This paper was converted on www.awesomepapers.org from LaTeX by an anonymous user.
Want to know more? Visit the Converter page.

Varsovian models II

Grigor Sargsyan Ralf Schindler Farmer Schlutzenberg
(September 14, 2025)
Abstract

Assume sufficient large cardinals. Let MswnM_{\mathrm{sw}n} be the minimal iterable proper class L[E]L[E] model satisfying “there are δ0<κ0<<δn1<κn1\delta_{0}<\kappa_{0}<\ldots<\delta_{n-1}<\kappa_{n-1} such that the δi\delta_{i} are Woodin cardinals and the κi\kappa_{i} are strong cardinals”. Let M=Msw2M=M_{\mathrm{sw}2}. We identify an inner model 𝒱2M\mathscr{V}_{2}^{M} of MM, which is a proper class model satisfying “there are 2 Woodin cardinals”, and is iterable both in VV and in MM, and closed under its own iteration strategy. The construction also yields significant information about the extent to which MM knows its own iteration strategy. We characterize the universe of 𝒱2M\mathscr{V}_{2}^{M} as the mantle and the least ground of MM, and as HODM[G]\mathrm{HOD}^{M[G]} for GColl(ω,λ)G\subseteq\mathrm{Coll}(\omega,\lambda) being MM-generic with λ\lambda sufficiently large. These results correspond to facts already known for Msw1M_{\mathrm{sw}1}, and the proofs are an elaboration of those, but there are substantial new issues and new methods with which to handle them. 2222020 Mathematics Subject Classifications: 03E45, 03E55, 03E40. 333Keywords: Inner model theory, mouse, iteration strategy, self-iterability, strategy mouse, HOD, mantle, ground, Varsovian model.

1 Introduction

The first generation of canonical inner models for large cardinals are those of the form M=L[E]M=L[E] (or Lα[E]L_{\alpha}[E]) where EE is a sequence of (partial) measures or extenders with various nice properties. The second generation are those of the form M=L[E,Σ]M=L[E,\Sigma] (or Lα[E,Σ]L_{\alpha}[E,\Sigma]), with EE as before, but Σ\Sigma is a (partial) iteration strategy for MM. We refer to the former as mice or extender models, and the latter as strategy mice or strategic extender models. Strategy mice arise naturally as HODs of determinacy models, and this phenomenon has been extensively studied. (The universe of) a strategy mouse 𝒱Msw\mathscr{V}^{{M_{\rm sw}}} was also found in [8] to be the mantle of and a certain HOD associated to the mouse Msw=Msw1M_{\mathrm{sw}}=M_{\mathrm{sw}1} (the “minimal” proper class mouse with a strong cardinal above a Woodin cardinal). While mice with Woodin cardinals (and which model ZFC, for example) can only compute restricted fragments of their own iteration strategies, strategy mice can be fully self-iterable.

One can contemplate the relationship between the two hierarchies; a key issue is the consistency strength of large cardinals when exhibited in the respective models: how do large cardinal hypotheses in (fully iterable) mice compare in consistency strength to those in (fully iterable) strategy mice, particularly for strategy mice which are closed under their own strategy? Continuing the line of investigation of [8], the present paper derives444Disclaimer: The “proofs” (and some definitions) presented here are not quite complete, because their full exposition depends on an integration, omitted here, of the method of *-translation (see [1]) with the techniques we develop. The integration itself is a straightforward matter of combining the two things. But because *-translation itself is already quite detailed, its inclusion would have added significantly to the length of the paper. It will be covered instead in [13]. the existence of a fully iterable proper class strategy mouse 𝒱=L[E,Σ]\mathscr{V}=L[E,\Sigma], closed under its strategy, and containing two Woodin cardinals, from the existence and full iterability of the mouse Mswsw#M_{\mathrm{swsw}}^{\#}. This is the least active mouse NN such that letting κ=crit(F)\kappa={\rm crit}(F) where FF is the active extender of NN, then N|κN|\kappa\vDash“There are ordinals δ0<κ0<δ1<κ1\delta_{0}<\kappa_{0}<\delta_{1}<\kappa_{1} such that each δi\delta_{i} is a Woodin cardinal and each κi\kappa_{i} is a strong cardinal”. Letting MswswM_{\mathrm{swsw}} be the proper class model left behind after iterating FF out of the universe, the strategy mouse 𝒱\mathscr{V} will be an inner model of MswswM_{\mathrm{swsw}}. (We also obtain Silver indiscernibles for 𝒱\mathscr{V}.) The analysis also shows that MswswM_{\mathrm{swsw}} computes substantial fragments of its own iteration strategy, thereby contributing to the investigation of self-iterability in mice as in [12], but here beyond the tame level.

Now recall that if WW is a model of ZFC, then PWP\subseteq W is a ground of WW iff PP is also a model of ZFC and there is some poset P{\mathbb{P}}\in P and some gg which is (P,)(P,{\mathbb{P}})-generic with W=P[g]W=P[g]. (Note this implies that PP is transitive in the sense of WW and contains all of the ordinals of WW; by the Woodin/Laver ground definability result [2], [6], PP is also definable from parameters over WW.) The intersection of all grounds of WW is called the mantle 𝕄W\mathbb{M}^{W} of WW. Recall WW is called a bedrock iff WW has no non-trivial grounds, or equivalently, W=𝕄WW=\mathbb{M}^{W}. See [2] and [25] for more general background on these topics not specific to inner model theory.

The reason that mice modelling ZFC + Woodin cardinals do not compute their own iteration strategies is connected with the fact that they have proper (set-)grounds. The standard examples of such grounds arise from Woodin’s genericity iterations. This phenomenon has led to inner model theoretic geology, which has proven to be an exciting and fruitful area of set theory. Its program is to analyze the collection of grounds and the mantle of given canonical inner models. See [3] and [8], which address exactly this kind of problem, and are precursors to the current work. See also [16], parts of which were motivated by the current work. The theme uncovered in these works is roughly that the mantle of a (sufficiently canonical) mouse tends to itself be a mouse or a strategy mouse, and hence can be analyzed in high detail.

The paper [3] proves that if M=L[E]M=L[E] is a tame proper class mouse with a Woodin cardinal but no strong cardinal, and some further technical assumptions hold, then the mantle of MM is itself a mouse, but is not a ground of L[E]L[E]; see [3, §3.4] and specifically [3, Theorem 3.33]. As an example, the mantle of M1M_{1} (the minimal proper class mouse with one Woodin cardinal) is the model left behind after iterating the unique measure on the least measurable of M1M_{1} out of the universe, and note this model has no measurable cardinals. The situation is entirely different if L[E]L[E] has a strong cardinal.

Let Msw#{M_{\rm sw}}^{\#} denote the minimal active mouse NN such that letting κ=crit(F)\kappa={\rm crit}(F) where FF is the active extender of NN, then N|κN|\kappa\vDash“there is a strong cardinal above a Woodin cardinal”, and suppose this mouse is fully iterable (for all set-sized trees). Let MswswM_{\mathrm{swsw}} be the proper class mouse left by iterating FF out of the universe. It is shown in [8] that there are only set many grounds of Msw{M_{\rm sw}} and that the mantle of Msw{M_{\rm sw}} is itself a ground of Msw{M_{\rm sw}} and hence a bedrock. There is therefore some analogy here between Msw{M_{\rm sw}} and VV in the presence of an extendible cardinal; see [26, Theorem 1.3]. The mantle of Msw{M_{\rm sw}}, however, also has an interesting structural analysis, as it is the universe of the strategy mouse 𝒱Msw\mathscr{V}^{{M_{\rm sw}}} mentioned earlier. It is, moreover, a canonical “least” inner model which has a Woodin cardinal and knows how to fully iterate itself; see [8, Lemma 2.20].

In personal communication with the second author [27], W. Hugh Woodin expressed suspicion that the mantle of any proper class mouse L[E]L[E] with a strong cardinal above a Woodin cardinal might perhaps contain non-trivial strategy information at its least Woodin cardinal and not at any larger Woodin.

A reasonable candidate for testing this suspicion and for extending the analysis of [8] is the big brother of Msw{M_{\rm sw}}, namely M=MswswM=M_{\mathrm{swsw}}, introduced above, and studied in this paper. We will show that the strategy mouse 𝒱M\mathscr{V}^{M}, also introduced above, has universe the mantle of MM, and so in fact, this mantle contains two Woodins together with non-trivial (and is closed under) strategy information for both of them. There is therefore a stronger analogy between hod mice (see [7]) and mantles of extender models L[E]L[E] than was previously expected. This universe is also a ground of MM, and hence is a bedrock. We will also show that 𝒱M\mathscr{V}^{M} has universe the eventual generic HOD of MM; that is, its universe is HODM[G]\mathrm{HOD}^{M[G]} whenever λ\lambda is a sufficiently large ordinal and GColl(ω,λ)G\subseteq\mathrm{Coll}(\omega,\lambda) is MM-generic.

In some more detail, we will first isolate the first Varsovian model 𝒱1=𝒱1M\mathscr{V}_{1}={\mathscr{V}}_{1}^{M} of MM and show that 𝒱1{\mathscr{V}}_{1} is a ground of MM, contains exactly two Woodin cardinals and a strong above them, and knows how to iterate itself fully for trees based on its least Woodin. This model is at first constructed in the form of “L[,]L[\mathcal{M}_{\infty},*]”, very much like in the construction of [8], which also mirrors Woodin’s analysis of HODL[x,G]\mathrm{HOD}^{L[x,G]}. We then show that this model admits a stratification as a fine structural strategy premouse. The indexing used for the stratification is new, and this indexing is important in the overall analysis we give. It is moreover determined in a very strong sense by the hierarchy of MM – the extender sequence of 𝒱1\mathscr{V}_{1} is in fact given by simply restricting the extenders on the sequence of MM above a certain point, some of which correspond to strategy. We then go on to isolate the second Varsovian model 𝒱2=𝒱2M\mathscr{V}_{2}=\mathscr{V}_{2}^{M} of MM, which will be constructed inside 𝒱1\mathscr{V}_{1} (so 𝒱2𝒱1M\mathscr{V}_{2}\subseteq\mathscr{V}_{1}\subseteq M), using an elaboration of the construction of 𝒱1\mathscr{V}_{1} in MM. We then analyze the model and compute an iteration strategy for it, and establish the remaining facts mentioned above: the universe of 𝒱2\mathscr{V}_{2} is the mantle and eventual generic HOD of MM, 𝒱2\mathscr{V}_{2} contains exactly two Woodin cardinals and knows fully how to iterate itself. We also show that the universe of 𝒱1\mathscr{V}_{1} is the κ0\kappa_{0}-mantle of MM, where κ0\kappa_{0} is the least strong of MM. The overall picture and process is expected to generalize to n<ωn<\omega iterations (working in the appropriate starting mouse) and beyond.

The reader who is familiar with [7], for example, will encounter a lot of parallels between our analysis and the theory of hod mice; a key difference, though, is that our treatment is purely combinatorial and “inner model theoretic”, using no descriptive set theory. Familiarity with [8] certainly helps, since the current paper is in large part an extension of that one, and some arguments covered in [8] are omitted here. But the reader who is reasonably familiar with inner model theory in general should be able to refer to [8] as needed.

The paper is organized as follows. There are some preliminaries and notation listed at the end of this section. In §2, we present the general method of assigning the (first) Varsovian model 𝒱L[E]{\mathscr{V}}^{L[E]} to an extender model L[E]L[E], and prove key facts about it, under certain hypotheses. In §3, we describe some key properties of MswswM_{\mathrm{swsw}} and its iteration strategy, which will be essential throughout. In §4, the first Varsovian model 𝒱1\mathscr{V}_{1} of MM, and its iteration strategy Σ𝒱1\Sigma_{\mathscr{V}_{1}}, are defined and analyzed. This analysis is centered around the stratification of 𝒱1\mathscr{V}_{1} as a strategy premouse. We also give natural characterizations of the universe of 𝒱1\mathscr{V}_{1}. In §5, we identify 𝒱2\mathscr{V}_{2}, also stratifying it as a strategy premouse. We show that 𝒱2\mathscr{V}_{2} has two Woodin cardinals, is fully iterable, and is closed under its iteration strategy. We expect that the hypothesis used to construct such a model is in some sense optimal. We finally show in §5.8 that the universe of 𝒱2\mathscr{V}_{2} is the mantle of MM and is HODM[G]\mathrm{HOD}^{M[G]} for sufficiently large collapse generics GG.

The work presented here was started by the first two authors, extending their [8]. In the early stages, significant progress was made, but without a full development of the level-by-level fine structural correspondence presented in this paper between the models M=MswswM=M_{\mathrm{swsw}}, 𝒱1\mathscr{V}_{1} and 𝒱2\mathscr{V}_{2}; such a correspondence was considered to some extent, but then put aside in favour of other methods. During this time, the first author developed an approach to computing the mantle of MM which does not use the level-by-level correspondence, but this has not been published. Later, the second author returned to the level-by-level correspondence, and developed some of the main ideas in its connection. Following this, in September 2017, the second and third authors then began discussing this approach. Over the next few months, building on what had already been established, they (mostly) completed the analysis via this approach, leading to the current presentation (some details being added over time somewhat later). Some of the evolution of ideas was documented by the second author’s talks at the 4th Münster conference on inner model theory, July 17–Aug 01, 2017, and at the 1st Girona conference on inner model theory, July 16–27, 2018, and in the handwritten notes [10].

The early development, worked out by the first two authors, directly yielded parts of the present paper, as well as precursors to some other parts. Some version of probably the most central concept in the paper, the strategy mouse hierarchy used in Definition 4.10 (which is also a precursor of Definition 5.17), is due to the first two authors, as is §4.7; the setup for the first direct limit system in §§4.1,4.3,4.4 is much as in [8] and is basically due to them, although the approach used in §4.2 for computing short tree strategy, and some other uses of normalization, are due to the 3rd author. The 2nd author is responsible for the majority of §2, including Definition 2.3, for the computation of HODM[G]\mathrm{HOD}_{\mathscr{E}}^{M[G]} in Theorem 4.5 via extending Lemma 4.5 (and the idea to consider HOD\mathrm{HOD}_{\mathscr{E}}), and the modified P-construction (Definition 5.4). The 2nd and 3rd authors jointly established Lemma 5.1.1, the construction of the second direct limit system in §5.2, and the strategy mouse hierarchy used in Definition 5.17 (adapting 4.10). The (self-)iterability of 𝒱1\mathscr{V}_{1} and 𝒱2\mathscr{V}_{2} is also mostly due to the 2nd and 3rd authors, integrating some of the earlier work of the first two. The 3rd author is responsible for Lemma 4.5, that 𝒱1[]\mathscr{V}_{1}\subseteq\mathcal{M}_{\infty}[*], Lemmas 2, 4.9, 4.12.4, 4.12.5, 5.6.4, 5.6.5, Definitions 4.28, 5.32, §§4.10, 4.11, 5.1.2, 5.1.3, 5.8, and the original version of §4.8.

1.1 Notation and Background

General: Given structures P,QP,Q, P\left\lfloor P\right\rfloor denotes the universe of PP, and P=^QP\ \widehat{=}\ Q means P=Q\left\lfloor P\right\rfloor=\left\lfloor Q\right\rfloor.

Premice: All premice in the paper are Jensen-indexed (λ\lambda-indexed). Given premouse N=(U,𝔼,F)N=(U,\mathbb{E},F) with universe UU, internal extender sequence 𝔼\mathbb{E} and active extender FF, we write N=U\left\lfloor N\right\rfloor=U, 𝔼N=𝔼\mathbb{E}^{N}=\mathbb{E}, FN=FF^{N}=F, and 𝔼+N=𝔼^F\mathbb{E}_{+}^{N}=\mathbb{E}\ \widehat{\ }\ F. Write Npv=(U,𝔼,)N^{\mathrm{pv}}=(U,\mathbb{E},\emptyset) for its passivization, N||αN||\alpha for the initial segment PP of NN with ORP=α\mathrm{OR}^{P}=\alpha (inclusive of active extender) and N|α=(N||α)pvN|\alpha=(N||\alpha)^{\mathrm{pv}}. Write lh(F)=ORN{\rm lh}(F)=\mathrm{OR}^{N}. Given premice M,NM,N, we write MNM\trianglelefteq N iff M=N||αM=N||\alpha for some αORN\alpha\leq\mathrm{OR}^{N}, and MNM\triangleleft N iff MNM\trianglelefteq N but NMN\not\trianglelefteq M. Given also m,nωm,n\leq\omega such that MM is mm-sound and NN is nn-sound, we write (M,m)(N,n)(M,m)\trianglelefteq(N,n) iff MNM\trianglelefteq N and if M=NM=N then mnm\leq n, and write (M,m)(N,n)(M,m)\triangleleft(N,n) iff (M,m)(N,n)(M,m)\trianglelefteq(N,n) but (N,n)(M,m)(N,n)\not\trianglelefteq(M,m). For ηORN\eta\leq\mathrm{OR}^{N}, we say η\eta is a cutpoint of NN iff for all E𝔼+NE\in\mathbb{E}_{+}^{N}, if crit(E)<η{\rm crit}(E)<\eta then lh(E)η{\rm lh}(E)\leq\eta, and a strong cutpoint iff for all E𝔼+NE\in\mathbb{E}_{+}^{N}, if crit(E)η{\rm crit}(E)\leq\eta then lh(E)η{\rm lh}(E)\leq\eta. For ξ<δORN\xi<\delta\in\mathrm{OR}^{N}, 𝔹δ,ξN\mathbb{B}^{N}_{\delta,\xi} denotes the δ\delta-generator extender algebra at δ\delta, with axioms induced by extenders E𝔼E\in\mathbb{E} with ν(E)\nu(E) inaccessible in NN and ξcrit(E)\xi\leq{\rm crit}(E). And 𝔹δN=𝔹δ,0N\mathbb{B}_{\delta}^{N}=\mathbb{B}^{N}_{\delta,0}.

Hulls: In general, HulltM(X)\mathrm{Hull}^{M}_{t}(X) denotes the structure whose universe is the collection of elements of MM, definable over MM from parameters in XX, with definitions of “kind tt”, and whose predicates are just the restrictions of those of MM. Here “kind tt” depends on context, but the main example is that if MM is a premouse, then the universe of Hulln+1M(X)\mathrm{Hull}_{n+1}^{M}(X) is the collection of all yMy\in M such that for some rΣn+1\mathrm{r}\Sigma_{n+1} formula φ\varphi and xX<ω\vec{x}\in X^{<\omega}, yy is the unique zMz\in M such that Mφ(z,x)M\vDash\varphi(z,\vec{x}). When it makes sense, cHulltM(X)\mathrm{cHull}_{t}^{M}(X) denotes the transitive collapse of Hulln+1M(X)\mathrm{Hull}_{n+1}^{M}(X) (including the collapses of predicates).

Ultrapowers: Let EE be an extender over NN. Write iEN:NUlt(N,E)i_{E}^{N}:N\to\mathrm{Ult}(N,E) for the ultrapower map, and iEN,nUltn(N,E)i_{E}^{N,n}\to\mathrm{Ult}_{n}(N,E) for the degree-nn ultrapower and associated map. Write κE=crit(E)\kappa_{E}={\rm crit}(E) for the critical point of EE, λE=λ(E)=iE(κE)\lambda_{E}=\lambda(E)=i_{E}(\kappa_{E}), and δ(E)\delta(E) for the measure space of EE; in particular, if EE is short then δ(E)=crit(E)+1\delta(E)={\rm crit}(E)+1.

Iteration trees: A fine structural iteration tree 𝒯\mathcal{T} consists of tree order <𝒯<^{\mathcal{T}}, tree-predecessor function α+1pred𝒯(α+1)\alpha+1\mapsto\mathrm{pred}^{\mathcal{T}}(\alpha+1), model-dropping node-set 𝒟𝒯lh(𝒯)\mathscr{D}^{\mathcal{T}}\subseteq{\rm lh}(\mathcal{T}), model-or-degree-dropping node-set 𝒟deg𝒯lh(𝒯)\mathscr{D}^{\mathcal{T}}_{\deg}\subseteq{\rm lh}(\mathcal{T}), models Mα𝒯M^{\mathcal{T}}_{\alpha} and degrees degα𝒯\deg^{\mathcal{T}}_{\alpha} (for α<lh(𝒯)\alpha<{\rm lh}(\mathcal{T})), extenders Eα𝒯𝔼+(Mα𝒯)E^{\mathcal{T}}_{\alpha}\in\mathbb{E}_{+}(M^{\mathcal{T}}_{\alpha}) and model pre-images Mα+1𝒯Mβ𝒯M^{*\mathcal{T}}_{\alpha+1}\trianglelefteq M^{\mathcal{T}}_{\beta} where β=pred𝒯(α+1)\beta=\mathrm{pred}^{\mathcal{T}}(\alpha+1) (for α+1<lh(𝒯)\alpha+1<{\rm lh}(\mathcal{T})), and here Mα+1𝒯=Ultd(Mα+1𝒯,Eα𝒯)M^{\mathcal{T}}_{\alpha+1}=\mathrm{Ult}_{d}(M^{*\mathcal{T}}_{\alpha+1},E^{\mathcal{T}}_{\alpha}) where d=degα𝒯d=\deg^{\mathcal{T}}_{\alpha}, and if α𝒯β\alpha\leq^{\mathcal{T}}\beta and (α,β]𝒯𝒟𝒯=(\alpha,\beta]_{\mathcal{T}}\cap\mathscr{D}^{\mathcal{T}}=\emptyset, iteration maps iαβ𝒯:Mα𝒯Mβ𝒯i^{\mathcal{T}}_{\alpha\beta}:M^{\mathcal{T}}_{\alpha}\to M^{\mathcal{T}}_{\beta}, and if α\alpha is also a successor ordinal, iαβ𝒯:Mα𝒯Mβ𝒯i^{*\mathcal{T}}_{\alpha\beta}:M^{*\mathcal{T}}_{\alpha}\to M^{\mathcal{T}}_{\beta}. (Note we are only indicating notation above; the definition of iteration tree has more demands.)

Let NN be an nn-sound premouse, where nωn\leq\omega, and 𝒯\mathcal{T} a fine structural iteration tree. Recall that 𝒯\mathcal{T} is nn-maximal on NN iff (i) (M0𝒯,deg0𝒯)=(N,n)(M^{\mathcal{T}}_{0},\deg^{\mathcal{T}}_{0})=(N,n), (ii) lh(Eα𝒯)<lh(Eβ𝒯){\rm lh}(E^{\mathcal{T}}_{\alpha})<{\rm lh}(E^{\mathcal{T}}_{\beta}) for α+1<β+1<lh(𝒯)\alpha+1<\beta+1<{\rm lh}(\mathcal{T}), (iii) pred𝒯(α+1)\mathrm{pred}^{\mathcal{T}}(\alpha+1) is the least β\beta such that crit(Eα𝒯)<λ(Eβ𝒯){\rm crit}(E^{\mathcal{T}}_{\alpha})<\lambda(E^{\mathcal{T}}_{\beta}), and (iv) (Mα+1𝒯,degα+1𝒯)(M^{*\mathcal{T}}_{\alpha+1},\deg^{\mathcal{T}}_{\alpha+1}) is the lex-largest (P,p)(P,p) such that (Mβ𝒯||lh(Eβ𝒯),0)(P,p)(Mβ𝒯,degβ𝒯)(M^{\mathcal{T}}_{\beta}||{\rm lh}(E^{\mathcal{T}}_{\beta}),0)\trianglelefteq(P,p)\trianglelefteq(M^{\mathcal{T}}_{\beta},\deg^{\mathcal{T}}_{\beta}) and crit(Eα𝒯)<ρpP{\rm crit}(E^{\mathcal{T}}_{\alpha})<\rho_{p}^{P}. We say 𝒯\mathcal{T} is normal if it is nn-maximal for some nn. For δ\delta an NN-cardinal, we say 𝒯\mathcal{T} is based on N|δN|\delta iff for all α+1<lh(𝒯)\alpha+1<{\rm lh}(\mathcal{T}), if [0,α]𝒯[0,\alpha]_{\mathcal{T}} does not drop in model then lh(Eα𝒯)i0α𝒯(δ){\rm lh}(E^{\mathcal{T}}_{\alpha})\leq i^{\mathcal{T}}_{0\alpha}(\delta). We say 𝒯\mathcal{T} is above κ\kappa iff crit(Eα𝒯)κ{\rm crit}(E^{\mathcal{T}}_{\alpha})\geq\kappa for all α+1<lh(𝒯)\alpha+1<{\rm lh}(\mathcal{T}), and strictly above κ\kappa iff crit(Eα𝒯)>κ{\rm crit}(E^{\mathcal{T}}_{\alpha})>\kappa for all α+1<lh(𝒯)\alpha+1<{\rm lh}(\mathcal{T}).

