleph_{\omega}}.

Claim 1.3.

It is consistent that μ>cf(μ)=ω,2ω<μ\mu>{\rm cf}(\mu)=\omega,2^{\omega}<\mu, but (μ+μ+)(μ+ω1μμ)\binom{\mu^{+}}{\mu^{+}}\nrightarrow\binom{\mu^{+}\ \omega_{1}}{\mu\quad\mu} and even (μ+μ+)(μ+ωμμ)\binom{\mu^{+}}{\mu^{+}}\nrightarrow\binom{\mu^{+}\ \omega}{\mu\quad\mu}.

Proof.
Begin with μ>cf(μ)=κ\mu>{\rm cf}(\mu)=\kappa such that κ\kappa is measurable and 2κ=κ+2^{\kappa}=\kappa^{+}. Choose θ=cf(θ)\theta={\rm cf}(\theta) such that κ+<θ<μ\kappa^{+}<\theta<\mu. Let \mathbb{Q} be Add(θ,μ+)Add(\theta,\mu^{+}) and let GG\subseteq\mathbb{Q} be VV-generic. By [1, Theorem 7.4] we have (μ+μ+)(θ+θ)\binom{\mu^{+}}{\mu^{+}}\nrightarrow\binom{\theta^{+}}{\theta} in V[G]V[G].

Working in V[G]V[G], let \mathbb{P} be Prikry forcing through κ\kappa (notice that κ\kappa remains measurable in V[G]V[G]). Let HH\subseteq\mathbb{P} be V[G]V[G]-generic. The argument in the proof of Claim 1.2 gives (μ+μ+)(μ+θ+θθ)\binom{\mu^{+}}{\mu^{+}}\nrightarrow\binom{\mu^{+}\ \theta^{+}}{\theta\quad\theta} in V[G][H]V[G][H].

Moreover, suppose that θ<λ<μ\theta<\lambda<\mu and cf(λ)=ω1{\rm cf}(\lambda)=\omega_{1}. By monotonicity we have (μ+μ+)(μ+λθθ)\binom{\mu^{+}}{\mu^{+}}\nrightarrow\binom{\mu^{+}\ \lambda}{\theta\quad\theta} in V[G][H]V[G][H], and since 2ω1<μ2^{\omega_{1}}<\mu we see that (μ+μ+)(μ+ω1θθ)\binom{\mu^{+}}{\mu^{+}}\nrightarrow\binom{\mu^{+}\ \omega_{1}}{\theta\quad\theta} as well. Another application of monotonicity yields (μ+μ+)(μ+ω1μμ)\binom{\mu^{+}}{\mu^{+}}\nrightarrow\binom{\mu^{+}\ \omega_{1}}{\mu\quad\mu} in V[G][H]V[G][H], as desired. The same argument gives the negative relation (μ+μ+)(μ+ωμμ)\binom{\mu^{+}}{\mu^{+}}\nrightarrow\binom{\mu^{+}\ \omega}{\mu\quad\mu} if one chooses λ>θ\lambda>\theta with cf(λ)=ω{\rm cf}(\lambda)=\omega, so the proof is accomplished.

1.3\qed_{\ref{clm14}}

Observe that 2cf(μ)<μ2^{{\rm cf}(\mu)}<\mu is satisfied in the generic extension, and for every specific χ<μ\chi<\mu one can force as in the above claim while retaining 2χ<μ2^{\chi}<\mu by choosing θ(χ,μ)\theta\in(\chi,\mu). However, the above idea seems to be inapplicable if one considers strong limit cardinals. In particular, the following claim shows that negative assumptions in the ground model with respect to some θ<μ\theta<\mu as needed for the above proof are impossible.

Claim 1.4.

Suppose that μ\mu is a strong limit cardinal and θ<μ\theta<\mu. Then (μ+μ)(μ+μ+μθ)\binom{\mu^{+}}{\mu}\rightarrow\binom{\mu^{+}\ \mu^{+}}{\mu\quad\theta}.

Proof.
Suppose that c:μ+×μ2c:\mu^{+}\times\mu\rightarrow 2. Let κ=cf(μ)μ\kappa={\rm cf}(\mu)\leq\mu and let (μγ:γκ)(\mu_{\gamma}:\gamma\in\kappa) be an increasing sequence of cardinals such that μ=γκμγ\mu=\bigcup_{\gamma\in\kappa}\mu_{\gamma}. For every αμ+\alpha\in\mu^{+} and each i{0,1}i\in\{0,1\} define:

Aαi={βμ:c(α,β)=i}.A_{\alpha i}=\{\beta\in\mu:c(\alpha,\beta)=i\}.