P-construction: Given a premouse MM and NMN\in M, 𝒫M(N)\mathscr{P}^{M}(N), or just 𝒫(N)\mathscr{P}(N) if MM is understood, denotes the P-construction as computed in MM over base set NN. In [12, §1], this model would be denoted 𝒫(M,N,){\cal P}(M,N,-). If 𝒯\mathcal{T} is a limit length iteration tree, 𝒫N(𝒯)\mathscr{P}^{N}(\mathcal{T}) abbreviates 𝒫N(M(𝒯))\mathscr{P}^{N}(M(\mathcal{T})), and if 𝒯\mathcal{T} is the trivial tree (that is, uses no extenders) then 𝒫N(𝒯)\mathscr{P}^{N}(\mathcal{T}) denotes NN. (The latter notation is just convenient when we set up indices for the direct limit systems, as then the trivial tree 𝒯\mathcal{T} on MM indexes the base of the system computed in MM.)

Remark 1.0.

For our overall purposes Jensen indexing for premice is natural. However, genericity iterations are essential, which are somewhat cumbersome with Jensen indexing and Jensen iteration rules (as for nn-maximality above). The process for this is described in [20, Theorem 5.8]. We f also use genericity inflation, sketched in §4.2, and minimal genericity inflation, see [15, §5.2***].)

2 Ground generation

In this section we shall present an abstract version of the construction of a Varsovian model 𝒱\mathscr{V} derived from a given inner model MM (satisfying the requirements below), and prove that 𝒱\mathscr{V} is a ground of MM. It will take some time to lay out the required hypotheses ((ug1)(ug24)); we will also collect some facts along the way.

Fix M,(d,),(𝒫p:pd)M,(d,\preceq),(\mathcal{P}_{p}\colon p\in d) such that

  1. (ug1)

    MM is a proper class transitive model of ZFC,

  2. (ug2)

    (d,)M(d,\preceq)\in M is a directed partial order,

  3. (ug3)

    (𝒫p:pd)({\cal P}_{p}\colon p\in d) is an indexed system of transitive proper class inner models of MM which is an MM-class; that is, each 𝒫p{\cal P}_{p} is a transitive proper class inner model of MM, and {(p,x):pdx𝒫p}\{(p,x)\colon p\in d\wedge x\in{\cal P}_{p}\} is an MM-class. 555In practice, MM and all 𝒫p{\cal P}_{p}, pdp\in d, will be (pure or strategic) premice, hence inner models constructed from a distinguished (class sized) predicate, in which case our definability hypothesis is supposed to mean that the collection of predicates constructing the 𝒫p{\cal P}_{p}, pdp\in d, is definable over MM.

Suppose that in VV there is a system (πpq:p,qdpq)(\pi_{pq}\colon p,q\in d\wedge p\preceq q) such that:

  1. (ug4)

    πpq:𝒫p𝒫q\pi_{pq}\colon{\cal P}_{p}\rightarrow{\cal P}_{q} is elementary whenever pqp\preceq q,

  2. (ug5)

    the maps are commuting; that is, πqrπpq=πpr\pi_{qr}\circ\pi_{pq}=\pi_{pr} for pqrp\preceq q\preceq r.

Let

𝒟ext=(𝒫p:pd,πpq:p,qdpq)\mathscr{D}^{\mathrm{ext}}=\big{(}\left<\mathcal{P}_{p}\colon p\in d\right>,\left<\pi_{pq}\colon p,q\in d\wedge p\preceq q\right>\big{)}

be the directed system (the ext stands for external). Define the direct limit (model and maps)

(ext,πp:pd)= dir lim 𝒟.\displaystyle({\cal M}_{\infty}^{\mathrm{ext}},\pi_{p\infty}\colon p\in d)=\mbox{ dir lim }\mathscr{D}. (1)

Suppose

  1. (ug6)

    ext\mathcal{M}_{\infty}^{\mathrm{ext}} is wellfounded; we take it transitive.

Note that the system 𝒟ext\mathscr{D}^{\mathrm{ext}} is not assumed to be an MM-class, hence neither ext\mathcal{M}_{\infty}^{\mathrm{ext}}. But suppose that 𝒟ext\mathscr{D}^{\mathrm{ext}} is “covered” by an MM-class, in the sense that there is an MM-class (d+,)(d^{+},\preceq) (we use the same symbol \preceq, since there will be no possibility of confusion) such that:

  1. (ug7)

    d+d×([OR]<ω\)d^{+}\subseteq d\times([{\rm OR}]^{<\omega}\backslash\emptyset) and \preceq is a directed partial order on d+d^{+},

  2. (ug8)

    if (p,s),(q,t)d+(p,s),(q,t)\in d^{+} then (p,s)(q,t)(p,s)\preceq(q,t) iff pqp\preceq q and sts\subseteq t

  3. (ug9)

    if (p,t)d+(p,t)\in d^{+} and st\emptyset\neq s\subseteq t then (p,s)d+(p,s)\in d^{+},

  4. (ug10)

    if (p,s)d+(p,s)\in d^{+}, qdq\in d and pqp\preceq q, then (q,s)d+(q,s)\in d^{+}.

Further, there is a system

𝒟=(Hsp:(p,s)d+,πps,qt:(p,s),(q,t)d+(p,s)(q,t))\displaystyle\mathscr{D}=\big{(}\left<H^{p}_{s}\colon(p,s)\in d^{+}\right>,\left<\pi_{ps,qt}\colon(p,s),(q,t)\in d^{+}\wedge(p,s)\preceq(q,t)\right>\big{)} (2)

such that:

  1. (ug11)

    𝒟\mathscr{D} is an MM-class,

  2. (ug12)

    for all (p,s)d+(p,s)\in d^{+}, HspH^{p}_{s} is an elementary substructure of 𝒬sp=𝒫p|max(s){\cal Q}^{p}_{s}={\cal P}_{p}|\max(s),666Here if 𝒫p{\cal P}_{p} is a (possibly strategy) premouse, then this is precisely defined, and is passive (strategy) premouse; in general 𝒫p{\cal P}_{p} should be stratified in an OR\mathrm{OR}-indexed increasing chain of Σ0\Sigma_{0}-elementary substructures and 𝒬sp{\cal Q}^{p}_{s} should be the proper level of that hierarchy indexed at max(s)\max(s).

  3. (ug13)

    for all (p,s),(q,s)d+(p,s),(q,s)\in d^{+} with pqp\preceq q, the map πps,qs:HspHsq\pi_{ps,qs}:H^{p}_{s}\to H^{q}_{s} is elementary,

  4. (ug14)

    for all (p,t)d+(p,t)\in d^{+} and sts\subseteq t, we have Hsp0HtpH^{p}_{s}\preceq_{0}H^{p}_{t}, and the map

    πps,pt:HspHtp\pi_{ps,pt}:H^{p}_{s}\to H^{p}_{t}

    is the inclusion map (hence Σ0\Sigma_{0}-elementary),

  5. (ug15)

    the maps πps,qt\pi_{ps,qt} commute, in that πqt,ruπps,qt=πps,ru\pi_{qt,ru}\circ\pi_{ps,qt}=\pi_{ps,ru},

Note if (p,s),(q,t)d+(p,s),(q,t)\in d^{+} and (p,s)(q,t)(p,s)\preceq(q,t), then (p,s)(q,s)(q,t)(p,s)\preceq(q,s)\preceq(q,t), so by (ug13), (ug14), (ug15),

πps,qt=πqs,qtπps,qs:HspHtq\pi_{ps,qt}=\pi_{qs,qt}\circ\pi_{ps,qs}:H^{p}_{s}\to H^{q}_{t}

is Σ0\Sigma_{0}-elementary and has the same graph as has πps,qs\pi_{ps,qs}, and in particular, the graph is independent of tt. And note that πps,qsπpt,qt\pi_{ps,qs}\subseteq\pi_{pt,qt} whenever sts\subseteq t and (p,t)d+(p,t)\in d^{+} and pqdp\preceq q\in d, because here (p,s)d+(p,s)\in d^{+} and

πpt,qtπps,pt=πps,qt=πqs,qtπps,qs,\pi_{pt,qt}\circ\pi_{ps,pt}=\pi_{ps,qt}=\pi_{qs,qt}\circ\pi_{ps,qs},

but πps,pt\pi_{ps,pt} and πqs,qt\pi_{qs,qt} are just inclusion maps.

Definition 2.1.

Given αOR\alpha\in\mathrm{OR} and pdp\in d, say α\alpha is pp-stable iff πpq(α)=α\pi_{pq}(\alpha)=\alpha for all qdq\in d with pqp\preceq q. Say s[OR]<ωs\in[\mathrm{OR}]^{<\omega} is pp-stable iff α\alpha is pp-stable for each αs\alpha\in s. Call (p,s)d+(p,s)\in d^{+} true iff ss is pp-stable and for all q,rdq,r\in d with pqrp\preceq q\preceq r, we have πqs,rs=πqrHsq\pi_{qs,rs}=\pi_{qr}\upharpoonright H^{q}_{s}.

Lemma 2.1.

For each s[OR]<ω\{}s\in[\mathrm{OR}]^{<\omega}\backslash\{\emptyset\}, there is pdp\in d such that ss is pp-stable.

The proof is standard, using the wellfoundedness of ext\mathcal{M}_{\infty}^{\mathrm{ext}}. Assume further:

  1. (ug16)

    for all s[OR]<ω\{}s\in[\mathrm{OR}]^{<\omega}\backslash\{\emptyset\}, there is pdp\in d with (p,s)d+(p,s)\in d^{+} and (p,s)(p,s) true.

  2. (ug17)

    for all pdp\in d and x𝒫px\in{\cal P}_{p}, there exists ss such that (p,s)d+(p,s)\in d^{+}, (p,s)(p,s) is true and xHspx\in H^{p}_{s}.

Define the direct limit (,πps,:(p,s)d+)= dir lim 𝒟({\cal M}_{\infty},\pi_{ps,\infty}\colon(p,s)\in d^{+})=\mbox{ dir lim }\mathscr{D}.

Lemma 2.1.

=ext\mathcal{M}_{\infty}=\mathcal{M}_{\infty}^{\mathrm{ext}} is MM-definable.

Proof.

Our assumptions immediately give that \mathcal{M}_{\infty} is MM-definable. Consider the equality. We proceed as in the proof of [8, Lemma 2.4] or the first few claims in [19]; the last few properties listed above been abstracted from those proofs. We will define a map χ:ext\chi\colon{\cal M}_{\infty}\rightarrow{\cal M}_{\infty}^{\mathrm{ext}} and show that χ\chi is the identity.

Let (p,s)d+(p,s)\in d^{+} and xHspx\in H^{p}_{s}. By (ug10) and (ug16), we may fix qq such that (p,s)(q,s)(p,s)\preceq(q,s) and (q,s)(q,s) is true. Define

χ(πps,(x))=πq,πps,qs(x).\chi(\pi_{ps,\infty}(x))=\pi_{q,\infty}\circ\pi_{ps,qs}(x).

By commutativity and truth (trueness), this does not depend on the choice of qq, so χ\chi is well-defined. Note that χ\chi is Σ0\Sigma_{0}-elementary and cofinal, hence fully elementary, by [4, Theorem II.1, p. 54; Remark II.2, p. 55]. If pdp\in d and x𝒫px\in{\cal P}_{p}, then by (ug17) there is ss with (p,s)(p,s) true and xHspx\in H^{p}_{s}. Hence πp,(x)=χ(πps,(x))ran(χ)\pi_{p,\infty}(x)=\chi(\pi_{ps,\infty}(x))\in{\rm ran}(\chi). So χ\chi is surjective, so χ=id\chi=\mathrm{id}. ∎

Given pdp\in d, write 𝒞p={qd:pq}{\cal C}_{p}=\{q\in d\colon p\preceq q\}, and given (p,s)d+(p,s)\in d^{+}, write 𝒞(p,s)={(q,t)d+:(p,s)(q,t)}{\cal C}_{(p,s)}=\{(q,t)\in d^{+}\colon(p,s)\preceq(q,t)\}. Call a set 𝒞d\mathcal{C}\subseteq d a cone iff 𝒞p𝒞\mathcal{C}_{p}\subseteq\mathcal{C} for some pdp\in d, and 𝒞d+\mathcal{C}^{\prime}\subseteq d^{+} a cone iff 𝒞(p,s)𝒞\mathcal{C}_{(p,s)}\subseteq\mathcal{C}^{\prime} for some (p,s)d+(p,s)\in d^{+}.

Lemma 2.1.

We have:

  1. 1.

    There is a cone 𝒞d\mathcal{C}\subseteq d such that πpq(ρ)=ρ\pi_{pq}(\rho)=\rho for all p,q𝒞p,q\in\mathcal{C} with pqp\preceq q.

  2. 2.

    There is a cone 𝒞d+\mathcal{C}^{\prime}\subseteq d^{+} such that ρHsp and πps,qt(ρ)=ρ\rho\in H^{p}_{s}\text{ and }\pi_{ps,qt}(\rho)=\rho for all (p,s),(q,t)𝒞(p,s),(q,t)\in\mathcal{C}^{\prime} with (p,s)(q,t)(p,s)\preceq(q,t), and

Proof.

Let s={ρ,ρ+1}s=\{\rho,\rho+1\} and (using (ug16)) let pdp\in d be such that (p,s)d+(p,s)\in d^{+} and (p,s)(p,s) is true (hence ss is pp-stable). Then 𝒞p\mathcal{C}_{p} and 𝒞(p,s)\mathcal{C}_{(p,s)} work. ∎

Note that part 2 of the previous lemma is understood by MM. Using this, we can define the associated *-map OROR\mathrm{OR}\to\mathrm{OR}. For αOR\alpha\in\mathrm{OR} write

ρ=πps,(ρ),\displaystyle\rho^{*}=\pi_{ps,\infty}(\rho), (3)

where (p,s)(p,s) is any element of any cone 𝒞\mathcal{C}^{\prime} witnessing part 2 of the lemma. Note this is well-defined, and * is a class of MM.

Lemma 2.1.

Let ρOR\rho\in\mathrm{OR}, and 𝒞,𝒞\mathcal{C},\mathcal{C}^{\prime} be cones witnessing Lemma 2. Then:

  1. 1.

    ρ=πp(ρ)\rho^{*}=\pi_{p\infty}(\rho) for all p𝒞p\in{\cal C},

  2. 2.

    ρHsp\rho\in H^{p}_{s} and ρ=πps,(ρ)\rho^{*}=\pi_{ps,\infty}(\rho) for all (p,s)𝒞(p,s)\in{\cal C}^{\prime},

  3. 3.

    ρ=min{πp(ρ):pd}\rho^{*}=\mbox{min}\{\pi_{p\infty}(\rho)\colon p\in d\}.

Proof.

Parts 1 and 2 follow directly from Lemma 2 and the fact that the function χ\chi defined in the proof of Lemma 2 is the identity.

Part 3: Let 𝒞d{\cal C}\subseteq d witness Lemma 2. Let pdp\in d. Then there is q𝒞q\in{\cal C} with pqp\preceq q. Therefore πpq(ρ)ρ\pi_{pq}(\rho)\geq\rho, so πp(ρ)πq(ρ)\pi_{p\infty}(\rho)\geq\pi_{q\infty}(\rho), which suffices. ∎

There is another important characterization of ρρ\rho\mapsto\rho^{*}, given some further properties. Assume:

  1. (ug18)

    There is a unique \preceq-minimal p0dp_{0}\in d. Moreover, M=𝒫p0M={\cal P}_{p_{0}} and πp0q(p0)=q\pi_{p_{0}q}(p_{0})=q for each qdq\in d.

So πp0q:M𝒫q\pi_{p_{0}q}:M\to{\cal P}_{q} for all qdq\in d, and πp0:M\pi_{p_{0}\infty}:M\to\mathcal{M}_{\infty}. The next hypotheses guarantee a homogeneity property of the system, in that each 𝒫p{\cal P}_{p} may equally serve as a base. Let 𝒟𝒫p=πp0p(𝒟)\mathscr{D}^{\mathcal{P}_{p}}=\pi_{p_{0}p}(\mathscr{D}), 𝒫p=πp0p()\mathcal{M}_{\infty}^{\mathcal{P}_{p}}=\pi_{p_{0}p}(\mathcal{M}_{\infty}), etc, for pdp\in d.777Note that we write πp0p(𝒟)\pi_{p_{0}p}(\mathscr{D}), not πp0p(𝒟ext)\pi_{p_{0}p}(\mathscr{D}^{\mathrm{ext}}); of the course the latter does not make sense. We know ext=\mathcal{M}_{\infty}^{\mathrm{ext}}=\mathcal{M}_{\infty}, but \mathcal{M}_{\infty}^{\mathcal{M}_{\infty}} is of course computed in \mathcal{M}_{\infty} as the direct limit of 𝒟\mathscr{D}^{\mathcal{M}_{\infty}}. At this stage it is not relevant whether there is some external system of elementary embeddings associated with 𝒟\mathscr{D}^{\mathcal{M}_{\infty}} analogous to 𝒟ext\mathscr{D}^{\mathrm{ext}}. Let cp=dpdc_{p}=d_{p}\cap d and cp+=dp+d+c^{+}_{p}=d^{+}_{p}\cap d^{+}. Suppose:

  1. (ug19)

    For all pdp\in d, cpc_{p} is dense in (dp,p)(d_{p},\preceq_{p}) and dense in (d,)(d,\preceq), and pcp=cp{\preceq_{p}}{\upharpoonright}c_{p}={\preceq}{\upharpoonright}c_{p},

  2. (ug20)

    For all pdp\in d and all (q,s),(r,t)cp+(q,s),(r,t)\in c_{p}^{+} with (q,s)(r,t)(q,s)\preceq(r,t), we have (𝒫q)𝒫p=𝒫q(\mathcal{P}_{q})^{\mathcal{P}_{p}}=\mathcal{P}_{q} and (Hsq)𝒫p=Hsq(H^{q}_{s})^{\mathcal{P}_{p}}=H^{q}_{s} and (πqs,rt)𝒫p=πqs,rt(\pi_{qs,rt})^{\mathcal{P}_{p}}=\pi_{qs,rt}.

  3. (ug21)

    For all s[OR]<ω\{}s\in[\mathrm{OR}]^{<\omega}\backslash\{\emptyset\} there is pdp\in d with (p,s)(p,s) true and (p,s)cp+(p,s)\in c^{+}_{p}.

Using these properties, it is now straightforward to deduce:

Lemma 2.1.

For each pdp\in d, we have:

  1. 1.

    cp+c_{p}^{+} is dense in (dp+,p)(d_{p}^{+},\preceq_{p}) and dense in (d+,)(d^{+},\preceq), and pcp+=pcp+{\preceq_{p}}{\upharpoonright}c_{p}^{+}={\preceq_{p}}{\upharpoonright}c_{p}^{+}.

  2. 2.

    The direct limit 𝒫p\mathcal{M}_{\infty}^{\mathcal{P}_{p}} of 𝒟𝒫p\mathscr{D}^{\mathcal{P}_{p}} is just \mathcal{M}_{\infty} , and the associated *-map 𝒫p*^{\mathcal{P}_{p}} is just *, so πp0p()=\pi_{p_{0}p}(\mathcal{M}_{\infty})=\mathcal{M}_{\infty} and πp0p()=\pi_{p_{0}p}(*)=*.

Definition 2.2.

For pdp\in d and s,t[OR]<ω\s,t\in[\mathrm{OR}]^{<\omega}\backslash\emptyset, say (p,s,t)(p,s,t) is embedding-good iff (p,t)d+(p,t)\in d^{+}, πps,Htp\pi_{ps,\infty}\in H^{p}_{t} and πpt,qt(πps,)=πqs,\pi_{pt,qt}(\pi_{ps,\infty})=\pi_{qs,\infty} for all q𝒞pq\in\mathcal{C}_{p}.

Note that embedding-good is an MM-class.

Lemma 2.2.
  1. 1.

    If (p,s)(p,s) is as in (ug21) then (q,s)(q,s) is true and (q,s)d+dq+(q,s)\in d^{+}\cap d^{+}_{q} for all q𝒞pq\in\mathcal{C}_{p}.

  2. 2.

    For each s[OR]<ω\s\in[\mathrm{OR}]^{<\omega}\backslash\emptyset there is pdp\in d such that for each q𝒞pq\in\mathcal{C}_{p}, we have (q,s)(q,s) true and (q,s)d+dq+(q,s)\in d^{+}\cap d^{+}_{q}, and for each x𝒫qx\in\mathcal{P}_{q} there is t[OR]<ωt\in[\mathrm{OR}]^{<\omega} such that (q,t)(q,t) is true and xHtqx\in H^{q}_{t} and (q,s,t)(q,s,t) is embedding-good.

Proof.

Part 1: We have (q,s)d+(q,s)\in d^{+} and (q,s)(q,s) true because (p,s)d+(p,s)\in d^{+} and (p,s)(p,s) is true, and (q,s)dq+(q,s)\in d_{q}^{+} because (p,s)dp+(p,s)\in d_{p}^{+} and πpq((p,s))=(q,s)\pi_{pq}((p,s))=(q,s) by (ug18) and because ss is pp-stable.

Part 2: Fix pdp\in d with (p,s)(p,s) true and (p,s)d+dp+(p,s)\in d^{+}\cap d^{+}_{p} (using (ug21)). Let q𝒞pq\in\mathcal{C}_{p}. By part 1 and (ug18)(ug20), (πrs,)𝒫r=πrs,(\pi_{rs,\infty})^{\mathcal{P}_{r}}=\pi_{rs,\infty} for all r𝒞qr\in\mathcal{C}_{q}. Since πqr(s)=s\pi_{qr}(s)=s for such rr, we get πqr(πqs,)=πrs,\pi_{qr}(\pi_{qs,\infty})=\pi_{rs,\infty}. Let x𝒫qx\in\mathcal{P}_{q}. Using (ug17), let t[OR]<ωt\in[\mathrm{OR}]^{<\omega} such that (q,t)d+(q,t)\in d^{+} is true and x,πqs,Htqx,\pi_{qs,\infty}\in H^{q}_{t}. Then q,tq,t works. ∎

Let 𝒢\mathscr{G} be the class of all embedding-good tuples. Define 𝒟=π0(𝒟)\mathscr{D}^{\mathcal{M}_{\infty}}=\pi_{0\infty}(\mathscr{D}) and =π0(){\cal M}_{\infty}^{\mathcal{M}_{\infty}}=\pi_{0\infty}(\mathcal{M}_{\infty}). Working in MM, define π:\pi_{\infty}:\mathcal{M}_{\infty}\to\mathcal{M}_{\infty}^{\mathcal{M}_{\infty}} by

π=(p,s,t)𝒢πpt,(πps,).\pi_{\infty}=\bigcup_{(p,s,t)\in\mathscr{G}}\pi_{pt,\infty}(\pi_{ps,\infty}).
Lemma 2.2.

π:\pi_{\infty}:\mathcal{M}_{\infty}\to\mathcal{M}_{\infty}^{\mathcal{M}_{\infty}} is elementary and π(ρ)=ρ\pi_{\infty}(\rho)=\rho^{*} for ρOR\rho\in\mathrm{OR}. Moreover, πp0q(π)=π\pi_{p_{0}q}(\pi_{\infty})=\pi_{\infty} for all qdq\in d.

Proof.

The well-definedness and elementarity of π\pi_{\infty} is left to the reader. Fix ρOR\rho\in\mathrm{OR}. Let (p,s)d+(p,s)\in d^{+} with ρrg(πps,)\rho\in\mathrm{rg}(\pi_{ps,\infty}), taking pp as in Lemma 2 part 2 with respect to ss. Note we may assume that πpq(ρ)=ρ\pi_{pq}(\rho)=\rho for all q𝒞pq\in\mathcal{C}_{p}. Let πps,(ρ¯)=ρ\pi_{ps,\infty}(\bar{\rho})=\rho. Let t[OR]<ω\{}t\in[\mathrm{OR}]^{<\omega}\backslash\{\emptyset\} be such that (p,t)(p,t) is true, ρ¯,ρ,πps,Htp\bar{\rho},\rho,\pi_{ps,\infty}\in H^{p}_{t} and (p,s,t)(p,s,t) is embedding-good. Then

ρ\displaystyle\rho^{*} =\displaystyle= πp(ρ)\displaystyle\pi_{p\infty}(\rho)
=\displaystyle= πpt,(πps,(ρ¯))\displaystyle\pi_{pt,\infty}(\pi_{ps,\infty}({\bar{\rho}}))
=\displaystyle= πpt,(πps,)(πpt,(ρ¯))\displaystyle\pi_{pt,\infty}(\pi_{ps,\infty})(\pi_{pt,\infty}({\bar{\rho}}))
=\displaystyle= π(ρ).\displaystyle\pi_{\infty}(\rho).

The “moreover” clause is as in Lemma 2. ∎

We now define the associated Varsovian model 𝒱\mathscr{V} as

𝒱=L[,π].\displaystyle\mathscr{V}=L[{\cal M}_{\infty},\pi_{\infty}]. (4)

So by Lemmas 2 and 2, 𝒱\mathscr{V} is a class of 𝒫p{\cal P}_{p}, for all pdp\in d, and πp0p(𝒱)=𝒱\pi_{p_{0}p}(\mathscr{V})=\mathscr{V}. Let 𝒱=πp0(𝒱)\mathscr{V}^{\mathcal{M}_{\infty}}=\pi_{p_{0}\infty}(\mathscr{V}), so 𝒱\mathscr{V}^{\mathcal{M}_{\infty}} is defined over \mathcal{M}_{\infty} just as 𝒱\mathscr{V} over MM. So letting π=πp0(π)\pi_{\infty}^{\mathcal{M}_{\infty}}=\pi_{p_{0}\infty}(\pi_{\infty}),

𝒱=L[,π].\mathscr{V}^{\mathcal{M}_{\infty}}=L[\mathcal{M}_{\infty}^{\mathcal{M}_{\infty}},\pi_{\infty}^{\mathcal{M}_{\infty}}].
Lemma 2.2.

π\pi_{\infty} extends uniquely to an elementary

π+:𝒱𝒱\pi_{\infty}^{+}:\mathscr{V}\to\mathscr{V}^{\mathcal{M}_{\infty}}

such that π+(π)=π\pi_{\infty}^{+}(\pi_{\infty})=\pi_{\infty}^{\mathcal{M}_{\infty}} (and π+()=π()=\pi_{\infty}^{+}(\mathcal{M}_{\infty})=\pi_{\infty}(\mathcal{M}_{\infty})=\mathcal{M}_{\infty}^{\mathcal{M}_{\infty}}). Moreover, π+\pi^{+}_{\infty} is 𝒱\mathscr{V}-definable from ,π\mathcal{M}_{\infty},\pi_{\infty}.

Proof.

Since every element of 𝒱\mathscr{V} is definable over 𝒱\mathscr{V} from \mathcal{M}_{\infty}, π\pi_{\infty} and some ordinal, it suffices to see that for all formulas φ\varphi and ordinals α\alpha, we have

𝒱φ(,π,α)𝒱φ(,π,π(α)).\mathscr{V}\vDash\varphi(\mathcal{M}_{\infty},\pi_{\infty},\alpha)\ \Longleftrightarrow\ \mathscr{V}^{\mathcal{M}_{\infty}}\vDash\varphi(\mathcal{M}_{\infty}^{\mathcal{M}_{\infty}},\pi_{\infty}^{\mathcal{M}_{\infty}},\pi_{\infty}(\alpha)).

But 𝒱φ(,π,α)\mathscr{V}\vDash\varphi(\mathcal{M}_{\infty},\pi_{\infty},\alpha) iff

𝒫p𝒱φ(,π,α)\mathcal{P}_{p}\vDash\text{``}\mathscr{V}\vDash\varphi(\mathcal{M}_{\infty},\pi_{\infty},\alpha)\text{''}

for each pdp\in d. Taking pp such that α\alpha is pp-stable, and then applying πp\pi_{p\infty}, note that the latter holds iff \mathcal{M}_{\infty} satisfies the corresponding formula regarding π(α)\pi_{\infty}(\alpha); that is, iff

𝒱φ(,π,π(α)).\mathscr{V}^{\mathcal{M}_{\infty}}\vDash\varphi(\mathcal{M}_{\infty}^{\mathcal{M}_{\infty}},\pi_{\infty}^{\mathcal{M}_{\infty}},\pi_{\infty}(\alpha)).\qed

It therefore makes sense to define, for any xx\in{\cal M}_{\infty},

x=π(x),\displaystyle x^{*}=\pi_{\infty}(x), (5)

and for x𝒱x\in\mathscr{V},

x+=π+(x);\displaystyle x^{*+}=\pi_{\infty}^{+}(x); (6)

that is, * and π\pi_{\infty} denote the same function, as do +*+ and π+\pi_{\infty}^{+}.

We next formulate a few more assumptions which ensure that certain sets are generic over 𝒱\mathscr{V}. Let δOR\delta\in\mathrm{OR} and 𝔹M\mathbb{B}\in M. Let δp=πp0p(δ)\delta_{p}=\pi_{p_{0}p}(\delta) and δ=πp0(δ)\delta_{\infty}=\pi_{p_{0}\infty}(\delta), etc. Assume:

  1. (ug22)

    MM\vDashδ\delta is regular and 𝔹\mathbb{B} is a δ\delta-cc complete Boolean algebra”, and

  2. (ug23)

    𝒱\mathscr{V}\vDashδ\delta_{\infty} is regular and 𝔹\mathbb{B}_{\infty} is δ\delta_{\infty}-cc”.

Now work in 𝒱\mathscr{V}. Let \mathcal{L} be the infinitary propositional language, with propositional symbols PξP_{\xi} for each ordinal ξ\xi, generated by closing under under negation and under conjunctions and disjunctions of length <δ{<\delta_{\infty}} (so if φαα<θμ\left<\varphi_{\alpha}\right>_{\alpha<\theta}\subseteq\mathcal{L}_{\mu} where θ<δ\theta<\delta_{\infty}, then α<θφα\bigwedge_{\alpha<\theta}\varphi_{\alpha} and α<θφα\bigvee_{\alpha<\theta}\varphi_{\alpha} are also in μ\mathcal{L}_{\mu}). (Note \mathcal{L} is a proper class of 𝒱\mathscr{V}.)

Working in any outer universe of 𝒱\mathscr{V}, given a set BB of ordinals, the satisfaction relation BφB\vDash\varphi for φμ\varphi\in\mathcal{L}_{\mu} is defined recursively as usual; that is, BPξB\vDash P_{\xi} iff ξB\xi\in B; B¬φB\vDash\lnot\varphi iff B⊭φB\not\vDash\varphi; Bα<θφαB\vDash\bigwedge_{\alpha<\theta}\varphi_{\alpha} iff BφαB\vDash\varphi_{\alpha} for all α<θ\alpha<\theta; and Bα<θφαB\vDash\bigvee_{\alpha<\theta}\varphi_{\alpha} iff BφαB\vDash\varphi_{\alpha} for some α<θ\alpha<\theta.

Fix some 𝔹p\mathbb{B}_{p}-name τp𝒫p\tau_{p}\in\mathcal{P}_{p} for a set of ordinals, for some pdp\in d, and let τj=πpq(τp)\tau_{j}=\pi_{pq}(\tau_{p}) for q𝒞pq\in\mathcal{C}_{p}, and τ=πp(τp)\tau_{\infty}=\pi_{p\infty}(\tau_{p}).

Definition 2.3.

Work in 𝒱\mathscr{V}. Let 𝕃\mathbb{L} be the poset whose conditions are formulas φ\varphi\in\mathcal{L} such that there is p𝔹p\in\mathbb{B}_{\infty} such that

p𝔹τφ+,p\Vdash^{\mathcal{M}_{\infty}}_{\mathbb{B}_{\infty}}\text{``}\tau_{\infty}\vDash\varphi^{*+}\text{''},

and with ordering φψ\varphi\leq\psi iff for every p𝔹p\in\mathbb{B}_{\infty}, we have

p𝔹τ(φ+ψ+)”.p\Vdash^{\mathcal{M}_{\infty}}_{\mathbb{B}_{\infty}}\text{``}\tau_{\infty}\vDash(\varphi^{*+}\Rightarrow\psi^{*+})\text{''.}

Although \mathcal{L} is proper class, it is easy to see that this is equivalent to a set forcing. Note here that since φ𝒱\varphi\in\mathscr{V}, φ+\varphi^{*+} is well-defined and

φ+𝒱,\varphi^{*+}\in\mathscr{V}^{\mathcal{M}_{\infty}}\subseteq\mathcal{M}_{\infty},

and the forcing assertions above make sense, as τ\tau_{\infty}\in\mathcal{M}_{\infty} is a 𝔹\mathbb{B}_{\infty}-name and φ+,ψ+\varphi^{*+},\psi^{*+}\in\mathcal{M}_{\infty}. Note that by modding out by the equivalence relation

φψφψφ,\varphi\approx\psi\Longleftrightarrow\varphi\leq\psi\leq\varphi,

we get a forcing-equivalent poset defined as follows:

Definition 2.4.

Work in 𝒱\mathscr{V}. Let 𝕃𝔹\mathbb{L}\subseteq\mathbb{B}_{\infty} be the forcing whose conditions are those Boolean values in 𝔹\mathbb{B}_{\infty} of the form

||τφ+||𝔹,||\text{``}\tau_{\infty}\vDash\varphi^{*+}\text{''}||_{\mathbb{B}_{\infty}}^{\mathcal{M}_{\infty}},

where φ\varphi\in\mathcal{L}, excluding the 0-condition of 𝔹\mathbb{B}_{\infty}, and with ordering induced by 𝔹\mathbb{B}_{\infty}.

Note that the forcing 𝕃\mathbb{L} depends on the name τ\tau_{\infty}; if we want to make this explicit, we will write 𝕃(τ)\mathbb{L}(\tau_{\infty}).

Lemma 2.4.

𝒱\mathscr{V}\vDash𝕃\mathbb{L} has the δ\delta_{\infty}-c.c.”

Proof.

Since 𝒱\mathscr{V}\vDash𝔹\mathbb{B}_{\infty} has the δ\delta_{\infty}-cc” (by (ug23)), this is an immediate consequence of Definition 2.4.∎

Lemma 2.4.

Let AMA\in M be a set of ordinals and p1dp_{1}\in d and suppose that for all q𝒞p1q\in\mathcal{C}_{p_{1}} there is gMg\in M such that gg is (𝒫q,𝔹q)({\cal P}_{q},{\mathbb{B}}_{q})-generic and (τq)g=A(\tau_{q})_{g}=A.888In our applications, where MM will be a (pure or strategic) premouse, AA will typically be a canonical code for M|μM|\mu, and the name τq\tau_{q} will provide a canonical translation of the pair (𝒫q|μ,g˙)({\cal P}_{q}|\mu,{\dot{g}}) into M|μM|\mu, where g˙\dot{g} is the generic filter. Then the filter

GA={φ𝕃|Aφ};G_{A}=\{\varphi\in\mathbb{L}\bigm{|}A\vDash\varphi\};

or equivalently, if using Definition 2.4 to define 𝕃\mathbb{L}, the filter

GA={||τφ+||𝔹|φAφ},G_{A}=\Big{\{}||\text{``}\tau_{\infty}\vDash\varphi^{*+}\text{''}||^{\mathcal{M}_{\infty}}_{\mathbb{B}_{\infty}}\Bigm{|}\varphi\in\mathcal{L}\wedge A\vDash\varphi\Big{\}},

is (𝒱,𝕃)(\mathscr{V},\mathbb{L})-generic, and A𝒱[GA]A\in\mathscr{V}[G_{A}] (so note 𝒱[A]=𝒱[GA]\mathscr{V}[A]=\mathscr{V}[G_{A}]).

Proof.

Easily, GAG_{A} is a filter. We verify genericity, and then clearly A𝒱[GA]A\in\mathscr{V}[G_{A}]. Let φαα<θ𝒱\left<\varphi_{\alpha}\right>_{\alpha<\theta}\in\mathscr{V} be a maximal antichain of 𝕃\mathbb{L}. We must see GAG_{A} meets φαα<θ\left<\varphi_{\alpha}\right>_{\alpha<\theta}, or equivalently, that AφαA\vDash\varphi_{\alpha} for some α\alpha. Supposing otherwise, AψA\vDash\psi where

ψ=α<θ¬φα,\psi=\bigwedge_{\alpha<\theta}\lnot\varphi_{\alpha},

and by Lemma 2, θ<δ\theta<\delta_{\infty}, so ψ\psi\in\mathcal{L}.

For each q𝒞p1q\in\mathcal{C}_{p_{1}}, we have 𝒱𝒫q\mathscr{V}\subseteq{\cal P}_{q}, so 𝕃𝒫q\mathbb{L}\in{\cal P}_{q}, and by hypothesis there is a (𝒫q,𝔹q)(\mathcal{P}_{q},\mathbb{B}_{q})-generic gMg\in M with (τq)g=A(\tau_{q})_{g}=A, so

p𝔹q[p𝔹q𝒫qτqψ].\displaystyle\exists p\in\mathbb{B}_{q}\,[p\Vdash^{{\cal P}_{q}}_{\mathbb{B}_{q}}\text{``}\tau_{q}\vDash\psi\text{''}]. (7)

Considering the definition of π+\pi_{\infty}^{+}, note that we may take q𝒞pq\in\mathcal{C}_{p} such that πq(ψ)=π+(ψ)=ψ+\pi_{q\infty}(\psi)=\pi_{\infty}^{+}(\psi)=\psi^{*+}, so that (7) implies

p𝔹[p𝔹τψ+],\exists p\in{\mathbb{B}}_{\infty}\,[p\Vdash^{{\cal M}_{\infty}}_{{\mathbb{B}}_{\infty}}\text{``}\tau_{\infty}\vDash\psi^{*+}\text{''}]{\rm,}

so ψ𝕃\psi\in\mathbb{L}. But the elementarity of π+\pi_{\infty}^{+} easily gives that ψφα\psi\perp\varphi_{\alpha} for every α<θ\alpha<\theta, so φαα<θ\left<\varphi_{\alpha}\right>_{\alpha<\theta} is not a maximal antichain. Contradiction! ∎

Finally, suppose:

  1. (ug24)

    For every ordinal μ\mu with cardM(VμM)=μ\mathrm{card}^{M}(V_{\mu}^{M})=\mu, there is a set A𝒫(μ)MA^{\prime}\in\mathcal{P}(\mu)^{M} coding VμMV_{\mu}^{M}, and there is p1dp_{1}\in d such that μ\mu is p1p_{1}-stable, and there is a 𝔹p1\mathbb{B}_{p_{1}}-name τp1𝒫p1\tau^{\prime}_{p_{1}}\in\mathcal{P}_{p_{1}} such that the hypotheses of Lemma 2 hold for A,p1,τp1A^{\prime},p_{1},\tau^{\prime}_{p_{1}}.

So under these assumptions for a given μ,A,τp1\mu,A^{\prime},\tau^{\prime}_{p_{1}}, the conclusion of Lemma 2 holds with respect to 𝕃(τ)\mathbb{L}(\tau^{\prime}_{\infty}). Assumption (ug24) basically says that the 𝒫p\mathcal{P}_{p} form a system of grounds for MM in a “uniform” manner.

Definition 2.5.

For MM, etc, as above, we say that 𝒟,𝒟+\mathscr{D},\mathscr{D}^{+} provide uniform grounds for MM iff conditions (ug1)(ug24) hold.

Theorem 2.5.

Under the uniform grounds assumptions, 𝒱\mathscr{V} is a ground of MM, via a forcing \mathbb{P} such that MM\vDash\mathbb{P} has cardinality 2δ\leq 2^{\delta_{\infty}}” and 𝒱\mathscr{V}\vDash\mathbb{P} is δ\delta_{\infty}-cc”. Therefore δ\delta_{\infty} is a regular cardinal in MM.

However, \mathcal{M}_{\infty} is not a ground of MM.

Proof.

We have that every set (of ordinals) in MM is generic over 𝒱\mathscr{V} for some 𝕃(τ)𝔹\mathbb{L}(\tau^{\prime}_{\infty})\subseteq\mathbb{B}_{\infty}. Since there are only set-many such forcings, 𝒱\mathscr{V} is in fact a ground of MM for some such 𝕃(τ)\mathbb{L}(\tau^{\prime}_{\infty}). Moreover, this forcing is δ\delta_{\infty}-cc in 𝒱\mathscr{V}, by [11, Theorem 2.2], we can find a forcing 𝒱\mathbb{P}\in\mathscr{V} as desired.

The “therefore” clause now follows (recall δ\delta_{\infty} is a regular cardinal of 𝒱\mathscr{V}).

Now 𝒱\mathscr{V}^{\mathcal{M}_{\infty}} is a ground of \mathcal{M}_{\infty} (since 𝒱\mathscr{V} is a ground of MM). Suppose \mathcal{M}_{\infty} is a ground of MM. Then 𝒱\mathscr{V}^{\mathcal{M}_{\infty}} is also a ground of MM. But MM defines π+:𝒱𝒱\pi_{\infty}^{+}:\mathscr{V}\to\mathscr{V}^{\mathcal{M}_{\infty}}, which is then a non-trivial elementary embedding between two grounds of MM, contradicting [5, Theorem 8]. ∎

When we produce instances of uniform grounds later, we will actually know more: we will have Vδ=Vδ𝒱V_{\delta_{\infty}}^{\mathcal{M}_{\infty}}=V_{\delta_{\infty}}^{\mathscr{V}} and δ\delta_{\infty} Woodin in 𝒱\mathscr{V} (hence also in \mathcal{M}_{\infty}, so δ\delta Woodin in MM, which will be an assumption), and 𝔹δ\mathbb{B}\subseteq\delta, so 𝕃δ\mathbb{L}\subseteq\delta_{\infty}, so some 𝕃(τ)\mathbb{L}(\tau^{\prime}_{\infty}) will be a \mathbb{P} as above, but in fact of cardinality δ\delta_{\infty} in 𝒱\mathscr{V} and hence also in MM.

3 The model MswswM_{\mathrm{swsw}}

In this section introduce the mouse MswswM_{\mathrm{swsw}} we will be analyzing, and establish some of its basic properties, as well as some of those of its iteration strategy.

Definition 3.1.

Let ψswsw\psi_{\mathrm{swsw}} be the statement, in the passive premouse language, asserting “There are ordinals δ0<κ0<δ1<κ1\delta_{0}<\kappa_{0}<\delta_{1}<\kappa_{1} with δi\delta_{i} Woodin and κi\kappa_{i} strong for i1i\leq 1, as witnessed by 𝔼\mathbb{E}”. Let M#M^{\#} be the least active mouse such that M#|μψswswM^{\#}|\mu\vDash\psi_{\mathrm{swsw}} where μ=crit(FM#)\mu={\rm crit}(F^{M^{\#}}).999By [18], Woodinness and strength is automatically witnessed by 𝔼#\mathbb{E}^{\mathcal{M}^{\#}}, as a consequence of iterability, but we will also consider premice NψswswN\vDash\psi_{\mathrm{swsw}} which need not be iterable. Then MswswM_{\mathrm{swsw}} denotes the proper class model left behind by iterating FM#F^{M^{\#}} out of the universe. Note ρω(M#)=ρ1(M#)=ω\rho_{\omega}({M^{\#}})=\rho_{1}(M^{\#})=\omega, p1M#=p_{1}^{M^{\#}}=\emptyset and M#M^{\#} is ω\omega-sound. We assume throughout that M#M^{\#} exists and is (ω,OR,OR)(\omega,\mathrm{OR},\mathrm{OR})-iterable.101010We could probably just work with (ω,ω1+1)(\omega,\omega_{1}+1)-iterability. By [20, Theorems 9.1, 9.3], because M#M^{\#} is ω\omega-sound and projects to ω\omega, (ω,ω1+1)(\omega,\omega_{1}+1)-iterability for M#M^{\#} implies (ω,ω1,ω1+1)(\omega,\omega_{1},\omega_{1}+1)^{*}-iterability, and similarly, (ω,OR)(\omega,\mathrm{OR})-iterability for M#M^{\#} implies (ω,OR,OR)(\omega,\mathrm{OR},\mathrm{OR})-iterability. We usually write M=MswswM=M_{\mathrm{swsw}}.

Let Σ\Sigma denote the (ω,OR)(\omega,\mathrm{OR})-iteration strategy (that is, for ω\omega-maximal, hence normal, trees, of set length) for MM which is induced by the unique (ω,OR)(\omega,\mathrm{OR})-strategy ΣM#\Sigma_{M^{\#}} for M#M^{\#}. Let Γ=Σstk\Gamma=\Sigma^{\mathrm{stk}} denote the optimal-(ω,OR,OR)(\omega,\mathrm{OR},\mathrm{OR})-strategy for MM which is induced by Σ\Sigma via the normalization process of [15] (see Fact 3 below, especially item (Σ\Sigma1) there).

Certain aspects of normalization, used to define Γ=Σstk\Gamma=\Sigma^{\mathrm{stk}} from Σ\Sigma, will be used in the paper. The main features we need are the properties of Σ\Sigma mentioned in Fact 3 below, which can be black-boxed. Some of the details of the normalization process will also come up to some extent later on, but the reader unfamiliar with those details should still be able to follow most of the arguments in the paper.

Remark 3.1.

MM knows enough of Σ\Sigma that M|ω1MM|\omega_{1}^{M} is definable over the universe of MM (without parameters). Therefore by [22, Theorem 1.1], 𝔼M\mathbb{E}^{M} is definable over the universe of MM without parameters. Thus, when we talk about definability over MM, it does not matter whether we are given 𝔼M\mathbb{E}^{M} as a predicate or not. However, if gg is MM-generic, then HODM[g]\mathrm{HOD}^{M[g]} can differ from HOD𝔼MM[g]\mathrm{HOD}^{M[g]}_{\mathbb{E}^{M}}, for example.

Definition 3.2.

If 𝒯{\vec{\mathcal{T}}} is a stack on MM via Γ\Gamma, then Γ𝒯,N\Gamma_{{\vec{\mathcal{T}}},N} denotes the tail stacks strategy for NN induced by Γ\Gamma, i.e. Γ𝒯,N(𝒰)=Γ(𝒯^𝒰)\Gamma_{{\vec{\mathcal{T}}},N}({\vec{\mathcal{U}}})=\Gamma({\vec{\mathcal{T}}}\ \widehat{\ }\ {\vec{\mathcal{U}}}). Also Σ𝒯,N\Sigma_{{\vec{\mathcal{T}}},N} denotes the normal part of Γ𝒯,N\Gamma_{{\vec{\mathcal{T}}},N}. Actually by what follows below, we can and usually do write ΓN\Gamma_{N} and ΣN\Sigma_{N}.

Recall that Γ=Σstk\Gamma=\Sigma^{\mathrm{stk}} is the strategy for stacks induced by Σ\Sigma.

Fact 3.2.

We have:

  1. (Σ\Sigma1)

    Σ\Sigma is the unique (ω,OR)(\omega,\mathrm{OR})-strategy for MM, so satisfies both strong hull condensation and minimal hull condensation, and therefore by [15]:

    • every iterate of MM via Γ\Gamma is also an iterate via Σ\Sigma,

    • if GG is VV-generic then Σ,Γ\Sigma,\Gamma extend canonically to V[G]V[G], with the same properties there; with an abuse of notation, we continue to write Σ,Γ=Σstk\Sigma,\Gamma=\Sigma^{\mathrm{stk}} for these extensions, or may write ΣV[G]\Sigma^{V[G]} or ΓV[G]\Gamma^{V[G]} to emphasize the distinction.

  2. (Σ\Sigma2)

    Γ\Gamma is fully positional, in that whenever 𝒯,𝒰\vec{\mathcal{T}},\vec{\mathcal{U}} are two stacks via Γ\Gamma with the same last model NN, then Γ𝒯,N=Γ𝒰,N\Gamma_{\vec{\mathcal{T}},N}=\Gamma_{\vec{\mathcal{U}},N}, irrespective of drops. However, positionality will only be relevant in the non-dropping case.

  3. (Σ\Sigma3)

    Γ\Gamma is commuting, i.e., if 𝒯^𝒰{\vec{\mathcal{T}}}\ \widehat{\ }\ {\vec{\mathcal{U}}} and 𝒯^𝒱{\vec{\mathcal{T}}}\ \widehat{\ }\ {\vec{\mathcal{V}}} are non-dropping stacks via Γ\Gamma with a common last model, then i𝒰=i𝒱i^{\vec{\mathcal{U}}}=i^{\vec{\mathcal{V}}}; see [15, ***Theorem 10.4].