Let ={Aα1:αμ+}\mathcal{F}=\{A_{\alpha 1}:\alpha\in\mu^{+}\}. By [9, Lemma 1] either there is some B[μ+]μ+B\in[\mu^{+}]^{\mu^{+}} such that |{μAα1:αB}|=μ|\bigcap\{\mu-A_{\alpha 1}:\alpha\in B\}|=\mu or there exists A[μ+]μ+A\in[\mu^{+}]^{\mu^{+}} such that {Aα1:αA}\{A_{\alpha 1}:\alpha\in A\} is a μ\mu-uniform filter base.

Lest the first option obtains we have a 0-monochromatic product B×CB\times C of size μ+×μ\mu^{+}\times\mu, stipulating C={μAα1:αB}C=\bigcap\{\mu-A_{\alpha 1}:\alpha\in B\}. If the second option holds, choose for every αA\alpha\in A an ordinal γ(α)κ\gamma(\alpha)\in\kappa such that |Aα1μγ(α)|θ|A_{\alpha 1}\cap\mu_{\gamma(\alpha)}|\geq\theta. Since |A|=μ+|A|=\mu^{+} we may assume, without loss of generality, that γ(α)=γ\gamma(\alpha)=\gamma for every αA\alpha\in A and some fixed γκ\gamma\in\kappa. Since μγ<μ\mu_{\gamma}<\mu and μ\mu is strong limit we see that |𝒫(μγ)|<μ<μ+|\mathcal{P}(\mu_{\gamma})|<\mu<\mu^{+}. Hence without loss of generality there is a fixed aμγa\subseteq\mu_{\gamma} such that |a|θ|a|\geq\theta and Aα1μγ=aA_{\alpha 1}\cap\mu_{\gamma}=a for every αA\alpha\in A. Verify that A×aA\times a is 11-monochromatic and conclude that (μ+μ)(μ+μ+μθ)\binom{\mu^{+}}{\mu}\rightarrow\binom{\mu^{+}\ \mu^{+}}{\mu\quad\theta} as desired.

1.4\qed_{\ref{clmslimit}}

Although we cannot use old colorings in the context of strong limit cardinals, we can still exploit the density arguments for sets of size ω1\omega_{1}. The following is the main result of this section:

Theorem 1.5.

It is consistent that μ\mu is a strong limit singular cardinal of countable cofinality, 2μ=μ+2^{\mu}=\mu^{+} and (μ+μ)(μ+ω1μμ)\binom{\mu^{+}}{\mu}\nrightarrow\binom{\mu^{+}\ \omega_{1}}{\mu\quad\mu}.

Proof.
Let μ\mu be a measurable cardinal, assume that 2μ=μ+2^{\mu}=\mu^{+} and let \mathbb{P} be Prikry forcing into μ\mu. We claim that (μ+μ)(μ+ω1μμ)\binom{\mu^{+}}{\mu}\nrightarrow\binom{\mu^{+}\ \omega_{1}}{\mu\quad\mu} in the generic extension by \mathbb{P}. Choose a generic subset GG\subseteq\mathbb{P}. We shall define a coloring c:μ+×μ2c:\mu^{+}\times\mu\rightarrow 2 in V[G]V[G].

As a first step we enumerate [μ+]μ[\mu^{+}]^{\mu} by {Bα:αμ+}\{B_{\alpha}:\alpha\in\mu^{+}\}. Now for each α(0,μ+)\alpha\in(0,\mu^{+}) we enumerate {Bβ:βα}\{B_{\beta}:\beta\in\alpha\} in such a way that the order-type will be μ\mu, say {Bαε:εμ}\{B_{\alpha\varepsilon}:\varepsilon\in\mu\}. If αμ\alpha\in\mu then we use repetitions. Similarly, for each α(0,μ+)\alpha\in(0,\mu^{+}) we list the ordinals of α\alpha by an enumeration of order-type μ\mu, say {αη:ημ}\{\alpha_{\eta}:\eta\in\mu\}. We emphasize that this enumeration of the ordinals of μ+\mu^{+} is done already in the ground model.