  4. (Σ\Sigma4)

    For all 𝒯{\vec{\mathcal{T}}} via Γ\Gamma, with last model NN, Σ𝒯,N\Sigma_{{\vec{\mathcal{T}}},N} has minimal hull condensation and Γ𝒯,N=(Σ𝒯,N)stk\Gamma_{{\vec{\mathcal{T}}},N}=(\Sigma_{{\vec{\mathcal{T}}},N})^{\mathrm{stk}}; see [15, ***Theorem 10.2].111111In order to define (Σ𝒯,N)stk(\Sigma_{{\vec{\mathcal{T}}},N})^{\mathrm{stk}}, one also needs that NN is nn-standard, where n=deg𝒯n=\deg^{{\vec{\mathcal{T}}}}_{\infty}, but this follows from the fact that MM is 0-standard, by [15, ***Remark 2.2]. Thus, every iterate of NN via Γ𝒯,N\Gamma_{{\vec{\mathcal{T}}},N} is also an iterate via Σ𝒯,N\Sigma_{{\vec{\mathcal{T}}},N}, in a unique manner,

  5. (Σ\Sigma5)

    If 𝒯,𝒰\mathcal{T},\mathcal{U} are via Σ\Sigma, of successor length, with non-dropping final branches, P=M𝒯P=M^{\mathcal{T}}_{\infty} and Q=M𝒰Q=M^{\mathcal{U}}_{\infty}, ηORM\eta\in\mathrm{OR}^{M}, η=i𝒯(η)=i𝒰(η)\eta^{\prime}=i^{\mathcal{T}}(\eta)=i^{\mathcal{U}}(\eta) and P|η=Q|ηP|\eta^{\prime}=Q|\eta^{\prime} then Σ𝒯,M𝒯\Sigma_{\mathcal{T},M^{\mathcal{T}}_{\infty}} and Σ𝒰,M𝒰\Sigma_{\mathcal{U},M^{\mathcal{U}}_{\infty}} agree with one another in their action on trees 𝒱\mathcal{V} based on P|ηP|\eta^{\prime}. See [15, ***Theorem 10.5].121212The precise version of this fact might be simplified by the fact that MM is below superstrong.

Remark 3.2.

Very strong hull condensation ([23]) implies minimal hull condensation ([15]), which implies minimal inflation condensation ([15]). For the normalization process of [15], minimal inflation condensation is sufficient, but for the generic absoluteness results, minimal hull condensation is used.

Definition 3.3.

We say that a stack 𝒯{\vec{\mathcal{T}}} on MM is correct if it is via Γ\Gamma. We say that NN is a Σ\Sigma-iterate of MM iff there is a correct stack 𝒯{\vec{\mathcal{T}}} on MM with last model N=M𝒯N=M^{{\vec{\mathcal{T}}}}_{\infty}. By the properties above, we may in fact take 𝒯\mathcal{T} via Σ\Sigma (hence normal), and note that this 𝒯\mathcal{T} is uniquely determined by NN (and Σ\Sigma); we write 𝒯N=𝒯\mathcal{T}_{N}=\mathcal{T}. A Σ\Sigma-iterate is a dropping iterate iff b𝒯b^{\mathcal{T}} drops, and otherwise is non-dropping.

Let NN be a non-dropping Σ\Sigma-iterate. Then a ΣN\Sigma_{N}-iterate is similarly an iterate of NN via ΣN\Sigma_{N} (equivalently, via ΓN\Gamma_{N}).131313We don’t need to iterate dropping iterates of MM further. If PP is a non-dropping ΣN\Sigma_{N}-iterate, let iNP:NPi_{NP}:N\to P be the iteration map (via ΣN\Sigma_{N}). Given δORN\delta\leq\mathrm{OR}^{N}, we say that NN is δ\delta-sound iff, letting 𝒯=𝒯N\mathcal{T}=\mathcal{T}_{N}, we have N=HullN(δrg(i𝒯))N=\mathrm{Hull}^{N}(\delta\cup\mathrm{rg}(i^{\mathcal{T}})); equivalently, ν(Eα𝒯)δ\nu(E^{\mathcal{T}}_{\alpha})\leq\delta for all α+1<lh(𝒯)\alpha+1<{\rm lh}(\mathcal{T}).

Definition 3.4.

Let M\mathscr{I}^{M} denote the class of critical points of the linear iteration of FM#F^{M^{\#}} which produces MM. For NN as above, let N=iMNM\mathscr{I}^{N}=i_{MN}``\mathscr{I}^{M}.

Definition 3.5 (MswswM_{\mathrm{swsw}}-like).

A premouse NN is MswswM_{\mathrm{swsw}}-like iff NN is proper class and satisfies a certain finite sub-theory TT of the theory of MM, including ψswsw+\psi_{\mathrm{swsw}}+“I have no active proper segment RR such that R|crit(FR)ψswswR|{\rm crit}(F^{R})\vDash\psi_{\mathrm{swsw}}”. We will not spell TT out exactly, but the reader should add statements to it as needed to make certain arguments work. For an MswswM_{\mathrm{swsw}}-like model NN, write

{δ0N= the least Woodin cardinal of Nκ0N= the least strong cardinal of Nκ0+N=(κ0N)+Nδ1N= the least Woodin cardinal of N above κ0Nκ1N= the least strong cardinal of N above δ0Nκ1+N=(κ1N)+N\displaystyle\begin{cases}\delta_{0}^{N}=\mbox{ the least Woodin cardinal of }N\\ \kappa_{0}^{N}=\mbox{ the least strong cardinal of }N\\ \kappa_{0}^{+N}=(\kappa_{0}^{N})^{+N}\\ \delta_{1}^{N}=\mbox{ the least Woodin cardinal of }N\mbox{ above }\kappa_{0}^{N}\\ \kappa_{1}^{N}=\mbox{ the least strong cardinal of }N\mbox{ above }\delta_{0}^{N}\\ \kappa_{1}^{+N}=(\kappa_{1}^{N})^{+N}\\ \end{cases} (8)

If N=MN=M, then we may suppress the superscript NN, so δ0=δ0M\delta_{0}=\delta_{0}^{M}, etc.

Fact 3.5.

Let NN be a non-dropping Σ\Sigma-iterate of MM and 𝒯=𝒯N\mathcal{T}=\mathcal{T}_{N}. Let δ=δ(𝒯)=supα+1<lh(𝒯)ν(Eα𝒯)\delta=\delta(\mathcal{T})=\sup_{\alpha+1<{\rm lh}(\mathcal{T})}\nu(E^{\mathcal{T}}_{\alpha}). Then δκ1N<min(N)\delta\leq\kappa_{1}^{N}<\min(\mathscr{I}^{N}) and N\mathscr{I}^{N} is the unique club class of indiscernibles II such that N=Hull1N(Iδ)N=\mathrm{Hull}_{1}^{N}(I\cup\delta), or alternatively such that N=Hull1N(Iκ1P)N=\mathrm{Hull}^{N}_{1}(I\cup\kappa_{1}^{P}).

The following two lemmas are instances of branch condensation (see [7]) and are simple variants of [8, Lemma 2.1]; we fill in a couple of key points which were omitted from that proof, however.

Lemma 3.5 (Branch condensation A).

Let 𝒰0\mathcal{U}_{0} be a successor length tree on MM, via Σ\Sigma, based on M|δ0MM|\delta_{0}^{M}, with b𝒰0b^{\mathcal{U}_{0}} non-dropping. Let 𝒯,𝒰\mathcal{T},\mathcal{U} be on N=M𝒰0N=M^{\mathcal{U}_{0}}_{\infty}, via ΣN\Sigma_{N}, based on N|δ0NN|\delta_{0}^{N}, with 𝒯\mathcal{T} of limit length and 𝒰\mathcal{U} successor with b𝒰b^{\mathcal{U}} non-dropping. Let GG be VV-generic. Let b,kV[G]b,k\in V[G] where bb is a non-dropping 𝒯\mathcal{T}-cofinal branch and

k:Mb𝒯|δ0Mb𝒯M𝒰|δ0M𝒰k:M^{\mathcal{T}}_{b}|\delta_{0}^{M^{\mathcal{T}}_{b}}\to M^{\mathcal{U}}_{\infty}|\delta_{0}^{M^{\mathcal{U}}_{\infty}}

is elementary with kib𝒯i0𝒰k\circ i^{\mathcal{T}}_{b}\subseteq i^{\mathcal{U}}_{0\infty}. Then b=ΣN(𝒯)b=\Sigma_{N}(\mathcal{T}).

Proof.

Because Σ\Sigma extends to V[G]V[G], with corresponding properties there (cf. Fact 3(Σ\Sigma1)), we may assume G=G=\emptyset. Let c=ΣN(𝒯)c=\Sigma_{N}(\mathcal{T}). Let Pb=Mb𝒯P_{b}=M^{\mathcal{T}}_{b} and Pc=Mc𝒯P_{c}=M^{\mathcal{T}}_{c}.

Suppose first δ(𝒯)<δ0Pb\delta(\mathcal{T})<\delta_{0}^{P_{b}}. Then there is a Q-structure QPbQ^{\prime}\triangleleft P_{b} for δ(𝒯)\delta(\mathcal{T}), and because δ(𝒯)\delta(\mathcal{T}) is a cardinal of PbP_{b}, M(𝒯)M(\mathcal{T}) has no Woodin cardinals, so δ(𝒯)\delta(\mathcal{T}) is a strong cutpoint of QQ^{\prime}. Because we have kk, QQ^{\prime} is iterable.

If cc is non-dropping and δ(𝒯)=δ0Pc\delta(\mathcal{T})=\delta_{0}^{P_{c}} then we can compare QQ^{\prime} versus PcP_{c} for a contradiction. So in any case, Q=Q(𝒯,c)Q=Q(\mathcal{T},c) exists. Since M(𝒯)M(\mathcal{T}) has no Woodins, δ(𝒯)\delta(\mathcal{T}) is also a strong cutpoint of QQ, so we can compare and get Q=QQ=Q^{\prime}, so b=cb=c.

Now suppose δ(𝒯)=δ0Pb\delta(\mathcal{T})=\delta_{0}^{P_{b}}. Then we can argue as in the proof of [8, Lemma 2.1]; however, we fill in a seemingly key point: We extend kk to

k+:PbM𝒰k^{+}:P_{b}\to M^{\mathcal{U}}_{\infty}

with k+ib𝒯=i0𝒰k^{+}\circ i^{\mathcal{T}}_{b}=i^{\mathcal{U}}_{0\infty} as in [8]. Now Pb=PcP_{b}=P_{c} (this was not mentioned in [8]); for PbP_{b} is iterable and is δ0Pb\delta_{0}^{P_{b}}-sound, and likewise for PcP_{c}, but both are models of “I am MswswM_{\mathrm{swsw}}”, so comparison gives Pb=PcP_{b}=P_{c}. And because Pb=PcP_{b}=P_{c} and ib𝒯,ic𝒯i^{\mathcal{T}}_{b},i^{\mathcal{T}}_{c} fix all sufficiently large indiscernibles, we can indeed conclude that ib𝒯X=ic𝒯Xi^{\mathcal{T}}_{b}{\upharpoonright}X=i^{\mathcal{T}}_{c}{\upharpoonright}X, where

X=HullN(IN)δ0N,X=\mathrm{Hull}^{N}(I^{N})\cap\delta_{0}^{N},

where INI^{N} is the class of NN-indiscernibles. So by the Zipper Lemma, we get b=cb=c. ∎

There is also a version at δ1\delta_{1}. We won’t directly use this, but will use a variant, which will use a similar proof:

Lemma 3.5 (Branch condensation B).

Let 𝒰0\mathcal{U}_{0} be successor length on MM, via Σ\Sigma, based on M|δ1MM|\delta_{1}^{M}, with b𝒰0b^{\mathcal{U}_{0}} non-dropping. Let 𝒯,𝒰\mathcal{T},\mathcal{U} be on N=M𝒰0N=M^{\mathcal{U}_{0}}_{\infty}, via ΣN\Sigma_{N}, based on N|δ1NN|\delta_{1}^{N}, with 𝒯\mathcal{T} of limit length and above κ0+N\kappa_{0}^{+N}, 𝒰\mathcal{U} successor length with b𝒰b^{\mathcal{U}} non-dropping. Let GG be VV-generic. Let b,kV[G]b,k\in V[G] where bb is a non-dropping 𝒯\mathcal{T}-cofinal branch and

k:Mb𝒯|δ1Mb𝒯M𝒰|δ1M𝒰k:M^{\mathcal{T}}_{b}|\delta_{1}^{M^{\mathcal{T}}_{b}}\to M^{\mathcal{U}}_{\infty}|\delta_{1}^{M^{\mathcal{U}}_{\infty}}

is elementary with kib𝒯=i0𝒰k\circ i^{\mathcal{T}}_{b}=i^{\mathcal{U}}_{0\infty}. Then b=ΣN(𝒯)b=\Sigma_{N}(\mathcal{T}).

Proof.

Again we may assume b,kVb,k\in V. Let αb𝒰0\alpha\in b^{\mathcal{U}_{0}} be least with either α+1=lh(𝒰0)\alpha+1={\rm lh}(\mathcal{U}_{0}) or κ0(Mα𝒰0)<crit(iα𝒰0)\kappa_{0}(M^{\mathcal{U}_{0}}_{\alpha})<{\rm crit}(i^{\mathcal{U}_{0}}_{\alpha\infty}). Let N¯=Mα𝒰0\bar{N}=M^{\mathcal{U}_{0}}_{\alpha}. So κ0N=κ0N¯\kappa_{0}^{N}=\kappa_{0}^{\bar{N}} and N¯\bar{N} is κ0N\kappa_{0}^{N}-sound and π:N¯N\pi:\bar{N}\to N where π=iα𝒰0\pi=i^{\mathcal{U}_{0}}_{\alpha\infty} and crit(π)>κ0N{\rm crit}(\pi)>\kappa_{0}^{N}. Let Pb=Mb𝒯P_{b}=M^{\mathcal{T}}_{b}, c=ΣN(𝒯)c=\Sigma_{N}(\mathcal{T}) and Pc=Mc𝒯P_{c}=M^{\mathcal{T}}_{c}. If δ(𝒯)<δ1Pb\delta(\mathcal{T})<\delta_{1}^{P_{b}} then let QbPbQ_{b}\triangleleft P_{b} be the Q-structure for δ(𝒯)\delta(\mathcal{T}); this exists because δ1N\delta_{1}^{N} is the least Woodin of NN above κ0N\kappa_{0}^{N}, and 𝒯\mathcal{T} is above κ0+N\kappa_{0}^{+N}. Otherwise let Qb=PbQ_{b}=P_{b}. This time, QbQ_{b} can have extenders EE overlapping δ(𝒯)\delta(\mathcal{T}), but only with crit(E)=κ0N{\rm crit}(E)=\kappa_{0}^{N}. Let QcPcQ_{c}\trianglelefteq P_{c} be likewise.

Define phalanxes 𝔓¯=((N¯,κ0N),Qb,δ(𝒯)) and 𝔔¯=((N¯,κ0N),Qc,δ(𝒯))\bar{\mathfrak{P}}=((\bar{N},\kappa_{0}^{N}),Q_{b},\delta(\mathcal{T}))\text{ and }\bar{\mathfrak{Q}}=((\bar{N},\kappa_{0}^{N}),Q_{c},\delta(\mathcal{T})). We claim 𝔓¯,𝔔¯\bar{\mathfrak{P}},\bar{\mathfrak{Q}} are iterable.141414The notation indicates that we start iterating the phalanx with extenders of index >δ(𝒯)>\delta(\mathcal{T}), and extenders with critical point κ0\kappa_{0} apply to N¯\bar{N}. Given this, we can compare 𝔓¯,𝔔¯\bar{\mathfrak{P}},\bar{\mathfrak{Q}}, and because N¯\bar{N} is κ0N\kappa_{0}^{N}-sound and Qb,QcQ_{b},Q_{c} are δ(𝒯)\delta(\mathcal{T})-sound, we get Qb=QcQ_{b}=Q_{c}, so if bcb\neq c then Pb=Qb=Qc=PcP_{b}=Q_{b}=Q_{c}=P_{c} and δ1Pb=δ(𝒯)\delta_{1}^{P_{b}}=\delta(\mathcal{T}), and we reach a contradiction like before.

Define phalanxes 𝔓=((N,κ0N),Pb,δ(𝒯))\mathfrak{P}=((N,\kappa_{0}^{N}),P_{b},\delta(\mathcal{T})) and 𝔔=((N,κ0N),Pc,δ(𝒯))\mathfrak{Q}=((N,\kappa_{0}^{N}),P_{c},\delta(\mathcal{T})). It suffices to see 𝔓,𝔔\mathfrak{P},\mathfrak{Q} are iterable, because then we can reduce trees on 𝔓¯\bar{\mathfrak{P}} to trees on 𝔓\mathfrak{P}, using π:N¯N\pi:\bar{N}\to N, and likewise 𝔔¯\bar{\mathfrak{Q}} to 𝔔\mathfrak{Q}.

But 𝔔\mathfrak{Q} is iterable because c=Σ(𝒯)c=\Sigma(\mathcal{T}). For 𝔓\mathfrak{P}, we have k+:PbM𝒰k^{+}:P_{b}\to M^{\mathcal{U}}_{\infty} defined as before (note that the same definition still works in case δ(𝒯)<δ1Pb\delta(\mathcal{T})<\delta_{1}^{P_{b}}). So PbP_{b} is iterable. But ib𝒯:NPbi^{\mathcal{T}}_{b}:N\to P_{b} with crit(ib𝒯)>κ0N{\rm crit}(i^{\mathcal{T}}_{b})>\kappa_{0}^{N}. So we can lift trees on 𝔓\mathfrak{P} to trees on PbP_{b} using the maps (ib𝒯,id)(i^{\mathcal{T}}_{b},\mathrm{id}). So 𝔓\mathfrak{P} is iterable. ∎

4 The first Varsovian model 𝒱1\mathscr{V}_{1}

We begin by identifying a natural direct limit system, giving uniform grounds for M=MswswM=M_{\mathrm{swsw}}, in the sense Definition 2.5 in §2, hence yielding a Varsovian model, which we denote 𝒱1\mathscr{V}_{1} (we will later define a second Varsovian model 𝒱2\mathscr{V}_{2}). The direct limit system will be defined analogously to that of [8, §2]. The main difference is in the increased large cardinal level. A smaller difference, one of approach, is that we use normalization, which means that we can focus on normal trees, instead of stacks.

4.1 The models for the system

Definition 4.1.

Let 𝒯\mathcal{T} be a limit length normal tree on MM, based on M|δ0MM|\delta_{0}^{M}, via Σ\Sigma.151515Recall Σ\Sigma is the (0,OR)(0,\mathrm{OR})-strategy (that is, for ω\omega-maximal, hence normal, trees) for MM. Let b=Σ(𝒯)b=\Sigma(\mathcal{T}). We say that 𝒯\mathcal{T} is short iff either bb drops or δ(𝒯)<i0b𝒯(δ0M)=δ0b𝒯\delta(\mathcal{T})<i^{\mathcal{T}}_{0b}(\delta_{0}^{M})=\delta_{0}^{{\cal M}_{b}^{\mathcal{T}}}; otherwise 𝒯\mathcal{T} is maximal. Let Σsh\Sigma_{\mathrm{sh}} be the restriction of Σ\Sigma to short trees.

If PP is a non-dropping Σ\Sigma-iterate of MM and 𝒯\mathcal{T} is limit length normal on PP and based on P|δ0PP|\delta_{0}^{P}, we define short/maximal for 𝒯\mathcal{T} analogously, and ΣP,sh\Sigma_{P,\mathrm{sh}} is the restriction of ΣP\Sigma_{P} to short trees.

Definition 4.2.

Let 𝕌{\mathbb{U}} consist of all iteration trees 𝒰M|κ0{\cal U}\in M|\kappa_{0} on MM, such that either 𝒰\mathcal{U} is trivial, or

  1. (a)

    𝒰{\cal U} is based on M|δ0M|\delta_{0}, via Σsh\Sigma_{\mathrm{sh}} (hence is ω\omega-maximal),

  2. (b)

    𝒰{\cal U} is maximal,

and for some strong cutpoint η<κ0\eta<\kappa_{0} of MM, writing δ=δ(𝒰)\delta=\delta(\mathcal{U}) and R=M(𝒰)R=M(\mathcal{U}),

  1. 3.

    lh(𝒰)=η+M=δ{\rm lh}({\cal U})=\eta^{+M}=\delta,

  2. 4.

    𝒰{\cal U} is definable from parameters over M|δM|\delta,

  3. 5.

    M|δM|\delta is RR-generic for 𝔹δR\mathbb{B}_{\delta}^{R},

  4. 6.

    P=def𝒫M(R)P=_{\mathrm{def}}\mathscr{P}^{M}(R) is proper class;161616Recall the notation 𝒫M\mathscr{P}^{M} from §1.1. 171717Recall δ\delta is Woodin in PP, as witnessed by 𝔼R\mathbb{E}^{R}, and VδPV_{\delta}^{P} is the universe of RR. hence PP is a ground of MM via 𝔹δR\mathbb{B}^{R}_{\delta}, and in fact P[M|δ]=^MP[M|\delta]\ \widehat{=}\ M. We write here also 𝒫M(𝒰)=P\mathscr{P}^{M}(\mathcal{U})=P.

The proof of [8, Lemma 2.2] or the first few claims in [19] give:

Lemma 4.2.

Let 𝒰𝕌{\cal U}\in{\mathbb{U}}, b=Σ(𝒰)b=\Sigma({\cal U}) and P=𝒫M(𝒰)P=\mathscr{P}^{M}(\mathcal{U}). Then b𝒰=P{\cal M}_{b}^{{\cal U}}=P, M=P\mathscr{I}^{M}=\mathscr{I}^{P} and i0b𝒯M=idi_{0b}^{\cal T}{\upharpoonright}\mathscr{I}^{M}=\mathrm{id}.

We have 𝕌M{\mathbb{U}}\subseteq M by definition, but because of the requirement that 𝒰𝕌\mathcal{U}\in{\mathbb{U}} be via Σsh\Sigma_{\mathrm{sh}} (hence via Σ\Sigma), it is not immediate that 𝕌M{\mathbb{U}}\in M. But we show in the next section that it is, and that 𝕌{\mathbb{U}} is rich, with the following properties: The restriction of Σsh\Sigma_{\mathrm{sh}} to MM is known to MM, and whenever P=𝒫M(𝒰)P=\mathscr{P}^{M}({\cal U}) for some 𝒰𝕌{\cal U}\in{\mathbb{U}}, the restriction of ΣP,sh\Sigma_{P,\mathrm{sh}} to MM is known to MM (and moreover, these are preserved by iMPi_{MP}). Pseudo-genericity iterations can be formed using these strategies to produce trees in 𝕌{\mathbb{U}}. Any two such models P1,P2P_{1},P_{2} can be pseudo-compared with these strategies. Moreover, every maximal tree 𝒯M|κ0{\cal T}\in M|\kappa_{0} via Σsh\Sigma_{\mathrm{sh}} is “absorbed” by some 𝒳𝕌{\cal X}\in{\mathbb{U}}.

4.2 The short tree strategy Σsh\Sigma_{\mathrm{sh}} for MM

We now show that MM is closed under Σsh\Sigma_{\mathrm{sh}} and ΣshM\Sigma_{\mathrm{sh}}{\upharpoonright}M is a class of MM, and that the same also holds with M[g]M[g] replacing MM, for any MM-generic gg (where gg need not be in VV); in fact when g=g=\emptyset the class can be taken lightface.

Let 𝒯\mathcal{T} be via Σ\Sigma of limit length, and b=Σ(𝒯)b=\Sigma(\mathcal{T}). Suppose we want to compute bb. Since Σ\Sigma has strong hull condensation, it suffices to find a tree 𝒳\mathcal{X} via Σ\Sigma and 𝒯\mathcal{T}-cofinal branch bb^{\prime} and a tree embedding Π:𝒯^b𝒳\Pi:\mathcal{T}\ \widehat{\ }\ b^{\prime}\to\mathcal{X}, for then b=bb^{\prime}=b.

Suppose also 𝒯M[g]\mathcal{T}\in M[g] and is based on M|δ0M|\delta_{0}. Working in M[g]M[g] we want to (i) determine whether 𝒯\mathcal{T} is short, and (ii) if short, compute Σsh(𝒯)\Sigma_{\mathrm{sh}}(\mathcal{T}). If it happens that 𝒯\mathcal{T} incorporates, in an appropriate manner, a genericity iteration for making 𝔼M\mathbb{E}^{M} generic, then we will be able to use P-constructions (combined with *-translation, discussed below) to achieve both of these goals. In the general case, we use the method of (genericity) inflation to reduce 𝒯\mathcal{T} to a tree 𝒳\mathcal{X} which does incorporate such a genericity iteration (see [20, §5.2], which adapts methods for tame mice from [12, §1]). We give here a sketch of the relevant methods from [20], restricted to our context; but the reader should consult [20] for details.

Suppose also that gg is MM-generic for some VθM\mathbb{P}\in V_{\theta}^{M}, and 𝒯VθM[g]\mathcal{T}\in V_{\theta}^{M[g]}. If θ<κ0\theta<\kappa_{0} let U=MU=M; otherwise let E𝔼ME\in\mathbb{E}^{M} be MM-total with crit(E)=κ0{\rm crit}(E)=\kappa_{0} and VθMU=Ult(M,E)V_{\theta}^{M}\subseteq U=\mathrm{Ult}(M,E) (so θ<λ(E)=κ0U\theta<\lambda(E)=\kappa_{0}^{U}). Let η\eta be a strong cutpoint of UU with θη<κ0U\theta\leq\eta<\kappa_{0}^{U}. Following [20], let 𝒳\mathcal{X} be the genericity inflation (explained further below) of 𝒯\mathcal{T} for making U|δ(𝒳)U|\delta(\mathcal{X}) generic for the δ(𝒳)\delta(\mathcal{X})-generator extender algebra, incorporating an initial linear iteration which moves the least measurable of M(𝒳)M(\mathcal{X}) beyond η\eta, and incorporating linear iterations past *-translations of Q-structures.181818The technique of inserting linear iterations past Q-structures comes from [17], where there are details of such a construction given. The *-translation is due to Steel, Neeman, Closson; see [1], together with an amendment in [13]. The *-translations of Q-structures are segments of UU which compute the Q-structures which guide branch choices for 𝒳\mathcal{X}.

Here is a sketch of the relevant material from [20]. We define 𝒳(α+1)\mathcal{X}{\upharpoonright}(\alpha+1) by induction on α\alpha. Suppose we have 𝒳(α+1)\mathcal{X}{\upharpoonright}(\alpha+1) defined, but have not yet succeeded in finding Σ(𝒯)\Sigma(\mathcal{T}). We will have an ordinal ηαOR(Mα𝒳)\eta_{\alpha}\leq\mathrm{OR}(M^{\mathcal{X}}_{\alpha}) defined, and possibly have an ordinal βα<lh(𝒯)\beta_{\alpha}<{\rm lh}(\mathcal{T}) and a lifting map

σα:Mβα𝒯||lh(Eβα𝒯)Mα𝒳||ηα\sigma_{\alpha}:M^{\mathcal{T}}_{\beta_{\alpha}}||{\rm lh}(E^{\mathcal{T}}_{\beta_{\alpha}})\to M^{\mathcal{X}}_{\alpha}||\eta_{\alpha}

defined. (At α=0\alpha=0 we have β0=0\beta_{0}=0 and η0=lh(E0𝒯)\eta_{0}={\rm lh}(E^{\mathcal{T}}_{0}) and σ0=id\sigma_{0}=\mathrm{id}.) We set Eα𝒳=FMα𝒳||ηαE^{\mathcal{X}}_{\alpha}=F^{M^{\mathcal{X}}_{\alpha}||\eta_{\alpha}}, unless there is an extender G𝔼Mα𝒳G\in\mathbb{E}^{M^{\mathcal{X}}_{\alpha}} with lh(G)<ηα{\rm lh}(G)<\eta_{\alpha} such that either (i) GG induces an extender algebra axiom which is not satisfied by 𝔼U\mathbb{E}^{U}, and GG satisfies some further conditions as explained in [20]191919It suffices that νG\nu_{G} is inaccessible in Mα𝒳|ηαM^{\mathcal{X}}_{\alpha}|\eta_{\alpha}, but one must also consider other extenders, including partial ones, because of the nature of genericity iteration with Jensen indexing. or (ii) GG is a measure to be used for one of the linear iterations mentioned above.202020The linear iterations need to be set up appropriately, to ensure that the process does not last too long; similar details are dealt with in the comparison arguments in [17]. We say Eα𝒳E^{\mathcal{X}}_{\alpha} is either copied from 𝒯\mathcal{T} (when lh(Eα𝒳)=ηα{\rm lh}(E^{\mathcal{X}}_{\alpha})=\eta_{\alpha} and (βα,σα)(\beta_{\alpha},\sigma_{\alpha}) are defined) or is inflationary (otherwise). The stages α\alpha for which (βα,σα)(\beta_{\alpha},\sigma_{\alpha}) is not defined correspond to a drop in model in 𝒳\mathcal{X}, below the image of the relevant extender from 𝒯\mathcal{T}, and arise because of the nature of genericity iteration with Jensen indexing. Let γ=pred𝒳(α+1)\gamma=\mathrm{pred}^{\mathcal{X}}(\alpha+1). If Eα𝒳E^{\mathcal{X}}_{\alpha} is copied then βα+1=βα+1\beta_{\alpha+1}=\beta_{\alpha}+1 is defined, and σα+1\sigma_{\alpha+1} is the restriction of a map given by the Shift Lemma applied to σα\sigma_{\alpha} and another map π\pi (whose domain is Mβα+1𝒯M^{*\mathcal{T}}_{\beta_{\alpha}+1}; we have not specified π\pi here). If Eα𝒳E^{\mathcal{X}}_{\alpha} is inflationary then βα+1\beta_{\alpha+1} is defined just in case βγ\beta_{\gamma} is defined and Eα𝒳E^{\mathcal{X}}_{\alpha} is total over Mγ𝒳||ηγM^{\mathcal{X}}_{\gamma}||\eta_{\gamma}, and in this case βα+1=βγ\beta_{\alpha+1}=\beta_{\gamma} and σα+1=iα+1𝒳σγ\sigma_{\alpha+1}=i^{*\mathcal{X}}_{\alpha+1}\circ\sigma_{\gamma}.

Now consider a limit stage λ\lambda. The first thing to do is either compute c=Σ(𝒳λ)c=\Sigma(\mathcal{X}{\upharpoonright}\lambda) (if λ<(η+)U\lambda<(\eta^{+})^{U}), or declare 𝒳,𝒯\mathcal{X},\mathcal{T} maximal (if λ=(η+)U\lambda=(\eta^{+})^{U}). Let δ=δ(𝒳λ)\delta=\delta(\mathcal{X}{\upharpoonright}\lambda). If M(𝒳λ)M(\mathcal{X}{\upharpoonright}\lambda) is a Q-structure for itself then bb is trivial, and arguing as in [17] shows that in this case, λ<(η+)U\lambda<(\eta^{+})^{U} (the argument is mostly standard, but some variant details arise, which are discussed there). So suppose otherwise. Then λ=δ\lambda=\delta and 𝒳δ\mathcal{X}{\upharpoonright}\delta is definable from parameters over (U|δ)[g](U|\delta)[g]. This is because η<δ\eta<\delta, 𝒯(U|η)[g]\mathcal{T}\in(U|\eta)[g], the process for determining ηα,Eα𝒳\eta_{\alpha},E^{\mathcal{X}}_{\alpha} is locally definable, and the *-translations of Q-structures used to compute the branches of 𝒳λ\mathcal{X}{\upharpoonright}\lambda are all proper segments of U|δU|\delta, because of the linear iterations past these *-translations. Moreover, U|δU|\delta is generic for the δ\delta-generator extender algebra of M(𝒳λ)M(\mathcal{X}{\upharpoonright}\lambda).

From now on, let us assume that g=g=\emptyset for simplicity; since η\eta is a strong cutpoint of UU, the general case only involves shifting to U[g]U[g]. Let c=Σ(𝒳δ)c=\Sigma(\mathcal{X}{\upharpoonright}\delta). Let Q=Q(𝒳δ,c)Q=Q(\mathcal{X}{\upharpoonright}\delta,c), considering 𝒳\mathcal{X} as a tree on M#M^{\#}. (Maybe 𝒳δ\mathcal{X}{\upharpoonright}\delta is not short.) Then QQ could have extenders overlapping δ\delta. But the *-translation QQ^{*} of (Q,𝒳δ)(Q,\mathcal{X}{\upharpoonright}\delta) is a premouse extending U|δU|\delta and having no overlaps of δ\delta, and in fact, either (i) δ<(η+)U\delta<(\eta^{+})^{U} and 𝒳δ\mathcal{X}{\upharpoonright}\delta is short and QUQ^{*}\triangleleft U, or (ii) λ=(η+)U\lambda=(\eta^{+})^{U} and 𝒳λ\mathcal{X}{\upharpoonright}\lambda is maximal and Q=U#Q^{*}=U^{\#}. So UU can see which of case (i) and (ii) we are in, and in case (i), compute Q,Q,cQ^{*},Q,c (as QQ^{*} is the unique segment of UU whose inverse *-translation is well-defined and terminates with a Q-structure for M(𝒳λ)M(\mathcal{X}{\upharpoonright}\lambda), which is then QQ). Moreover, the branch cc is determined by the *-translation QQ^{*} of a Q-structure, as promised earlier.

Suppose λ<(η+)U\lambda<(\eta^{+})^{U}. So we have computed c=Σ(𝒳λ)c=\Sigma(\mathcal{X}{\upharpoonright}\lambda) in U[g]U[g]. By [20], this determines either (i) some βλ<lh(𝒯)\beta_{\lambda}<{\rm lh}(\mathcal{T}) (and possibly a σλ\sigma_{\lambda} as before), in which case we continue the process; or (ii) a 𝒯\mathcal{T}-cofinal branch bb and a tree embedding

Π:𝒯^b𝒳^c\Pi:\mathcal{T}\ \widehat{\ }\ b\hookrightarrow\mathcal{X}\ \widehat{\ }\ c

with bb mapped cofinally into cc, and bb is encoded into cc, in such a manner that U[g]U[g] can compute b,Πb,\Pi from (𝒯,𝒳,c)(\mathcal{T},\mathcal{X},c).

Now suppose that the process reaches 𝒳\mathcal{X} of length (η+)U(\eta^{+})^{U}. So 𝒳\mathcal{X} is maximal and Q=U#Q^{*}=U^{\#}. Let c=Σ(𝒳)c=\Sigma(\mathcal{X}) and b=Σ(𝒯)b=\Sigma(\mathcal{T}). So ic𝒳(δ0M)=δ(𝒳λ)=(η+)Ui^{\mathcal{X}}_{c}(\delta_{0}^{M})=\delta(\mathcal{X}{\upharpoonright}\lambda)=(\eta^{+})^{U}. Again by [20], there is a tree embedding

Π:𝒯^b𝒳^c\Pi:\mathcal{T}\ \widehat{\ }\ b\hookrightarrow\mathcal{X}\ \widehat{\ }\ c

which maps bb cofinally in cc, and since 𝒯,𝒳\mathcal{T},\mathcal{X} are based on M|δ0MM|\delta_{0}^{M}, then 𝒯\mathcal{T} is maximal. Also in this case, considering 𝒯,𝒳\mathcal{T},\mathcal{X} as trees on MM, instead of on M#M^{\#}, we get that Mc𝒳=𝒫U(𝒳)M^{\mathcal{X}}_{c}=\mathscr{P}^{U}(\mathcal{X}) (the P-construction of UU above (𝒳)\mathcal{M}(\mathcal{X}), which is the analogue of the inverse *-translation of UU in this case), so if U=MU=M (and still g=g=\emptyset) then 𝒳𝕌\mathcal{X}\in\mathbb{U}.

This completes the sketch. For further details the reader should refer to [20], augmented by [1], [13] and [22].

Definition 4.3.

For a non-dropping Σ\Sigma-iterate PP of MM, ΣP,sh\Sigma_{P,\mathrm{sh}} (the short tree strategy for PP) denotes the restriction of ΣP\Sigma_{P} to short trees. Also, ΣP|δ0P\Sigma_{P|\delta_{0}^{P}} denotes the (0-maximal) strategy for P|δ0PP|\delta_{0}^{P} induced by Σ\Sigma (including maximal trees) and ΣP|δ0P,sh\Sigma_{P|\delta_{0}^{P},\mathrm{sh}} denotes its restriction to short trees.

Note that by Fact 3(Σ\Sigma5), the notations ΣP|δ0P\Sigma_{P|\delta_{0}^{P}} and ΣP|δ0P,sh\Sigma_{P|\delta_{0}^{P},\mathrm{sh}} are unambiguous; that is, if PQP\neq Q are both non-dropping Σ\Sigma-iterates of MM with P|δ0P=Q|δ0QP|\delta_{0}^{P}=Q|\delta_{0}^{Q}, then ΣP\Sigma_{P} agrees with ΣQ\Sigma_{Q} in terms of their action on trees based on P|δ0PP|\delta_{0}^{P}. Of course ΣP,sh\Sigma_{P,\mathrm{sh}} is equivalent to ΣP|δ0P,sh\Sigma_{P|\delta_{0}^{P},\mathrm{sh}}, except that the two strategies have different base models. This is useful notationally below, where we can refer directly to P|δ0PP|\delta_{0}^{P} but maybe not to PP.

We summarize the main results of this section in the following two lemmas:

Lemma 4.3.

Let gg be MM-generic. Then:

  1. 1.

    M[g]M[g] is closed under Σsh\Sigma_{\mathrm{sh}}.

  2. 2.

    𝔼M,ΣshM[g] and dom(ΣshM[g])\mathbb{E}^{M},\ \Sigma_{\mathrm{sh}}{\upharpoonright}M[g]\text{ and }{\rm dom}(\Sigma_{\mathrm{sh}}{\upharpoonright}M[g]) are classes of M[g]M[g], definable over M[g]M[g] (as a coarse structure) from the parameter M|(λ+ω)MM|(\lambda^{+\omega})^{M} where gM|λg\subseteq M|\lambda, uniformly in λ\lambda.

  3. 3.

    If g=g=\emptyset then these are in fact lightface classes of the universe M\left\lfloor M\right\rfloor of MM.

  4. 4.

    Therefore 𝕌\mathbb{U} is lightface MM-definable, as is 𝒫M(𝒰)𝒰𝕌\left<\mathscr{P}^{M}(\mathcal{U})\right>_{\mathcal{U}\in\mathbb{U}} (recall 𝒫N(𝒰)=N\mathscr{P}^{N}(\mathcal{U})=N if 𝒰\mathcal{U} is the trivial tree on NN),

  5. 5.

    For each non-dropping Σ\Sigma-iterate PP of MM with P¯=P|δ0PM\bar{P}=P|\delta_{0}^{P}\in M, MM is closed under ΣP¯,sh\Sigma_{\bar{P},\mathrm{sh}}, and ΣP¯,shM\Sigma_{\bar{P},\mathrm{sh}}{\upharpoonright}M is definable over MM from P¯\bar{P}, uniformly in P¯\bar{P}. Therefore the function

    S:P¯ΣP¯,shM,S:\bar{P}\mapsto\Sigma_{\bar{P},\mathrm{sh}}{\upharpoonright}M,

    with domain the class of all such P¯M\bar{P}\in M, is lightface MM-definable.

  6. 6.

    The corresponding facts hold after replacing MM by NN and Σsh\Sigma_{\mathrm{sh}} by ΣN,sh\Sigma_{N,\mathrm{sh}} and 𝕌\mathbb{U} by 𝕌N\mathbb{U}^{N}, for any non-dropping Σ\Sigma-iterate NN of MM. Moreover,

    iMN(ΣM,shM)=ΣN,shN,i_{MN}(\Sigma_{M,\mathrm{sh}}{\upharpoonright}M)=\Sigma_{N,\mathrm{sh}}{\upharpoonright}N,

    and with SS from part 5, iMN(S)i_{MN}(S) has the corresponding domain in NN, and iMN(S)(P¯)=ΣP¯,shNi_{MN}(S)(\bar{P})=\Sigma_{\bar{P},\mathrm{sh}}{\upharpoonright}N for each P¯dom(iMN(S))\bar{P}\in{\rm dom}(i_{MN}(S)).

Proof.

By the previous discussion, M[g]M[g] is closed under Σsh\Sigma_{\mathrm{sh}}. Moreover,

ΣshM[g] and dom(ΣshM[g])\Sigma_{\mathrm{sh}}{\upharpoonright}M[g]\text{ and }{\rm dom}(\Sigma_{\mathrm{sh}}{\upharpoonright}M[g])

are definable over M[g]M[g] from the predicate 𝔼M\mathbb{E}^{M}. But the universe M\left\lfloor M\right\rfloor of MM is definable over M[g]M[g] from M|(λ+ω)MM|(\lambda^{+\omega})^{M} by Woodin-Laver [6], [28]. By [22], 𝔼M\mathbb{E}^{M} is definable over M\left\lfloor M\right\rfloor from Mω1MM{\upharpoonright}\omega_{1}^{M}, but the latter is (ω,ω1+1)(\omega,\omega_{1}+1)-iterable in M\left\lfloor M\right\rfloor (via Σsh\Sigma_{\mathrm{sh}}), and is therefore definable without parameters there (which is relevant to the case that g=g=\emptyset). Part 5 is a straightforward adaptation; in fact, note that trees via ΣP¯,sh\Sigma_{\bar{P},\mathrm{sh}} normalize to trees via Σsh\Sigma_{\mathrm{sh}}. Part 6 is also straightforward, using the uniformity of the process.212121However, working inside NN, if 𝒯\mathcal{T} on N|δ0NN|\delta_{0}^{N} is maximal and we minimally inflate 𝒯\mathcal{T} to produce 𝒳\mathcal{X}, and build the proper class model 𝒫N(M(𝒳))\mathscr{P}^{N}(M(\mathcal{X})) by P-construction, and c=ΣN(𝒳)c=\Sigma_{N}(\mathcal{X}), then it need not be that Mc𝒳=𝒫N(M(𝒳))M^{\mathcal{X}}_{c}=\mathscr{P}^{N}(M(\mathcal{X})). But in this case, Mc𝒳M^{\mathcal{X}}_{c} and 𝒫N(M(𝒳))\mathscr{P}^{N}(M(\mathcal{X})) will still compare to a common model above δ(𝒳)\delta(\mathcal{X}). Related issues will be discussed further in §4.11.

Lemma 4.3.

Let gg be MM-generic for \mathbb{P} and 𝒯M[g]{\cal T}\in M[g] be a limit length normal tree on MM which is based on M|δ0MM|\delta_{0}^{M} and via Σ\Sigma. If 𝒯M|κ0\mathcal{T}\in M|\kappa_{0} let U=MU=M, and otherwise let E𝔼ME\in\mathbb{E}^{M} be MM-total with crit(E)=κ0{\rm crit}(E)=\kappa_{0} and

VθMU=Ult(M,E)\mathbb{P}\in V_{\theta}^{M}\subseteq U=\mathrm{Ult}(M,E)

and 𝒯VθM[g]\mathcal{T}\in V_{\theta}^{M[g]}. Let b=Σ(𝒯)b=\Sigma(\mathcal{T}). Let η\eta be a strong cutpoint of UU with θη<κ0U\theta\leq\eta<\kappa_{0}^{U}. Then there is 𝒳=𝒳𝒯,ηU[g]M[g]\mathcal{X}=\mathcal{X}_{\mathcal{T},\eta}\in U[g]\subseteq M[g] such that:

  1. (1)

    𝒳{\cal X} is a limit length tree on UU (but is equivalent to one on MM), based on M|δ0MM|\delta_{0}^{M}, via ΣU\Sigma_{U} (hence ω\omega-maximal); let c=Σ(𝒳)c=\Sigma(\mathcal{X}) and δ=δ(𝒳)\delta=\delta(\mathcal{X}),

  2. (2)

    δ(η+)U\delta\leq(\eta^{+})^{U},

  3. (3)

    U|δU|\delta is M(𝒳)M(\mathcal{X})-generic for 𝔹δM(𝒳)\mathbb{B}_{\delta}^{M(\mathcal{X})},

  4. (4)

    If 𝒯{\cal T} is maximal then 𝒳\mathcal{X} is maximal, δ0Mc𝒳=δ=(η+)U\delta_{0}^{M^{\mathcal{X}}_{c}}=\delta=(\eta^{+})^{U} and Mc𝒳=𝒫U(𝒳)M^{\mathcal{X}}_{c}=\mathscr{P}^{U}(\mathcal{X}).

  5. (5)

    Suppose 𝒯\mathcal{T} is short. Then 𝒳\mathcal{X} is short and η<δ(𝒳)<(η+)U\eta<\delta(\mathcal{X})<(\eta^{+})^{U}, and there is RU|(η+)UR\triangleleft U|(\eta^{+})^{U} which computes the Q-structure Q(𝒳,c)Q(\mathcal{X},c) via inverse *-translation above M(𝒳)M(\mathcal{X}).

  6. (6)

    There is a tree embedding Π:𝒯^b𝒳^c\Pi:\mathcal{T}\ \widehat{\ }\ b\hookrightarrow\mathcal{X}\ \widehat{\ }\ c, and b,Πb,\Pi can be computed locally from (𝒯,𝒳,c)(\mathcal{T},\mathcal{X},c) (hence if 𝒯,𝒳\mathcal{T},\mathcal{X} are short then bU[g]b\in U[g]).

  7. (7)

    If 𝒯M|κ0\mathcal{T}\in M|\kappa_{0} (so U=MU=M) and 𝒯\mathcal{T} is maximal then 𝒳𝕌\mathcal{X}\in{\mathbb{U}}.

Definition 4.4.

We may also express the situation of the preceding lemma by saying that 𝒯^b{\cal T}\ \widehat{\ }\ b is absorbed by 𝒳^c{\cal X}\ \widehat{\ }\ c, or 𝒯{\cal T} is absorbed by 𝒳{\cal X}.

4.3 The first direct limit system

4.3.1 The external direct limit system 𝒟ext\mathscr{D}^{\mathrm{ext}}

We now define a system of uniform grounds for MM. In the notation of §2, we use index set

d={M|δ0}{(𝒰)|𝒰𝕌 is non-trivial}.d=\{M|\delta_{0}\}\cup\{\mathcal{M}(\mathcal{U})\bigm{|}\mathcal{U}\in\mathbb{U}\text{ is non-trivial}\}.

For pdp\in d, the associated model is 𝒫p=𝒫M(p)\mathcal{P}_{p}=\mathscr{P}^{M}(p). Of course dd and 𝕌\mathbb{U} are essentially equivalent. By Lemma 4.2, (d,𝒫ppd)(d,\left<\mathcal{P}_{p}\right>_{p\in d}) is lightface MM-definable. Write ={𝒫ppd}{\mathscr{F}}=\{\mathcal{P}_{p}\mid p\in d\}.

We now define the partial order \preceq on dd, and maps πpq\pi_{pq}. Let 𝒯,𝒰𝕌\mathcal{T},{\cal U}\in{\mathbb{U}} and P=𝒫M(𝒯)P=\mathscr{P}^{M}({\cal T}) and Q=𝒫M(𝒰)Q=\mathscr{P}^{M}({\cal U}). Set

(𝒯)(𝒰)Q is a ΣP-iterate of P.\mathcal{M}(\mathcal{T})\preceq\mathcal{M}(\mathcal{U})\Longleftrightarrow Q\text{ is a }\Sigma_{P}\text{-iterate of }P.