As a second step we choose for every αμ+\alpha\in\mu^{+} and each BαεB_{\alpha\varepsilon} an ordinal βBαε\beta\in B_{\alpha\varepsilon} with the goal of setting c(α,β)=1c(\alpha,\beta)=1. We do this, however, with some control. Fix αμ+\alpha\in\mu^{+} and choose for each εμ\varepsilon\in\mu an ordinal γαε\gamma_{\alpha\varepsilon} so that γαεBαε{γαηζ:η<ε,ζε}\gamma_{\alpha\varepsilon}\in B_{\alpha\varepsilon}-\{\gamma_{\alpha_{\eta}\zeta}:\eta<\varepsilon,\zeta\leq\varepsilon\}. Notice that we remove a small set from BαεB_{\alpha\varepsilon} and |Bαε|=μ|B_{\alpha\varepsilon}|=\mu, so the choice is possible. Define:

c(α,β)=1εμ,β=γαε.c(\alpha,\beta)=1\Leftrightarrow\exists\varepsilon\in\mu,\beta=\gamma_{\alpha\varepsilon}.

We must show that cc has no 0-monochromatic product of size μ+×μ\mu^{+}\times\mu and no 11-monochromatic product of size ω1×μ\omega_{1}\times\mu.

For the first mission suppose that A[μ+]μ+A\in[\mu^{+}]^{\mu^{+}} and B[μ]μB\in[\mu]^{\mu}. Let αA\alpha\in A be such that B{Bβ:βα}B\in\{B_{\beta}:\beta\in\alpha\} and let εμ\varepsilon\in\mu be such that B=BαεB=B_{\alpha\varepsilon}. Let β=γαε\beta=\gamma_{\alpha\varepsilon}, so βBαε=B\beta\in B_{\alpha\varepsilon}=B. By definition, c(α,β)=1c(\alpha,\beta)=1 and hence A×BA\times B is not 0-monochromatic.

For the second mission assume that A[μ+]ω1A\in[\mu^{+}]^{\omega_{1}} and B[μ]μB\in[\mu]^{\mu}. Assume toward contradiction that A×BA\times B is 11-monochromatic. Choose AAA^{\prime}\subseteq A such that |A|=1|A^{\prime}|=\aleph_{1} and AVA^{\prime}\in V. Define S={ημ:γ,δA,γ=δη}S=\{\eta\in\mu:\exists\gamma,\delta\in A^{\prime},\gamma=\delta_{\eta}\}. Notice that SμS\subseteq\mu and SVS\in V since AVA^{\prime}\in V. In particular, SS is bounded in μ\mu, so let ρ=sup(S)<μ\rho=\sup(S)<\mu. Define T={βμ:αA,c(α,β)=1}T=\{\beta\in\mu:\forall\alpha\in A^{\prime},c(\alpha,\beta)=1\}. Observe that TBT\supseteq B since AAA^{\prime}\subseteq A and for every αA,βB\alpha\in A,\beta\in B we have c(α,β)=1c(\alpha,\beta)=1. We shall prove that |T|<μ|T|<\mu thus arriving at a contradiction since |B|=μ|B|=\mu.

Firstly we observe that if αμ+\alpha\in\mu^{+} and η<ε<μ\eta<\varepsilon<\mu and γ(αη,ζ)=γ(α,ε)\gamma(\alpha_{\eta},\zeta)=\gamma(\alpha,\varepsilon) then ε<ζ\varepsilon<\zeta. To see this recall that αη<α\alpha_{\eta}<\alpha, so if ζε\zeta\leq\varepsilon then we required in the choice of the γ\gammas that γ(αη,ζ)γ(α,ε)\gamma(\alpha_{\eta},\zeta)\neq\gamma(\alpha,\varepsilon). Secondly, choose some βT\beta\in T and recall that c(α,β)=1c(\alpha,\beta)=1 for every αA\alpha\in A^{\prime}. It follows that for each αA\alpha\in A^{\prime} there exists a unique ordinal ε(α)μ\varepsilon(\alpha)\in\mu such that β=γαε(α)\beta=\gamma_{\alpha\varepsilon(\alpha)}. We claim that there must be some αA\alpha\in A^{\prime} for which ε(α)ρ\varepsilon(\alpha)\in\rho. Suppose not, and choose σ,δA\sigma,\delta\in A^{\prime} such that σ<δ\sigma<\delta. Let ημ\eta\in\mu be so that σ=δη\sigma=\delta_{\eta}. By the definition of ρ\rho we see that η<ρ\eta<\rho, so η<ε(δ)\eta<\varepsilon(\delta) by our assumption. Since both γσε(σ)=β\gamma_{\sigma\varepsilon(\sigma)}=\beta and γδε(δ)=β\gamma_{\delta\varepsilon(\delta)}=\beta we see that γσε(σ)=γδε(δ)\gamma_{\sigma\varepsilon(\sigma)}=\gamma_{\delta\varepsilon(\delta)} and by the above observation we have ε(σ)>ε(δ)\varepsilon(\sigma)>\varepsilon(\delta). Since AA^{\prime} is infinite, if we choose an increasing sequence σn:nω\langle\sigma_{n}:n\in\omega\rangle of elements of AA^{\prime} we produce an infinite decreasing sequence of ordinals ε(σn):nω\langle\varepsilon(\sigma_{n}):n\in\omega\rangle, which is an absurd.