We also define the order \preceq on \mathscr{F} by PQP\preceq Q iff (𝒯)(𝒰)\mathcal{M}(\mathcal{T})\preceq\mathcal{M}(\mathcal{U}). The associated embedding π(𝒯)(𝒰)\pi_{\mathcal{M}(\mathcal{T})\mathcal{M}(\mathcal{U})} is just the iteration map iPQi_{PQ}. We remark that if PQP\neq Q then the tree witnessing that PQP\preceq Q is of the form 𝒱^ΣP(𝒱)\mathcal{V}\ \widehat{\ }\ \Sigma_{P}(\mathcal{V}), with 𝒱\mathcal{V} via ΣP,sh\Sigma_{P,\mathrm{sh}} and 𝒱M\mathcal{V}\in M, but ΣP(𝒱)M\Sigma_{P}(\mathcal{V})\notin M.222222MM cannot have an elementary embedding PQP\to Q, because P,QP,Q are both grounds of MM and by [5]. Therefore ΣP(𝒱)M\Sigma_{P}(\mathcal{V})\notin M. 𝒱\mathcal{V} is determined by P,Q,ΣP,shP,Q,\Sigma_{P,\mathrm{sh}} (in fact, just by P,QP,Q, because all the relevant Q-structures are segments of QQ), so 𝒱M\mathcal{V}\in M. We write 𝒯PQ\mathcal{T}_{PQ} for 𝒱^ΣP(𝒱)\mathcal{V}\ \widehat{\ }\ \Sigma_{P}(\mathcal{V}), and 𝒯PQ,sh=𝒱\mathcal{T}_{PQ,\mathrm{sh}}=\mathcal{V}. While iPQi_{PQ} is not amenable to MM (if non-identity), we do have:

Lemma 4.4.

\preceq is a directed partial order, is lightface MM-definable, and the associated embeddings commute: if PQRP\preceq Q\preceq R then iQRiPQ=iPRi_{QR}\circ i_{PQ}=i_{PR}.

Proof Sketch.

For the definability, note that PQP\preceq Q iff the pseudo-comparison of P,QP,Q, using ΣP,sh\Sigma_{P,\mathrm{sh}} to iterate PP,232323Or just reading Q-structures from segments of QQ to compute branches. yields a limit length tree 𝒯\mathcal{T} on PP with (𝒯)=Q|δ0Q\mathcal{M}(\mathcal{T})=Q|\delta_{0}^{Q} (so QQ does not move in the pseudo-comparison).

The fact that \preceq is a partial order, and the commutativity, follows from the properties of Σstk\Sigma^{\mathrm{stk}} in Fact 3.

For directedness, given P,QP,Q\in\mathscr{F}, witnessed by trees 𝒯,𝒰𝕌\mathcal{T},\mathcal{U}\in\mathbb{U}, form a simultaneous pseudo-comparison and 𝔼M\mathbb{E}^{M}-genericity iteration of P,QP,Q in MM, using ΣP,sh,ΣQ,sh\Sigma_{P,\mathrm{sh}},\Sigma_{Q,\mathrm{sh}}, producing trees 𝒱,𝒲\mathcal{V},\mathcal{W} respectively, and RR\in\mathscr{F} with P,QRP,Q\preceq R; note that if we normalize the stack (𝒯,𝒱)(\mathcal{T},\mathcal{V}), or the stack (𝒰,𝒲)(\mathcal{U},\mathcal{W}), we get the same normal tree 𝒳𝕌\mathcal{X}\in{\mathbb{U}}; here R=𝒫M(𝒳)R=\mathscr{P}^{M}(\mathcal{X}). ∎

Now define 𝒟ext=(P,Q,iPQ:PQ)\mathscr{D}^{\mathrm{ext}}=(P,Q,i_{PQ}\colon P\preceq Q\in{\mathscr{F}}). By the lemma, 𝒟ext\mathscr{D}^{\mathrm{ext}} is a direct limit system with properties (ug1), (ug2), (ug3), (ug4), (ug5). Note that (ug18) holds, with p0=M|δ0p_{0}=M|\delta_{0}. Define the direct limit model and maps

(ext,(iP:P))=dirlim𝒟ext.\displaystyle(\mathcal{M}_{\infty}^{\mathrm{ext}},(i_{P\infty}\colon P\in{\mathscr{F}}))=\mathrm{dirlim}\ \mathscr{D}^{\mathrm{ext}}. (9)

Notice that even though {\mathscr{F}} is a definable collection of classes in MM, this system is not “in” MM, as the maps iNPi_{NP} (when non-identity) are not amenable to MM. As usual, ext\mathcal{M}_{\infty}^{\mathrm{ext}} is wellfounded, giving (ug6).

Definition 4.5.

For PP\in\mathscr{F}, let τP\tau^{P} be the canonical class 𝔹δ0PP\mathbb{B}^{P}_{\delta_{0}^{P}}-name for MM; that is, τP\tau^{P} is the name for the class “premouse” NN such that N|δ0PN|\delta_{0}^{P} is given by the extender algebra generic, and 𝔼N[δ0P,)\mathbb{E}^{N}{\upharpoonright}[\delta_{0}^{P},\infty) is given by extending 𝔼P\mathbb{E}^{P} via the usual extension to small generic extensions (equivalently, 𝔼N[δ0P,)\mathbb{E}^{N}{\upharpoonright}[\delta_{0}^{P},\infty) agrees with 𝔼P[δ0P,)\mathbb{E}^{P}{\upharpoonright}[\delta_{0}^{P},\infty) on the ordinals). (Of course, for some generics, this might not actually yield a premouse, but with gg the generic for adding M|δ0PM|\delta_{0}^{P}, we have (τP)g=M(\tau^{P})_{g}=M.) Note that iMP(τM)=τPi_{MP}(\tau^{M})=\tau^{P}.

Lemma 4.5.

(ug19) holds: for each PP\in\mathscr{F}, cP=ddPc^{P}=d\cap d^{P} is dense in (P,P)(\mathscr{F}^{P},\preceq^{P}) and dense in (,)(\mathscr{F},\preceq), and PcP=cP{\preceq^{P}}{\upharpoonright}c^{P}={\preceq}{\upharpoonright}c^{P}.

Proof.

Let PP\in\mathscr{F}. The fact that PcP=cP{\preceq^{P}}{\upharpoonright}c^{P}={\preceq}{\upharpoonright}c^{P} is by Lemma 4.2 part 6. So let QPQ\in\mathscr{F}^{P} and RR\in\mathscr{F}. We must find some SPS\in\mathscr{F}^{P}\cap\mathscr{F} with Q,RSQ,R\preceq S. Let σ\sigma be some 𝔹δ0PP\mathbb{B}_{\delta_{0}^{P}}^{P}-name such that σg=R\sigma_{g}=R. Let η\eta be a strong cutpoint of PP such that δ0P<η\delta_{0}^{P}<\eta and Q|δ0Q,σP|ηQ|\delta_{0}^{Q},\sigma\in P|\eta. Let p1𝔹δ0PPp_{1}\in\mathbb{B}_{\delta_{0}^{P}}^{P} be the Boolean value of the statement “τP\tau^{P} is an MswswM_{\mathrm{swsw}}-like premouse and στP\sigma\in\mathscr{F}^{\tau^{P}}”. Then working in PP, we can form a tree 𝒯\mathcal{T} on PP by Boolean-valued comparison of P,QP,Q and all interpretations of σ\sigma below p1p_{1}, with 𝔼P\mathbb{E}^{P}-genericity and Boolean-valued τP\tau^{P}-genericity iteration folded in, and using the short tree strategies to iterate. (The Boolean-valued genericity iteration means that we use extenders EE under the usual circumstances as for genericity iteration, and given that there is some 𝔹δ0PP\mathbb{B}_{\delta_{0}^{P}}^{P} condition forcing that EE induces an axiom false for τP\tau^{P}.) For each limit λ(η+)P\lambda\leq(\eta^{+})^{P}, if M(𝒯λ)M(\mathcal{T}{\upharpoonright}\lambda) is not a Q-structure for itself then δ(𝒯λ)=λ\delta(\mathcal{T}{\upharpoonright}\lambda)=\lambda and 𝒯λ\mathcal{T}{\upharpoonright}\lambda is definable from parameters over P|λP|\lambda, because (i) the segments of τP\tau^{P} are determined level-by-level by 𝔼P\mathbb{E}^{P} above δ0P\delta_{0}^{P}, and (ii) for all limits ξ<λ\xi<\lambda, the Q-structures guiding branch choice at stage ξ\xi do not overlap δ(𝒯ξ)\delta(\mathcal{T}{\upharpoonright}\xi), and (iii) the Q-structures QξQ_{\xi} of all trees at stage ξ\xi are identical, and hence QξM(𝒯λ)Q_{\xi}\triangleleft M(\mathcal{T}{\upharpoonright}\lambda); this means that we can use P-construction to compute Q-structures, and obtain an iterate in P\mathscr{F}\cap\mathscr{F}^{P}. (For (ii), suppose ξ\xi is least such that a Q-structure overlaps δ(𝒯ξ)\delta(\mathcal{T}{\upharpoonright}\xi). Then there are fatal drops passed before stage ξ\xi. This has to originally arise from a disagreement between the extender sequences of some projecting structures, as opposed to extenders used for genericity iteration purposes (as the latter are only used when they are sufficiently total; cf. the process in [20]). But then we can find some mutual generics witnessing this disagreement, and because the short tree strategies extend to generic extensions (because τP\tau^{P} is forced MswswM_{\mathrm{swsw}}-like), and given the fatal drop, these strategies suffice to complete the comparison between the conflicting projecting structures in the generic extension, which leads to the usual contradiction. Because QξQ_{\xi} does not overlap δ(𝒯ξ)\delta(\mathcal{T}{\upharpoonright}\xi), note that no extenders in 𝔼+Qξ\mathbb{E}_{+}^{Q_{\xi}} of length >δ(𝒯ξ)>\delta(\mathcal{T}{\upharpoonright}\xi) will be used for genericity iteration purposes.) ∎

4.3.2 The internal direct limit system 𝒟\mathscr{D}

Definition 4.6.

Work in MM. Given PP\in{\mathscr{F}} and s[OR]<ω\{}s\in[\mathrm{OR}]^{<\omega}\backslash\{\emptyset\}, say PP is weakly ss-iterable iff for all QQ\in{\mathscr{F}} with PQP\preceq Q, letting 𝒯=𝒯PQ,sh\mathcal{T}=\mathcal{T}_{PQ,\mathrm{sh}}, there is λOR\lambda\in\mathrm{OR} such that Coll(ω,λ)\mathrm{Coll}(\omega,\lambda) forces the existence of a 𝒯\mathcal{T}-cofinal branch bb such that

ib𝒯(s)=s and ib𝒯(P|max(s))=Q|max(s)\displaystyle i^{\mathcal{T}}_{b}(s)=s\mbox{ and }i^{\mathcal{T}}_{b}(P|\max(s))=Q|\max(s) (10)

(in particular, ss is in the wellfounded part of Mb𝒯M^{\mathcal{T}}_{b}). We say that PP is ss-iterable iff every QQ\in{\mathscr{F}} with PQP\preceq Q is weakly ss-iterable.

Given an ss-iterable PP, define

γsP=sup(HullP|max(s)(s)δ0P),\gamma^{P}_{s}=\sup(\mathrm{Hull}^{P|\max(s)}(s^{-})\cap\delta_{0}^{P}),
HsP=HullP|max(s)(γsPs).H^{P}_{s}=\mathrm{Hull}^{P|\max(s)}(\gamma^{P}_{s}\cup s^{-}).

(Note that the hulls here are uncollapsed. Recall that P|max(s)=(P||max(s))pvP|\max(s)=(P||\max(s))^{\mathrm{pv}} is passive by definition.) Given also a tt-iterable QQ with sts\subseteq t and PQP\preceq Q, define

πPs,Qt:HsPHtQ\pi_{Ps,Qt}:H^{P}_{s}\to H^{Q}_{t}

as the common restriction of iteration maps ib𝒯i^{\mathcal{T}}_{b} for bb witnessing the weak ss-iterability requirement (10). 242424Notice that πPs,Qt\pi_{Ps,Qt} does not depend on tt, because πPs,Qt\pi_{Ps,Qt} and πPs,Qs\pi_{Ps,Qs} have the same graph. In [8], the notation for the analogous map, πPQs\pi_{PQ}^{s}, does not mention tt. (Those restrictions agree pairwise by the Zipper Lemma.) Say that PP is strongly ss-iterable iff PP is ss-iterable and whenever Q,RQ,R\in{\mathscr{F}} and PQRP\preceq Q\preceq R (hence PRP\preceq R), then

πPs,Rs=πQs,RsπPs,Qs.\pi_{Ps,Rs}=\pi_{Qs,Rs}\circ\pi_{Ps,Qs}.

Let +={(P,s)|P and P is strongly s-iterable}\mathscr{F}^{+}=\{(P,s)\bigm{|}P\in\mathscr{F}\text{ and }P\text{ is strongly }s\text{-iterable}\}, and similarly let d+={(P|δ0P,s)|(P,s)+}d^{+}=\{(P|\delta_{0}^{P},s)\bigm{|}(P,s)\in\mathscr{F}^{+}\}. The order \preceq on d+d^{+} is now determined by (ug8): for (P¯,s),(Q¯,t)d+(\bar{P},s),(\bar{Q},t)\in d^{+}, we have (P¯,s)(Q¯,t)(\bar{P},s)\preceq(\bar{Q},t) iff P¯Q¯\bar{P}\preceq\bar{Q} and sts\subseteq t. Define the order \preceq on +\mathscr{F}^{+} in the same manner. Clearly

(P,s)(Q,t)(R,u)πPs,Ru=πQt,RuπPs,Qt.(P,s)\preceq(Q,t)\preceq(R,u)\implies\pi_{Ps,Ru}=\pi_{Qt,Ru}\circ\pi_{Ps,Qt}.

Define the system 𝒟=(HsP,HtQ,πPs,Qt:(P,s)(Q,t)+)\mathscr{D}=(H^{P}_{s},H^{Q}_{t},\pi_{Ps,Qt}\colon(P,s)\preceq(Q,t)\in\mathscr{F}^{+}).

Given PP\in\mathscr{F} and s[OR]<ωs\in[\mathrm{OR}]^{<\omega}, recall that ss is PP-stable iff πPQ(s)=s\pi_{PQ}(s)=s for every QQ\in\mathscr{F} with PQP\preceq Q.

Remark 4.6.

Even though it is superfluous, we note that ss-iterability actually implies strong ss-iterability. This follows from calculations in [15]. For let 𝒯=𝒯PQ,sh\mathcal{T}=\mathcal{T}_{PQ,\mathrm{sh}}, 𝒰=𝒰QR,sh\mathcal{U}=\mathcal{U}_{QR,\mathrm{sh}} and 𝒳=𝒳PR,sh\mathcal{X}=\mathcal{X}_{PR,\mathrm{sh}}. Say that a 𝒯\mathcal{T}-cofinal branch is 𝒯\mathcal{T}-good iff Mb𝒯M^{\mathcal{T}}_{b} is δ(𝒯)+1\delta(\mathcal{T})+1-wellfounded and ib𝒯(δ0P)=δ(𝒯)i^{\mathcal{T}}_{b}(\delta_{0}^{P})=\delta(\mathcal{T}); likewise for the other trees. Then the 𝒳\mathcal{X}-good branches dd correspond exactly to pairs (b,c)(b,c) such that bb is 𝒯\mathcal{T}-good and cc is 𝒰\mathcal{U}-good; and moreover, the corresponding iteration maps δ0P{\upharpoonright}\delta_{0}^{P} then commute (see [15, ***Theorem 10.8]). Let bb be 𝒯\mathcal{T}-good and witness weak ss-iterability. Let 𝒯\mathcal{T}^{\prime} be the 0-maximal tree on P|max(s)P|\max(s) given by 𝒯\mathcal{T}. So Mb𝒯=Ult0(P|max(s),Eb𝒯)M^{\mathcal{T}^{\prime}}_{b}=\mathrm{Ult}_{0}(P|\max(s),E^{\mathcal{T}}_{b}), where Eb𝒯E^{\mathcal{T}}_{b} is the branch extender. By a condensation argument due to J. Steel, Mb𝒯Mb𝒯M^{\mathcal{T}^{\prime}}_{b}\trianglelefteq M^{\mathcal{T}}_{b}, and since ib𝒯(max(s))=max(s)i^{\mathcal{T}}_{b}(\max(s))=\max(s), clearly OR(Mb𝒯)=max(s)\mathrm{OR}(M^{\mathcal{T}^{\prime}}_{b})=\max(s), so Mb𝒯=Q|max(s)M^{\mathcal{T}^{\prime}}_{b}=Q|\max(s), and similarly ib𝒯(s)=si^{\mathcal{T}^{\prime}}_{b}(s^{-})=s^{-}. Likewise for cc being 𝒰\mathcal{U}-good and witnessing weak ss-iterability, and 0-maximal tree 𝒰\mathcal{U}^{\prime} on Q|max(s)Q|\max(s). Let d=db,cd=d_{b,c} be the corresponding branch, and 𝒳\mathcal{X}^{\prime} the 0-maximal tree on P|max(s)P|\max(s). Then we get Md𝒳=Mc𝒰=R|max(s)M^{\mathcal{X}^{\prime}}_{d}=M^{\mathcal{U}^{\prime}}_{c}=R|\max(s), and id𝒳(s)=ic𝒰(ib𝒯(s))=si^{\mathcal{X}^{\prime}}_{d}(s^{-})=i^{\mathcal{U}^{\prime}}_{c}(i^{\mathcal{T}^{\prime}}_{b}(s^{-}))=s^{-}, and commutativity in general. But note that these embeddings agree with the covering direct limit maps (consider the natural factor map Mb𝒯Mb𝒯|max(s)M^{\mathcal{T}^{\prime}}_{b}\to M^{\mathcal{T}}_{b}|\max(s)), and therefore we get strong ss-iterability.

The following is proved by the usual arguments (recall that since ext\mathcal{M}_{\infty}^{\mathrm{ext}} is wellfounded, for all s[OR]<ωs\in[\mathrm{OR}]^{<\omega}, there is PP\in\mathscr{F} such that ss is PP-stable):

Lemma 4.6.

We have:

  1. (a)

    if PP\in{\mathscr{F}} and s[OR]<ω\{}s\in[\mathrm{OR}]^{<\omega}\backslash\{\emptyset\} and ss is PP-stable, then (P,s)+(P,s)\in\mathscr{F}^{+} and (P,s)(P,s) is true (see Definition 2.1).

  2. (b)

    (+,)(\mathscr{F}^{+},\preceq) is directed – for (P,s)(P,s), (Q,t)+(Q,t)\in\mathscr{F}^{+} there is (R,u)+(R,u)\in\mathscr{F}^{+} with (P,s)(R,u)(P,s)\preceq(R,u) and (Q,t)(R,u)(Q,t)\preceq(R,u) (note u=stu=s\cup t suffices).

  3. (c)

    Therefore properties (ug7), (ug8), (ug9), (ug10), (ug16) hold.

The following properties follow directly from the definitions; note that strong ss-iterability is used for (ug15):

Lemma 4.6.

𝒟\mathscr{D} is lightface MM-definable, and properties (ug11), (ug12), (ug13), (ug14), (ug15) hold.

For the following, recall P\mathscr{I}^{P} from Definition 3.4:

Lemma 4.6.

For each PP\in\mathscr{F}, {α}\{\alpha\} is PP-stable for every αM=P\alpha\in\mathscr{I}^{M}=\mathscr{I}^{P}. Therefore property (ug17) holds, as witnessed by some s[M]<ωs\in[\mathscr{I}^{M}]^{<\omega}.

Proof.

The proof is standard, but we give a reminder. By Fact 3, P=HullP(Pδ0P)P=\mathrm{Hull}^{P}(\mathscr{I}^{P}\cup\delta_{0}^{P}). By Lemma 4.1, πMPM=id\pi_{MP}{\upharpoonright}\mathscr{I}^{M}=\mathrm{id}, so P=M\mathscr{I}^{P}=\mathscr{I}^{M}, and we have {α}\{\alpha\}-stability for each αM\alpha\in\mathscr{I}^{M}. Now let xPx\in P. By these facts, we can fix s[M]<ωs\in[\mathscr{I}^{M}]^{<\omega} such that xHullP|max(s)(δ{s})x\in\mathrm{Hull}^{P|\max(s)}(\delta\cup\{s^{-}\}). But we can also arrange that γsP\gamma^{P}_{s} is as large below δ0P\delta_{0}^{P} as desired. It follows we can get xHsPx\in H^{P}_{s}, and by Lemma 4.3.2, this works. ∎

We now have enough properties from §2 to define (working in MM) the direct limit

(,πPs,:(P,s)+)=dirlim𝒟,({\cal M}_{\infty},\pi_{Ps,\infty}\colon(P,s)\in\mathscr{F}^{+})=\mathrm{dirlim}\ \mathscr{D}, (11)

and the *-map, and Lemmas 2 and 2 hold, so in particular, χ:ext\chi:{\cal M}_{\infty}\to{\cal M}_{\infty}^{\mathrm{ext}} is the identity and =ext\mathcal{M}_{\infty}=\mathcal{M}_{\infty}^{\mathrm{ext}}. Property (ug20) is straightforward (the main point is that if PP\in\mathscr{F} and Q¯dPd\bar{Q}\in d^{P}\cap d then 𝒫Q¯P=𝒫P(Q¯)=𝒫M(Q¯)\mathcal{P}_{\bar{Q}}^{P}=\mathscr{P}^{P}(\bar{Q})=\mathscr{P}^{M}(\bar{Q}), because 𝔼P,𝔼M\mathbb{E}^{P},\mathbb{E}^{M} agree above δ0P\delta_{0}^{P}). For property (ug21), given ss, note that any PP\in\mathscr{F} such that ss is PP-stable works.

So far we have verified (ug1)(ug21). For the remaining properties we use δ=δ0M\delta=\delta_{0}^{M} and 𝔹=𝔹δ0M\mathbb{B}=\mathbb{B}_{\delta_{0}}^{M} (the δ0\delta_{0}-generator extender algebra of MM at δ0\delta_{0}). This immediately secures (ug22). Recall we defined τP\tau^{P} in Definition 4.5, and δ=iM(δ0)=δ0\delta_{\infty}=i_{M\infty}(\delta_{0})=\delta_{0}^{\mathcal{M}_{\infty}}.

Lemma 4.6.

We have:

  1. 1.

    For each MM-stable αOR\alpha\in\mathrm{OR} and each PP\in\mathscr{F}, letting τPα=iMP(τMα)\tau^{P}{\upharpoonright}\alpha=i_{MP}(\tau^{M}{\upharpoonright}\alpha) and gg be the PP-generic filter for 𝔹δ0PP\mathbb{B}_{\delta_{0}^{P}}^{P} given by M|δ0PM|\delta_{0}^{P}, then (τPα)g=M|α(\tau^{P}{\upharpoonright}\alpha)_{g}=M|\alpha. Moreover, M=^P[g]=^P[M|δ0P]M\ \widehat{=}\ P[g]\ \widehat{=}\ P[M|\delta_{0}^{P}].

  2. 2.

    Property (ug24) holds.

  3. 3.

    κ0M\kappa_{0}^{M} is the least measurable cardinal of {{\cal M}_{\infty}}.

  4. 4.

    κ0+M=δ\kappa_{0}^{+M}=\delta_{\infty}.

Proof.

Part 1 is already clear, and part 2 is an easy consequence. Part 3 is also clear. Part 4 is by the proof of [8, Lemma 2.7(b)].252525Actually, an easy cardinality calculation shows that δκ0+M\delta_{\infty}\leq\kappa_{0}^{+M}, and we will show directly later that δ\delta_{\infty} is Woodin in 𝒱1\mathscr{V}_{1} and 𝒱1\mathscr{V}_{1} is a ground of MM via a forcing which has the δ\delta_{\infty}-cc in 𝒱\mathscr{V}, and hence δ\delta_{\infty} is regular in MM, so δ=κ0+M\delta_{\infty}=\kappa_{0}^{+M}, without using the proof of [8, Lemma 2.7(b)].

Lemma 4.6.

Let E𝔼ME\in\mathbb{E}^{M} be MM-total with crit(E)=κ0{\rm crit}(E)=\kappa_{0} and let 𝒩=iE()\mathcal{N}=i_{E}(\mathcal{M}_{\infty}). We have:

  1. 1.

    =M\mathscr{I}^{\mathcal{M}_{\infty}}=\mathscr{I}^{M}, and so iMM=id=Mi_{M\mathcal{M}_{\infty}}{\upharpoonright}\mathscr{I}^{M}=\mathrm{id}=*{\upharpoonright}\mathscr{I}^{M}.

  2. 2.

    𝒩\mathcal{N} is a δ0𝒩\delta_{0}^{\mathcal{N}}-sound Σ\Sigma_{\mathcal{M}_{\infty}}-iterate of \mathcal{M}_{\infty}.

  3. 3.

    𝒩=Ult(M,E)\mathscr{I}^{\mathcal{N}}=\mathscr{I}^{\mathrm{Ult}(M,E)}.

  4. 4.

    iEM:𝒩i^{M}_{E}{\upharpoonright}\mathcal{M}_{\infty}:\mathcal{M}_{\infty}\to\mathcal{N} is the Σ\Sigma_{\mathcal{M}_{\infty}}-iteration map.

Proof.

We delay the proof until Lemma 4.11, which is more general.262626It is fine to read 4.114.11 at this point, which covers what is needed.

Lemma 4.6.

The following are true.

  1. (a)

    The restriction of Σ\Sigma_{{{\cal M}_{\infty}}} to trees in MM and based on |δ{{\cal M}_{\infty}}|\delta_{\infty}, is lightface definable over MM.

  2. (b)

    Let λOR\lambda\in\mathrm{OR} and gg be in some generic extension of VV, and be {\mathbb{P}}-generic over MM for some M|λ{\mathbb{P}}\in M|\lambda. Let Σ\Sigma^{\prime}_{\mathcal{M}_{\infty}} be the restriction of Σ\Sigma_{{{\cal M}_{\infty}}} to trees in M[g]M[g] and based on |δ{{\cal M}_{\infty}}|\delta_{\infty}. Then Σ\Sigma^{\prime}_{\mathcal{M}_{\infty}} is definable over the universe of M[g]M[g] from the parameter x=M|(λ+ω)Mx=M|(\lambda^{+\omega})^{M}, uniformly in λ\lambda.272727If gVg\notin V, we are extending Σ\Sigma and Σstk\Sigma^{\mathrm{stk}} canonically to V[g]V[g] as in Fact 3(Σ\Sigma1).

Proof.

The short tree strategy for \mathcal{M}_{\infty} is computed just like for MM, and the definability is like in 4.2. The computation of branches at maximal stages is just like [8, Lemma 2.9(a),(b)], supplemented by Lemmas 3 and 4.3.2, and for the definability, use the definability of 𝔼M\mathbb{E}^{M} from xx in M[g]M[g] (see 4.2). Here is a sketch for g=g=\emptyset. Let E𝔼ME\in\mathbb{E}^{M} be MM-total, with crit(E)=κ0{\rm crit}(E)=\kappa_{0} and 𝒯M|λ(E)\mathcal{T}\in M|\lambda(E) a maximal tree on |δ\mathcal{M}_{\infty}|\delta_{\infty}. Let U=Ult(M,E)U=\mathrm{Ult}(M,E). By Lemma 4.3.2, 𝒩=iE()\mathcal{N}=i_{E}(\mathcal{M}_{\infty}) is a δ0𝒩\delta_{0}^{\mathcal{N}}-sound iterate of \mathcal{M}_{\infty} and iEM:𝒩i^{M}_{E}{\upharpoonright}\mathcal{M}_{\infty}:\mathcal{M}_{\infty}\to\mathcal{N} is the correct iteration map. Now let P=M(𝒯)P=M(\mathcal{T}). Then UU\vDashPP is a maximal Σsh\Sigma_{\mathrm{sh}}-iterate of M|δ0MM|\delta_{0}^{M}”, and therefore UU\vDash𝒩|δ0𝒩\mathcal{N}|\delta_{0}^{\mathcal{N}} is a maximal ΣP,sh\Sigma_{P,\mathrm{sh}}-iterate of PP”, considering statements satisfied by MM regarding such iterates. But UU is correct about this. Let 𝒮\mathcal{S} be the tree on PP leading to 𝒩|δ0𝒩\mathcal{N}|\delta_{0}^{\mathcal{N}}. Working in a generic extension of MM, find a 𝒯\mathcal{T}-cofinal branch bb and 𝒮\mathcal{S}-cofinal branch cc such that iEM(|δ)=ic𝒮ib𝒯i^{M}_{E}{\upharpoonright}(\mathcal{M}_{\infty}|\delta_{\infty})=i^{\mathcal{S}}_{c}\circ i^{\mathcal{T}}_{b}, and then verify that b=Σ(𝒯)b=\Sigma_{\mathcal{M}_{\infty}}(\mathcal{T}), using Lemma 3.282828There is an alternate proof which uses properties of normalization and is more direct. Let 𝒲^d\mathcal{W}\ \widehat{\ }\ d be the tree leading from \mathcal{M}_{\infty} to 𝒩\mathcal{N} (with final branch dd). We have 𝒲,dM\mathcal{W},d\in M by Lemma 4.3.2. But 𝒲\mathcal{W} (of limit length) is the normalization of the stack (𝒯,𝒮)(\mathcal{T},\mathcal{S}) (the trees in the first given proof). Letting b,cb,c be the correct branches through 𝒯,𝒮M\mathcal{T},\mathcal{S}\in M, dd determines (together with 𝒯,𝒮,𝒲\mathcal{T},\mathcal{S},\mathcal{W}) the pair (b,c)(b,c) uniquely via normalization.

Remark 4.6.

The strategy Σ\Sigma_{\mathcal{M}_{\infty}} also has minimal hull condensation, so we get the canonical stacks strategy (Σ)stk(\Sigma_{\mathcal{M}_{\infty}})^{\mathrm{stk}} induced by Σ\Sigma_{\mathcal{M}_{\infty}}, which agrees with the tail strategy Γ=(Σstk)\Gamma_{\mathcal{M}_{\infty}}=(\Sigma^{\mathrm{stk}})_{\mathcal{M}_{\infty}}, by Fact 3. It is easily definable from Σ\Sigma_{\mathcal{M}_{\infty}}, and for stacks based on |δ\mathcal{M}_{\infty}|\delta_{\infty}, we only need the normal strategy for trees based there. So M[g]M[g] can also compute the restriction of (Σ)stk=Γ(\Sigma_{\mathcal{M}_{\infty}})^{\mathrm{stk}}=\Gamma_{\mathcal{M}_{\infty}} to stacks based on |δ\mathcal{M}_{\infty}|\delta_{\infty}, which are in M[g]M[g].

Note that we have now verified all of the requirements for uniform grounds, excluding (ug23). This will be established later in Lemma 4.6.

4.4 The first Varsovian model as []\mathcal{M}_{\infty}[*]

In §2 we defined the elementary maps π:\pi_{\infty}:\mathcal{M}_{\infty}\to\mathcal{M}_{\infty}^{\mathcal{M}_{\infty}} and π+:𝒱𝒱\pi_{\infty}^{+}:\mathscr{V}\to\mathscr{V}^{\mathcal{M}_{\infty}}. We now want to show that \mathcal{M}_{\infty}^{\mathcal{M}_{\infty}} is an iterate of \mathcal{M}_{\infty} and π\pi_{\infty} is a correct iteration map. We also want to generalize this to other iterates of MM, but in general one must be a little careful.

Definition 4.7.

Given an MswswM_{\mathrm{swsw}}-like premouse NN, let 𝒟N\mathscr{D}^{N} and N\mathcal{M}_{\infty}^{N} be defined over NN just as how 𝒟\mathscr{D}, \mathcal{M}_{\infty} are defined over MM. If NN is a correct iterate of MswswM_{\mathrm{swsw}}, also define (ext)N(\mathcal{M}_{\infty}^{\mathrm{ext}})_{N} (the external direct limit) relative to NN, as for MM: given a maximal tree 𝒯𝕌N\mathcal{T}\in\mathbb{U}^{N} (considered as a tree on NN), let b=ΣN(𝒯)b=\Sigma_{N}(\mathcal{T}) and M𝒯=Mb𝒯M_{\mathcal{T}}=M^{\mathcal{T}}_{b}, and let (ext)N(\mathcal{M}_{\infty}^{\mathrm{ext}})_{N} be the direct limit of these models M𝒯M_{\mathcal{T}} under the iteration maps (by Lemma 4.2, and in particular its part 6, these trees 𝒯\mathcal{T} are indeed according to ΣN\Sigma_{N}).292929These models can in general be distinct from the models 𝒫M(𝒯)N\mathcal{P}^{N}_{M(\mathcal{T})} computed by NN via P-construction, which is why the care mentioned above is needed. If in fact M𝒯=𝒫M(𝒯)NM_{\mathcal{T}}=\mathscr{P}^{N}_{M(\mathcal{T})} (the model indexed by M(𝒯)M(\mathcal{T}) in the covering system 𝒟N\mathscr{D}^{N}) for each such 𝒯\mathcal{T}, then define χN:N(ext)N\chi_{N}:\mathcal{M}_{\infty}^{N}\to(\mathcal{M}_{\infty}^{\mathrm{ext}})_{N} as in §2.

Lemma 4.7.

Let NN be a δ0N\delta_{0}^{N}-sound, non-dropping correct iterate of MM. Then M𝒯=𝒫N(M(𝒯))M_{\mathcal{T}}=\mathscr{P}^{N}(M(\mathcal{T})) for each 𝒯𝕌N\mathcal{T}\in\mathbb{U}^{N}, N=(ext)N\mathcal{M}_{\infty}^{N}=(\mathcal{M}_{\infty}^{\mathrm{ext}})_{N} and χN=id\chi^{N}=\mathrm{id}, and N\mathcal{M}_{\infty}^{N} is a δ0N\delta_{0}^{\mathcal{M}_{\infty}^{N}}-sound, non-dropping correct iterate of both MM and NN.

Proof.

The proof is just like for MM, using the δ0N\delta_{0}^{N}-soundness of NN (and resulting δ0N\delta_{0}^{\mathcal{M}_{\infty}^{N}}-soundness of N\mathcal{M}_{\infty}^{N}) as a substitute for the fact that M=Hull1M(M)M=\mathrm{Hull}_{1}^{M}(\mathscr{I}^{M}), to see that the models of 𝒟N\mathscr{D}^{N} really are iterates of NN. ∎

We will see later, however, that if NN is a Σ\Sigma-iterate of MM which is κ0N\kappa_{0}^{N}-sound but non-δ0N\delta_{0}^{N}-sound, then (ext)NN(\mathcal{M}^{\mathrm{ext}}_{\infty})_{N}\neq\mathcal{M}_{\infty}^{N}, so we need a little more care in this case.

By the lemma, =(ext)\mathcal{M}_{\infty}^{\mathcal{M}_{\infty}}=(\mathcal{M}_{\infty}^{\mathrm{ext}})_{\mathcal{M}_{\infty}} is an iterate of \mathcal{M}_{\infty}. Now recall that π:\pi_{\infty}:\mathcal{M}_{\infty}\to\mathcal{M}_{\infty}^{\mathcal{M}_{\infty}} is the union of all πpt,(πps,)\pi_{pt,\infty}(\pi_{ps,\infty}) for embedding-good tuples (p,s,t)(p,s,t), and that π(x)=x\pi_{\infty}(x)=x^{*}, and if ρOR\rho\in\mathrm{OR} then

π(ρ)=ρ=min({πN(ρ):N})=πPs,(ρ),\displaystyle\pi_{\infty}(\rho)=\rho^{*}=\min(\{\pi_{N\infty}(\rho)\colon N\in\mathscr{F}\})=\pi_{Ps,\infty}(\rho), (12)

where (P,s)+(P,s)\in\mathscr{F}^{+} is any pair with ρs\rho\in s and ρ<max(s)\rho<\max(s). As usual we have:

Lemma 4.7.

π:\pi_{\infty}:\mathcal{M}_{\infty}\to\mathcal{M}_{\infty}^{\mathcal{M}_{\infty}} is the iteration map according to Σ\Sigma_{\mathcal{M}_{\infty}}.

Similarly, let NN be as in Lemma 4.4 (so N\mathcal{M}_{\infty}^{N} a δ0N\delta_{0}^{\mathcal{M}_{\infty}^{N}}-sound correct iterate, and likewise N\mathcal{M}_{\infty}^{\mathcal{M}_{\infty}^{N}}). Let πN=iMN(π)\pi_{\infty}^{N}=i_{MN}(\pi_{\infty}). Then πN\pi_{\infty}^{N} is the iteration map NN\mathcal{M}_{\infty}^{N}\to\mathcal{M}_{\infty}^{\mathcal{M}_{\infty}^{N}} according to ΣN\Sigma_{\mathcal{M}_{\infty}^{N}}.

Write N=N=\mathcal{M}_{\infty}. As in [8], since the tree from NN to N\mathcal{M}_{\infty}^{N} is based on N|δ0NN|\delta_{0}^{N}, π:NN\pi_{\infty}:N\to\mathcal{M}_{\infty}^{N} is determined by π=π(N|δ0N)\pi=\pi_{\infty}{\upharpoonright}(N|\delta_{0}^{N}) (as π\pi_{\infty} is the ultrapower map by the extender derived from π\pi), which is in turn determined by the pair (πδ0N,N|δ0N)(\pi_{\infty}{\upharpoonright}\delta_{0}^{N},\mathcal{M}_{\infty}^{N}|\delta_{0}^{\mathcal{M}_{\infty}^{N}}). Since N|δ0NN\mathcal{M}_{\infty}^{N}|\delta_{0}^{\mathcal{M}_{\infty}^{N}}\in N, it follows that

L[,]=L[,π]=L[,πδ].L[\mathcal{M}_{\infty},*]=L[\mathcal{M}_{\infty},\pi_{\infty}]=L[\mathcal{M}_{\infty},\pi_{\infty}{\upharpoonright}\delta_{\infty}].

Moreover, π\pi_{\infty} is definable over this universe from the predicate N=N=\mathcal{M}_{\infty} (given NN, we can recover N\mathcal{M}_{\infty}^{N} and the maximal tree 𝒯\mathcal{T} leading from NN to N\mathcal{M}_{\infty}^{N}, but in L[N,π]L[N,\pi_{\infty}], there is a unique 𝒯\mathcal{T}-cofinal branch bb with Mb𝒯=NM^{\mathcal{T}}_{b}=\mathcal{M}_{\infty}^{N}; but ib𝒯=πi^{\mathcal{T}}_{b}=\pi_{\infty}).

Definition 4.8.

The first Varsovian model of MM (cf. (4)) is the structure

[]=(L[,],,);\displaystyle\mathcal{M}_{\infty}[*]=(L[\mathcal{M}_{\infty},*],\mathcal{M}_{\infty},*); (13)

that is, []\mathcal{M}_{\infty}[*] has universe L[,]L[\mathcal{M}_{\infty},*] and predicates \mathcal{M}_{\infty} and *.

(By the preceding comments, it would suffice to just have the predicate \mathcal{M}_{\infty}, but we include * for convenience.) Later we will introduce a second presentation 𝒱1\mathscr{V}_{1} of []\mathcal{M}_{\infty}[*], constructed from a different predicate (but giving the same universe). However, the two predicates will be inter-definable over that universe.

Before we introduce that presentation, we first develop some properties of []\mathcal{M}_{\infty}[*] using the presentation above. We may at times blur the distinction between the universe L[,]L[\mathcal{M}_{\infty},*] and the structure []\mathcal{M}_{\infty}[*], but for definability issues over []\mathcal{M}_{\infty}[*], we can by default use (,)(\mathcal{M}_{\infty},*) as a predicate.

4.5 HODM[G]\mathrm{HOD}^{M[G]}_{\mathscr{E}}

Up until this point, the paper has covered material which is mostly a direct adaptation from that of [8]. But in this section we begin to see some new features. In [8] it is shown that the Varsovian model has universe that of HODMsw[g]\mathrm{HOD}^{{M_{\rm sw}}[g]}, where gColl(ω,<κ)g\subseteq\mathrm{Coll}(\omega,{<\kappa}) is Msw{M_{\rm sw}}-generic, for κ\kappa the strong cardinal of Msw{M_{\rm sw}}. In this section we will establish an analogue of this fact.

Let GG be (M,Coll(ω,<κ0))(M,\mathrm{Coll}(\omega,{<\kappa_{0}}))-generic. Note that if HODM[G]\mathrm{HOD}^{M[G]} is the universe of []\mathcal{M}_{\infty}[*], then it would follow as in [8] that []\mathcal{M}_{\infty}[*] is closed under maximal branches according to Σ\Sigma_{\mathcal{M}_{\infty}} (those branches are in MM by 4.3.2, and have length of uncountable cofinality in M[G]M[G], and hence are unique there). Thus, such a fact is at least useful in verifying that the first Varsovian model can iterate its own least Woodin cardinal, which one would like to prove.

Also, in order to proceed to the next step of the mantle analysis, one might want to consider iteration trees on []\mathcal{M}_{\infty}[*], based on []|δ1M\mathcal{M}_{\infty}[*]|\delta_{1}^{M} (we will show that δ1M\delta_{1}^{M} is Woodin in []\mathcal{M}_{\infty}[*]). But because []\mathcal{M}_{\infty}[*] is built from the somewhat cumbersome combination of \mathcal{M}_{\infty} and *, the nature of its large cardinals above δ0\delta_{0}^{\mathcal{M}_{\infty}} (and so far also below there, though that is resolved by standard methods) is somewhat unclear, as is its fine structure.

Now if we are to expect []\mathcal{M}_{\infty}[*] to be closed under Σ\Sigma_{\mathcal{M}_{\infty}}, a possible goal is to find a presentation of it as a strategy mouse, built from extenders and strategy for Σ\Sigma_{\mathcal{M}_{\infty}}, with a fine structural hierarchy; with this target in mind, we write 𝒱1\mathscr{V}_{1} for the desired model of this form (whatever its eventual presentation might be). The first two authors considered various candidates for such a presentation, with one possibility being a construction by level-by-level correspondence between 𝒱1\mathscr{V}_{1} and MM, via a modified kind of P-construction. This P-construction would result from restricting the extenders of MM to segments of 𝒱1\mathscr{V}_{1}, starting above some point θ\theta not too far above κ0\kappa_{0}. (An early candidate was θ=(κ0+3)M\theta=(\kappa_{0}^{+3})^{M}, but the second and third authors later reduced this to an optimal starting point, which we use.) Of course standard P-constructions build a ground of the outer model, and this feature was expected, via a Bukowsky-style forcing as in [8]. Here we use the forcing 𝕃\mathbb{L} from §2, which was eventually isolated by the second author. But note that a new feature in this P-construction would be that some extenders (those extenders EE with crit(E)=κ0{\rm crit}(E)=\kappa_{0}) overlap the forcing 𝕃\mathbb{L}. This would cause a problem with a standard P-construction (where the base forcing is produced by genericity iteration). But such extenders EE yield strategy information, via the process in the proof of 4.3.2 (whereas those with crit(E)>κ0{\rm crit}(E)>\kappa_{0} would be as usual). So it appears that one might construct 𝒱1\mathscr{V}_{1} with such a P-construction, with extenders EE having crit(E)=κ0{\rm crit}(E)=\kappa_{0} corresponding to strategy information, to be added fine structurally to the relevant segment of 𝒱1\mathscr{V}_{1}. This could then lead to a model closed under Σ\Sigma_{\mathcal{M}_{\infty}} for trees based on δ\delta_{\infty}, as is desired. The model 𝒱1\mathscr{V}_{1} should also inherit iterability for itself, from the iterability of MM, in a manner similar to standard P-constructions.

A first basic question is whether the model 𝒱1\mathscr{V}_{1} constructed as above will end up []\subseteq\mathcal{M}_{\infty}[*]. We now make the key observation which shows that it does. A useful first step is to restrict one’s attention to the action of the extenders on the ordinals; this will be enough for the P-construction. For the purpose of the next lemma, let us write

𝔽>κ0M={(ν,α,β)OR3|ν>κ0M,𝔼νM, and 𝔼νM(α)=β},{\mathbb{F}}^{M}_{>\kappa_{0}}=\{(\nu,\alpha,\beta)\in\mathrm{OR}^{3}\bigm{|}\nu>\kappa_{0}^{M},\ \mathbb{E}_{\nu}^{M}\not=\emptyset,\text{ and }\mathbb{E}_{\nu}^{M}(\alpha)=\beta\}{\rm,} (14)

where, since we are using Jensen indexing, the MM-extender 𝔼νM\mathbb{E}_{\nu}^{M} in (14) is an elementary embedding j:M|μ+M|νM|νj:M|\mu^{+M|\nu}\to M|\nu where μ=crit(𝔼νM)\mu={\rm crit}(\mathbb{E}_{\nu}^{M}), so (𝔽>κ0M)ν=jμ+M|ν(\mathbb{F}^{M}_{>\kappa_{0}})_{\nu}=j{\upharpoonright}\mu^{+M|\nu}.

In the following lemma, recall that for definability over []\mathcal{M}_{\infty}[*], we by default have the predicate (,)(\mathcal{M}_{\infty},*) available for free:

Lemma 4.8.

𝔽>κ0M{\mathbb{F}}^{M}_{>\kappa_{0}} is lightface definable over []\mathcal{M}_{\infty}[*].

Proof.

Let (ν,α,β)OR3(\nu,\alpha,\beta)\in\mathrm{OR}^{3} with ν>κ0\nu>\kappa_{0}. We claim that (ν,α,β)𝔽>κ0M(\nu,\alpha,\beta)\in{\mathbb{F}}^{M}_{>\kappa_{0}} iff

F and F(α)=β where F=F||ν,F\neq\emptyset\text{ and }F(\alpha^{*})=\beta^{*}\text{ where }F=F^{\mathcal{M}_{\infty}||\nu^{*}},

which suffices. This equivalence holds as for every PP\in\mathscr{F}, we have FP||νOR=FM||νORF^{P||\nu}{\upharpoonright}\mathrm{OR}=F^{M||\nu}{\upharpoonright}\mathrm{OR}, since ν>crit(FM||ν)κ0\nu>{\rm crit}(F^{M||\nu})\geq\kappa_{0} and PP results from a P-construction of MM above some point below κ0\kappa_{0}. ∎

One can now proceed directly with the P-construction, using (|κ0+,δ0)(\mathcal{M}_{\infty}|\kappa_{0}^{+\mathcal{M}_{\infty}},*{\upharpoonright}\delta_{0}^{\mathcal{M}_{\infty}}) and 𝔽>κ0M\mathbb{F}^{M}_{>\kappa_{0}} to define it. But we postpone this, and first establish some other characterizations of the universe of []\mathcal{M}_{\infty}[*].

The proof of the preceding lemma can be extended to show that []\mathcal{M}_{\infty}[*] has universe HODM[G]\mathrm{HOD}^{M[G]}_{\mathscr{E}}, for a certain collection \mathscr{E} of premice in M[G]M[G], and GG as above. Thus, we use HOD\mathrm{HOD}_{\mathscr{E}} here in place of the use of HOD\mathrm{HOD} in [8]. We describe how this works next. What follows is slightly related to some methods from [17]; also cf. 4.8.

Definition 4.9.

Let L[𝔼]L[\mathbb{E}] be a premouse, and let μ\mu be a strong cutpoint of L[𝔼]L[\mathbb{E}]. If gg is Col(ω,μ){\rm Col}(\omega,\mu)-generic over L[𝔼]L[\mathbb{E}], then every extender 𝔼ν\mathbb{E}_{\nu} from 𝔼\mathbb{E} with ν>μ\nu>\mu (and hence crit(𝔼ν)>μ{\rm crit}(\mathbb{E}_{\nu})>\mu) lifts canonically to an extender 𝔼νg\mathbb{E}^{g}_{\nu} over (L[𝔼]|ν)[g](L[\mathbb{E}]|\nu)[g]. Let us write 𝔼g=𝔼νgν>μ\mathbb{E}^{g}=\left<\mathbb{E}_{\nu}^{g}\right>_{\nu>\mu}. Then L[𝔼][g]L[\mathbb{E}][g] gets reorganized as a premouse over (L[𝔼]||μ,g)(L[\mathbb{E}]||\mu,g) with extender sequence 𝔼g\mathbb{E}^{g}; so L[𝔼][g]=^L[𝔼g](L[𝔼]||μ,g)L[\mathbb{E}][g]\ \widehat{=}\ L[\mathbb{E}^{g}](L[\mathbb{E}]||\mu,g).