Therefore, for each βT\beta\in T we choose αA\alpha\in A^{\prime} such that β=γαε(α)\beta=\gamma_{\alpha\varepsilon(\alpha)} and ε(α)<ρ\varepsilon(\alpha)<\rho. It follows now from the definition of the set TT that T{γαε:αA,ε<ρ}T\subseteq\{\gamma_{\alpha\varepsilon}:\alpha\in A^{\prime},\varepsilon<\rho\} and hence |T||ρ|1<μ|T|\leq|\rho|\cdot\aleph_{1}<\mu, so we are done.

1.5\qed_{\ref{thmmt}}

The above theorem was proved using Prikry forcing, and this is probably the simplest way to carry out the argument. But the method itself is a bit more general, and in particular applies to a wider collection of forcing notions. If \mathbb{P} forces countable cofinality to μ\mu where μcf(μ)>ω\mu\geq{\rm cf}(\mu)>\omega in the ground model and every new set of size 1\aleph_{1} contains an old set of size 1\aleph_{1} then a similar proof works. Consequently, one can use other Prikry-type forcing notions. An answer to [2, Problems 10 and 14] can be given now using Magidor’s method from [10] and [11] to singularize a measurable cardinal with interleaved collapses.

Corollary 1.6.

It is consistent that (μ+μ)(μ+ω1μμ)\binom{\mu^{+}}{\mu}\nrightarrow\binom{\mu^{+}\ \omega_{1}}{\mu\quad\mu} where μ=ω\mu=\aleph_{\omega} is strong limit and 2μ=μ+2^{\mu}=\mu^{+}. Similarly, (μ+μ+)(μ+ω1μμ)\binom{\mu^{+}}{\mu^{+}}\nrightarrow\binom{\mu^{+}\ \omega_{1}}{\mu\quad\mu} is consistent at μ=ω\mu=\aleph_{\omega} under the same assumptions.

1.6\qed_{\ref{coralephomega}}

The following remark which sheds some light on the role of ω1\omega_{1} in the above statements. The general idea behind the proof of the main result it to begin with a negative relation at μ\mu, to force a desired property of μ\mu (here it is countable cofinality) in such a way that the negative relation is preserved. Thus we commence with a measurable cardinal μ\mu with 2μ=μ+2^{\mu}=\mu^{+} so (μ+μ)(μ+ω1μμ)\binom{\mu^{+}}{\mu}\nrightarrow\binom{\mu^{+}\ \omega_{1}}{\mu\quad\mu} in the ground model, and we force Prikry in order to singularize μ\mu while keeping the negative relation.

But under the above assumption we know that (μ+μ)(μ+ωμμ)\binom{\mu^{+}}{\mu}\nrightarrow\binom{\mu^{+}\ \omega}{\mu\quad\mu} as well in the ground model. When we force with Prikry forcing we secure the negative relation (μ+μ)(μ+ω1μμ)\binom{\mu^{+}}{\mu}\nrightarrow\binom{\mu^{+}\ \omega_{1}}{\mu\quad\mu} but we also get the positive relation (μ+μ)(μ+ωμμ)\binom{\mu^{+}}{\mu}\rightarrow\binom{\mu^{+}\ \omega}{\mu\quad\mu} in the generic extension. One may wonder what is the difference between ω\omega and ω1\omega_{1} in this context, and at least one aspect of the answer becomes clearer. New sets of size 1\aleph_{1} in the Prikry extension contain old sets of the same size. Contrariwise, new ω\omega-sequences cannot be approximated by infinite sets from the ground model. This fact explains the peculiarity of singular cardinals with countable cofinality with respect to the unbalanced relation discussed in this paper.

We conclude with a couple of open problems. The first one is about the possibility of the positive direction.

Question 1.7.

Is it consistent that the positive relation (μ+μ)(μ+ω1μμ)\binom{\mu^{+}}{\mu}\rightarrow\binom{\mu^{+}\ \omega_{1}}{\mu\quad\mu} holds under GCH where μ>cf(μ)=ω\mu>{\rm cf}(\mu)=\omega?

For the second question let us indicate that large cardinals are not necessary in order to force (μ+μ)(μ+ω1μμ)\binom{\mu^{+}}{\mu}\nrightarrow\binom{\mu^{+}\ \omega_{1}}{\mu\quad\mu} under the above assumptions. For example, if one forces with Namba forcing over the constructible universe then every singular cardinal μ\mu so that cfV(μ)=ω2{\rm cf}^{V}(\mu)=\omega_{2} will satisfy (μ+μ)(μ+ω1μμ)\binom{\mu^{+}}{\mu}\nrightarrow\binom{\mu^{+}\ \omega_{1}}{\mu\quad\mu} in the generic extension. However, by assuming the existence of large cardinals one can force a universe in which every singular strong limit cardinal with countable cofinality is ex-measurable, and then (μ+μ)(μ+ω1μμ)\binom{\mu^{+}}{\mu}\nrightarrow\binom{\mu^{+}\ \omega_{1}}{\mu\quad\mu} holds globally at every such cardinal. We do not know whether large cardinals are indispensable for this result:

Question 1.8.

Can one force without large cardinals that GCH holds, and (μ+μ)(μ+ω1μμ)\binom{\mu^{+}}{\mu}\nrightarrow\binom{\mu^{+}\ \omega_{1}}{\mu\quad\mu} whenever μ>cf(μ)=ω\mu>{\rm cf}(\mu)=\omega?

References

  • [1] James E. Baumgartner, Almost-disjoint sets, the dense set problem and the partition calculus, Ann. Math. Logic 9 (1976), no. 4, 401–439. MR 401472
  • [2] P. Erdős, A. Hajnal, and R. Rado, Partition relations for cardinal numbers, Acta Math. Acad. Sci. Hungar. 16 (1965), 93–196. MR MR0202613 (34 #2475)
  • [3] Paul Erdős, András Hajnal, Attila Máté, and Richard Rado, Combinatorial set theory: partition relations for cardinals, Studies in Logic and the Foundations of Mathematics, vol. 106, North-Holland Publishing Co., Amsterdam, 1984. MR MR795592 (87g:04002)
  • [4] Shimon Garti, Polarized relations at singulars over successors, Discrete Math. 343 (2020), no. 9, 111961, 9. MR 4101445
  • [5] Shimon Garti, Menachem Magidor, and Saharon Shelah, Infinite monochromatic paths and a theorem of Erdos-Hajnal-Rado, Electron. J. Combin. 27 (2020), no. 2, 11 pages.
  • [6] Shimon Garti and Saharon Shelah, A strong polarized relation, J. Symbolic Logic 77 (2012), no. 3, 766–776. MR 2987137
  • [7] Moti Gitik, Prikry-type forcings, Handbook of set theory. Vols. 1, 2, 3, Springer, Dordrecht, 2010, pp. 1351–1447. MR 2768695
  • [8] András Hajnal and Jean A. Larson, Partition relations, Handbook of set theory. Vols. 1, 2, 3, Springer, Dordrecht, 2010, pp. 129–213. MR 2768681
  • [9] Albin L. Jones, A polarized partition relation for cardinals of countable cofinality, Proc. Amer. Math. Soc. 136 (2008), no. 4, 1445–1449. MR 2367118
  • [10] Menachem Magidor, On the singular cardinals problem. I, Israel J. Math. 28 (1977), no. 1-2, 1–31. MR 491183
  • [11] by same author, On the singular cardinals problem. II, Ann. of Math. (2) 106 (1977), no. 3, 517–547. MR 491184
  • [12] A. R. D. Mathias, On sequences generic in the sense of Prikry, J. Austral. Math. Soc. 15 (1973), 409–414. MR 0332482
  • [13] Saharon Shelah, A polarized partition relation and failure of GCH at singular strong limit, Fund. Math. 155 (1998), no. 2, 153–160. MR 1606515
  • [14] Neil H. Williams, Combinatorial set theory, Studies in Logic and the Foundations of Mathematics, vol. 91, North-Holland Publishing Co., Amsterdam, 1977. MR 3075383