Let L[𝔼0]L[\mathbb{E}_{0}], L[𝔼1]L[\mathbb{E}_{1}] be proper class premice and μOR\mu\in\mathrm{OR}. Write

𝔼0μ𝔼1\mathbb{E}_{0}\sim^{\mu}\mathbb{E}_{1}

iff μ\mu is a strong cutpoint in both L[𝔼0]L[\mathbb{E}_{0}] and L[𝔼1]L[\mathbb{E}_{1}] and there are g0,g1g_{0},g_{1} with gig_{i} being Col(ω,μ){\rm Col}(\omega,\mu)-generic over L[𝔼i]L[\mathbb{E}_{i}] and Lμ+ω[𝔼0][g0]=^Lμ+ω[𝔼1][g1]L_{\mu+\omega}[\mathbb{E}_{0}][g_{0}]\ \widehat{=}\ L_{\mu+\omega}[\mathbb{E}_{1}][g_{1}] and (𝔼0)g0=(𝔼1)g1(\mathbb{E}_{0})^{g_{0}}=(\mathbb{E}_{1})^{g_{1}}. So “𝔼0μ𝔼1\mathbb{E}_{0}\sim^{\mu}\mathbb{E}_{1}” expresses the fact that above μ\mu, 𝔼0\mathbb{E}_{0} and 𝔼1\mathbb{E}_{1} are intertranslatable: for every ν>μ\nu>\mu, (𝔼0)ν=(𝔼1)νg1L[𝔼0]|ν(\mathbb{E}_{0})_{\nu}=(\mathbb{E}_{1})_{\nu}^{g_{1}}\cap L[\mathbb{E}_{0}]|\nu, and vice versa. Write

𝔼0<μ𝔼1\mathbb{E}_{0}\sim^{<\mu}\mathbb{E}_{1}

iff there is some μ¯<μ{\bar{\mu}}<\mu with 𝔼0μ¯𝔼1\mathbb{E}_{0}\sim^{\bar{\mu}}\mathbb{E}_{1}. Both μ\sim^{\mu} and <μ\sim^{<\mu} are equivalence relations.

Let L[𝔼]L[\mathbb{E}] be a proper class premouse, let μ\mu be inaccessible in L[𝔼]L[\mathbb{E}], and let HH be Col(ω,<μ){\rm Col}(\omega,{<\mu})-generic over L[𝔼]L[\mathbb{E}]. We denote by 𝔼L[𝔼][H]\mathscr{E}_{\mathbb{E}}^{L[\mathbb{E}][H]} the collection of all 𝔼\mathbb{E}^{\prime} such that 𝔼|μL[𝔼][H]\mathbb{E}^{\prime}|{\mu}\in L[\mathbb{E}][H] and L[𝔼][H]L[\mathbb{E}][H]\vDash𝔼<μ𝔼\mathbb{E}^{\prime}\sim^{<\mu}\mathbb{E}”.

Remark 4.9.

Note that if 𝔼𝔼L[𝔼][H]\mathbb{E}^{\prime}\in\mathscr{E}_{\mathbb{E}}^{L[\mathbb{E}][H]} then

  1. (i)

    There are μ¯<μ\bar{\mu}<\mu and generics g,gL[𝔼][H]g,g^{\prime}\in L[\mathbb{E}][H] witnessing that 𝔼μ¯𝔼\mathbb{E}^{\prime}\sim^{\bar{\mu}}\mathbb{E}.

  2. (ii)

    𝔼\mathbb{E}^{\prime} is Σ1\Sigma_{1}-definable inside L[𝔼][H]L[\mathbb{E}][H] from the set parameter 𝔼|μ¯\mathbb{E}^{\prime}|{\bar{\mu}} and the class parameter 𝔼\mathbb{E}, uniformly in 𝔼,μ¯\mathbb{E}^{\prime},\bar{\mu}.

  3. (iii)

    There is HH^{\prime} which is Col(ω,<μ){\rm Col}(\omega,{<\mu})-generic over L[𝔼]L[\mathbb{E}^{\prime}], with L[𝔼][H]=^L[𝔼][H]L[\mathbb{E}^{\prime}][H^{\prime}]\ \widehat{=}\ L[\mathbb{E}][H]. For any such HH^{\prime}, we have 𝔼L[𝔼][H]=𝔼L[𝔼][H]\mathscr{E}^{L[\mathbb{E}][H]}_{\mathbb{E}}=\mathscr{E}^{L[\mathbb{E}^{\prime}][H^{\prime}]}_{\mathbb{E}^{\prime}}.

  4. (iv)

    𝔼L[𝔼][H]\mathscr{E}_{\mathbb{E}}^{L[\mathbb{E}][H]} is definable over L[𝔼][H]L[\mathbb{E}][H] from 𝔼,μ\mathbb{E},\mu, uniformly in 𝔼,μ,H\mathbb{E},\mu,H.

  5. (v)

    𝔼L[𝔼][H]\mathscr{E}_{\mathbb{E}}^{L[\mathbb{E}][H]} is definable over L[𝔼][H]L[\mathbb{E}][H] from 𝔼,μ\mathbb{E}^{\prime},\mu, for all 𝔼𝔼L[𝔼][H]\mathbb{E}^{\prime}\in\mathscr{E}^{L[\mathbb{E}][H]}_{\mathbb{E}}, uniformly in 𝔼,μ,H,𝔼\mathbb{E},\mu,H,\mathbb{E}^{\prime}.

Fix now GCol(ω,<κ0)G\subseteq{\rm Col}(\omega,<\kappa_{0}) which is MM-generic. We write =L[𝔼M][G]\mathscr{E}=\mathscr{E}^{L[\mathbb{E}^{M}][G]}.

The following is now immediate.

Lemma 4.9.

If N=L[𝔼]N=L[\mathbb{E}^{\prime}]\in\mathscr{F}, then there is GG^{\prime} which is Col(ω,<κ0){\rm Col}(\omega,{<\kappa_{0}})-generic over NN such that N[G]=^M[G]N[G^{\prime}]\ \widehat{=}\ M[G], and for any such GG^{\prime}, we have 𝔼L[𝔼][G]=\mathscr{E}_{\mathbb{E}^{\prime}}^{L[\mathbb{E}^{\prime}][G^{\prime}]}=\mathscr{E}.

Theorem 4.9.

We have:

  1. (i)

    []\mathcal{M}_{\infty}[*] (including its predicates) is definable over M[G]M[G] from the parameter \mathscr{E}, and

  2. (ii)

    []\mathcal{M}_{\infty}[*] has universe HODM[G]\mathrm{HOD}_{\mathscr{E}}^{M[G]}.

Remark 4.9.

This leaves the question: is HODM[G]\mathrm{HOD}^{M[G]} the universe of []\mathcal{M}_{\infty}[*]?

Proof.

We first verify (i). Write 𝔼=𝔼M\mathbb{E}=\mathbb{E}^{M}. Say that 𝔼\mathbb{E}^{\prime} is MswswM_{\mathrm{swsw}}-like iff L[𝔼]L[\mathbb{E}^{\prime}] is MswswM_{\mathrm{swsw}}-like. Fix an MswswM_{\mathrm{swsw}}-like 𝔼\mathbb{E}^{\prime}\in\mathscr{E}. We claim that {\cal M}_{\infty} and * are defined over L[𝔼]L[\mathbb{E}^{\prime}] in the same manner as over MM, which suffices. For the systems L[𝔼]\mathscr{F}^{L[\mathbb{E}^{\prime}]} and M\mathscr{F}^{M} have cofinally many points in common, which easily suffices. To see this fact, use a Boolean-valued comparison argument as in the last part of the proof of [8, Claim 2.11] (comparison with simultaneous genericity iteration, against L[𝔼′′]L[\mathbb{E}^{\prime\prime}] for various MswswM_{\mathrm{swsw}}-like 𝔼′′𝔼L[𝔼][G]\mathbb{E}^{\prime\prime}\in\mathscr{E}_{\mathbb{E}^{\prime}}^{L[\mathbb{E}^{\prime}][G^{\prime}]}). Because “MswswM_{\mathrm{swsw}}-like” includes short-tree iterability, etc, we can indeed form this iteration successfully.

Part (ii): By (i), []HODM[G]\mathcal{M}_{\infty}[*]\subseteq\mathrm{HOD}^{M[G]}_{\mathscr{E}}. We now prove the converse. Let AA be a set of ordinals, φ\varphi a formula, αOR\alpha\in\mathrm{OR} such that for every ξOR\xi\in\mathrm{OR},

ξAM[G]φ(ξ,α,).\xi\in A\Longleftrightarrow M[G]\vDash\varphi(\xi,\alpha,\mathscr{E}).

So for every 𝔼\mathbb{E}^{\prime}\in\mathscr{E} and GG^{\prime} with L[𝔼][G]=^M[G]L[\mathbb{E}^{\prime}][G^{\prime}]\ \widehat{=}\ M[G], and every ξOR\xi\in\mathrm{OR}, we have

ξAL[𝔼][G]φ(ξ,α,𝔼L[𝔼][G])\xi\in A\Longleftrightarrow L[\mathbb{E}^{\prime}][G^{\prime}]\vDash\varphi(\xi,\alpha,\mathscr{E}_{\mathbb{E}^{\prime}}^{L[\mathbb{E}^{\prime}][G^{\prime}]})

(since 𝔼L[𝔼][G]=\mathscr{E}^{L[\mathbb{E}^{\prime}][G^{\prime}]}_{\mathbb{E}^{\prime}}=\mathscr{E}, by Remark 4.5).

Given an MswswM_{\mathrm{swsw}}-like 𝔼\mathbb{E}^{\prime}, write ˙L[𝔼]\dot{\mathscr{E}}^{L[\mathbb{E}^{\prime}]} for the natural Coll(ω,<κ0L[𝔼])\mathrm{Coll}(\omega,{<\kappa_{0}^{L[\mathbb{E}^{\prime}]}})-name for 𝔼L[𝔼][G]\mathscr{E}^{L[\mathbb{E}^{\prime}][G^{\prime}]}_{\mathbb{E}^{\prime}} (for GG^{\prime} the Coll(ω,<κ0L[𝔼])\mathrm{Coll}(\omega,{<\kappa_{0}^{L[\mathbb{E}^{\prime}]}})-generic filter; cf. the remarks on the uniform definability of 𝔼L[𝔼][G]\mathscr{E}^{L[\mathbb{E}^{\prime}][G^{\prime}]}_{\mathbb{E}^{\prime}} above).

Let ξOR\xi\in\mathrm{OR}. Pick N=L[𝔼]N=L[\mathbb{E}^{\prime}]\in{\mathscr{F}} with ξ=πN(ξ)\xi^{*}=\pi_{N{\cal M}_{\infty}}(\xi) and α=πN(α)\alpha^{*}=\pi_{N\cal{{\cal M}_{\infty}}}(\alpha), and let GG^{\prime} be as in Lemma 4.5 for NN. Then

ξA\displaystyle\xi\in A \displaystyle\Longleftrightarrow M[G]φ(ξ,α,)\displaystyle M[G]\vDash\varphi(\xi,\alpha,\mathscr{E})
\displaystyle\Longleftrightarrow N[G]φ(ξ,α,𝔼N[G])\displaystyle N[G^{\prime}]\vDash\varphi(\xi,\alpha,\mathscr{E}^{N[G^{\prime}]}_{\mathbb{E}^{\prime}})
\displaystyle\Longleftrightarrow Col(ω,<κ0)Nφ(ξˇ,αˇ,˙N)\displaystyle\Vdash^{N}_{{\rm Col}(\omega,<\kappa_{0})}\varphi({\check{\xi}},{\check{\alpha}},\dot{\mathscr{E}}^{N})
\displaystyle\Longleftrightarrow Col(ω,<κ0)φ(ξˇ,αˇ,˙).\displaystyle\Vdash^{{\cal M}_{\infty}}_{{\rm Col}(\omega,<\kappa_{0}^{{\cal M}_{\infty}})}\varphi({\check{\xi}^{*}},\check{\alpha^{*}},\dot{\mathscr{E}}^{{\cal M}_{\infty}}).

Therefore A[]A\in{\cal M}_{\infty}[*]. ∎

4.6 Uniform grounds

Recall that δ=δ\delta_{\infty}=\delta^{\mathcal{M}_{\infty}} is the least Woodin of \mathcal{M}_{\infty}. The following lemma completes the proof that the first direct limit system for MM provides uniform grounds (§2):

Lemma 4.9.

We have:

  1. (a)

    Vδ[]=VδV_{\delta_{\infty}}^{\mathcal{M}_{\infty}[*]}=V_{\delta_{\infty}}^{{{\cal M}_{\infty}}}.

  2. (b)

    δ\delta_{\infty} is (the least) Woodin in []\mathcal{M}_{\infty}[*].

  3. (c)

    Property (ug23) of uniform grounds holds for 𝒱1,δ\mathscr{V}_{1},\delta_{\infty}; that is, 𝒱1\mathscr{V}_{1}\vDashδ\delta_{\infty} is regular and 𝔹\mathbb{B}_{\infty} is δ\delta_{\infty}-cc”. Moreover, 𝒱1\mathscr{V}_{1}\vDash𝔹\mathbb{B}_{\infty} is a complete Boolean algebra”.

Proof.

(a): The usual considerations show that η*\upharpoonright\eta\in{{\cal M}_{\infty}} for every η<δ\eta<\delta_{\infty}. Combined with the proof of Theorem 4.5, this suffices. (Cf. [8, Claim 2.12 (b)].)

(b): By the proof of [8, Theorem 2.19] or of [19, Claim 13].

(c): Property (ug23) holds because δ\delta_{\infty} is Woodin in []\mathcal{M}_{\infty}[*] and 𝔹\mathbb{B}_{\infty} is the extender algebra. The “moreover” clause follows from this and (a). ∎

So by Theorem 2, []\mathcal{M}_{\infty}[*] is a ground for MM, and in fact as in its proof, there is some MM-stable μOR\mu\in\mathrm{OR} such that M|μM|\mu is ([],𝕃)(\mathcal{M}_{\infty}[*],\mathbb{L})-generic, where 𝕃=𝕃(μ)\mathbb{L}=\mathbb{L}(\mu^{*}), and [][M|μ]=^M\mathcal{M}_{\infty}[*][M|\mu]\ \widehat{=}\ M. We will actually refine this result in Lemma 4.9.

We can immediately deduce the following corollary, which however will be extended in Lemma 4.9:

Corollary 4.9.

For all maximal trees 𝒯[]\mathcal{T}\in\mathcal{M}_{\infty}[*] via Σ\Sigma_{\mathcal{M}_{\infty}}, based on |δ\mathcal{M}_{\infty}|\delta_{\infty}, we have b=Σ(𝒯)[]b=\Sigma_{\mathcal{M}_{\infty}}(\mathcal{T})\in\mathcal{M}_{\infty}[*], and bb is the unique 𝒯\mathcal{T}-cofinal branch in []\mathcal{M}_{\infty}[*].

Proof.

By Lemma 4.3.2, bMb\in M. And by Lemma 4.3.2, δ\delta_{\infty} is regular in MM and in M[G]M[G], whenever GColl(ω,<κ0)G\subseteq\mathrm{Coll}(\omega,{<\kappa_{0}}) is MM-generic. Therefore M[G]M[G] contains no other 𝒯\mathcal{T}-cofinal branch. Since []\mathcal{M}_{\infty}[*] is the universe of HODM[G]\mathrm{HOD}^{M[G]}_{\mathscr{E}} (with notation as in Theorem 4.5), and 𝒯[]\mathcal{T}\in\mathcal{M}_{\infty}[*], it follows that b[]b\in\mathcal{M}_{\infty}[*] also. ∎

4.7 The structure 𝒬\mathcal{Q}

Let U=EνU=E_{\nu}^{{{\cal M}_{\infty}}} be the least total measure on the {{\cal M}_{\infty}}-sequence with critical point κ0\kappa_{0}^{{{\cal M}_{\infty}}}. Fix a natural tree 𝒯𝕌ult(;U){\cal T}\in{\mathbb{U}}^{{\rm ult}({{\cal M}_{\infty}};U)} with δ(𝒯)=κ0+\delta({\cal T})=\kappa_{0}^{+{{\cal M}_{\infty}}} and which makes |κ0+{{\cal M}_{\infty}}|\kappa_{0}^{+{{\cal M}_{\infty}}} generic, after iterating the least measurable out to κ0\kappa_{0}^{\mathcal{M}_{\infty}}. As 𝒯{\cal T} lives on |δ0\mathcal{M}_{\infty}|\delta_{0}^{{{\cal M}_{\infty}}}, we may and shall construe 𝒯{\cal T} as a tree on {{\cal M}_{\infty}} rather than on ult(;U){\rm ult}({{\cal M}_{\infty}};U). If b=Σ(𝒯)b=\Sigma_{{{\cal M}_{\infty}}}({\cal T}), then

𝒫ult(;U)((𝒯))=b𝒯\mathscr{P}^{{\rm ult}({{\cal M}_{\infty}};U)}({\cal M}({\cal T}))={\cal M}_{b}^{\cal T}

and δ(𝒯)=π0,b𝒯(δ0)\delta({\cal T})=\pi_{0,b}^{\cal T}(\delta_{0}^{{{\cal M}_{\infty}}}). Also,

𝒫ult(;U)((𝒯))[|θ0]=ult(;U).\displaystyle\mathscr{P}^{{\rm ult}({{\cal M}_{\infty}};U)}({\cal M}({\cal T}))[{{\cal M}_{\infty}}|\theta_{0}^{{{\cal M}_{\infty}}}]={\rm ult}({{\cal M}_{\infty}};U). (15)

Let us write

ι=π0,b𝒯δ0.\displaystyle\iota=\pi_{0,b}^{\cal T}\upharpoonright\delta_{0}^{{\cal M}_{\infty}}. (16)

By Corollary 4.6, ι[]\iota\in\mathcal{M}_{\infty}[*]. Hence

𝒬=(|κ0+;ι)\displaystyle{\cal Q}=({{\cal M}_{\infty}}|\kappa_{0}^{+{\cal M}_{\infty}};\iota) (17)

is an amenable structure and is an element of []\mathcal{M}_{\infty}[*].

Lemma 4.9 (Soundness of 𝒬{\cal Q}).

𝒬=Hull𝒬(ι){\cal Q}={\rm Hull}^{\cal Q}(\iota).

Proof.

Let

σ:𝒬¯=(M¯;ι¯)X=Hull𝒬(ι)𝒬.\sigma\colon{\bar{\cal Q}}=({\bar{M}};{\bar{\iota}})\cong X={\rm Hull}^{\cal Q}(\iota)\prec{\cal Q}.

As ι={(ξ,η):ξ<δ0η=ι(ξ)}\iota=\{(\xi,\eta)\colon\xi<\delta_{0}^{{{\cal M}_{\infty}}}\wedge\eta=\iota(\xi)\}, δ0X\delta_{0}^{{{\cal M}_{\infty}}}\subset X, so that σδ0=id\sigma\upharpoonright\delta_{0}^{{{\cal M}_{\infty}}}={\rm id} and |δ0M¯{{\cal M}_{\infty}}|\delta_{0}^{{{\cal M}_{\infty}}}\triangleleft{\bar{M}}. Let 𝒯¯{\bar{\cal T}} be defined over M¯{\bar{M}} as 𝒯{\cal T} was defined over |θ0{{\cal M}_{\infty}}|\theta_{0}^{{{\cal M}_{\infty}}}. The tree T¯{\bar{T}} is on M¯{\bar{M}} which lives on |δ0{{\cal M}_{\infty}}|\delta_{0}^{{{\cal M}_{\infty}}}, but we may and shall construe T¯{\bar{T}} as a tree on {{\cal M}_{\infty}}, and as such 𝒯¯{\bar{\cal T}} is according to Σ\Sigma_{{{\cal M}_{\infty}}}.

Let b¯=Σ(𝒯¯){\bar{b}}=\Sigma_{{{\cal M}_{\infty}}}({\bar{\cal T}}). By branch condensation Lemma 3, b¯{\bar{b}} is the pullback of bb via σ\sigma. We will have that ι¯=π0,b¯𝒯¯δ0{\bar{\iota}}=\pi_{0,{\bar{b}}}^{\bar{\cal T}}\upharpoonright\delta_{0}^{{{\cal M}_{\infty}}} and there is a canonical elementary embedding

σ^:b¯𝒯¯b𝒯{\hat{\sigma}}\colon{\cal M}_{\bar{b}}^{{\bar{\cal T}}}\rightarrow{\cal M}_{b}^{\cal T}

defined by

σ^(π0,b¯𝒯¯(f)(a))=π0,b𝒯(f)(σ(a)),{\hat{\sigma}}(\pi_{0,{\bar{b}}}^{\bar{\cal T}}(f)(a))=\pi_{0,{b}}^{{\cal T}}(f)(\sigma(a)){\rm,}

where ff\in{{\cal M}_{\infty}} and a[ORM¯]<ωa\in[{\rm OR}\cap{\bar{M}}]^{<\omega}. We will have that (𝒯¯)=dom(σ)dom(σ^){\cal M}({\bar{\cal T}})={\rm dom}(\sigma)\cap{\rm dom}({\hat{\sigma}}) and σ\sigma and σ^{\hat{\sigma}} agree on this common part of their domains.

If Eν(𝒯¯)E_{\nu}^{{\cal M}({\bar{\cal T}})} is a total extender from the (𝒯¯)\mathcal{M}(\bar{\mathcal{T}})-sequence, then by the elementarity of σ\sigma, M¯{\bar{M}} satisfies all the axioms of the extender algebra of (𝒯¯){\cal M}({\bar{\cal T}}) given by Eν(𝒯¯)E_{\nu}^{{\cal M}({\bar{\cal T}})}, as |θ0{{\cal M}_{\infty}}|\theta_{0}^{{{\cal M}_{\infty}}} satisfies all the axioms of the extender algebra of (𝒯){\cal M}({\cal T}) given by Eσ(ν)E_{\sigma(\nu)}^{{{\cal M}_{\infty}}}. We may conclude that M¯{\bar{M}} is generic over b¯𝒯¯{\cal M}_{\bar{b}}^{{\bar{\cal T}}}. If g¯\bar{g} is the associated generic over b¯𝒯¯{\cal M}_{\bar{b}}^{{\bar{\cal T}}} and gg that over b𝒯{\cal M}_{b}^{\cal T}, then σ^g¯=σg¯g{\hat{\sigma}}\mbox{``}\bar{g}=\sigma\mbox{``}\bar{g}\subset g, and hence we may lift σ^{\hat{\sigma}} to an elementary embedding

σ^:b¯𝒯¯[M¯]b𝒯[|κ0+]=ult(;U),{\hat{\sigma}}^{*}\colon{\cal M}_{\bar{b}}^{\bar{\cal T}}[{\bar{M}}]\rightarrow{\cal M}_{b}^{\cal T}[{{\cal M}_{\infty}}|\kappa_{0}^{+{{\cal M}_{\infty}}}]={\rm ult}({{\cal M}_{\infty}};U){\rm,}

defined by σ^(τg¯)=(σ^(τ))g{\hat{\sigma}}^{*}(\tau^{\bar{g}})=({\hat{\sigma}}(\tau))^{g}.

But notice that δ0{crit(U)}ran(σ^)\delta_{0}^{{{\cal M}_{\infty}}}\cup\{{\rm crit}(U)\}\subset{\rm ran}({\hat{\sigma}}^{*}), so that by the δ0\delta_{0}^{{{\cal M}_{\infty}}}-soundness of {{\cal M}_{\infty}} and by the choice of UU as a measure, σ^{\hat{\sigma}}^{*} must be the identity, and therefore so is σ\sigma. ∎

Corollary 4.9.
  1. (a)

    κ0+\kappa_{0}^{+{{\cal M}_{\infty}}} has size δ0𝒱1\delta_{0}^{\mathscr{V}_{1}} inside []\mathcal{M}_{\infty}[*].

  2. (b)

    κ0++=κ0++M\kappa_{0}^{++{{\cal M}_{\infty}}}=\kappa_{0}^{++M}.

Proof.

(a) follows from Lemma 4.7 together with (17). (b) is then immediate by κ0++MCard\kappa_{0}^{++M}\in{\rm Card}^{{{\cal M}_{\infty}}}. ∎

This corollary should be compared with Lemma 4.9, to come.

4.8 The κ0{\kappa_{0}}-mantle of MM

We now give another characterization of the universe of []\mathcal{M}_{\infty}[*], though no results outside of this subsection actually depend on it.

The following definitions are essentially taken from [26], though the notation and terminology is different. If WW is an inner model and λ\lambda is a cardinal of WW, then W¯W{\bar{W}}\subset W is a λ\lambda ground of WW iff W¯{\bar{W}} is an inner model of WW and there is some poset W¯{\mathbb{P}}\in{\bar{W}} which has size λ\lambda in W¯{\bar{W}} and some gg which is {\mathbb{P}}-generic over W¯{\bar{W}} such that W=W¯[g]W={\bar{W}}[g]. W¯{\bar{W}} is called a <λ<\lambda ground of WW iff there is some λ¯<λ{\bar{\lambda}}<\lambda such that W¯{\bar{W}} is a λ¯{\bar{\lambda}} ground of WW. The <λ<\lambda mantle of WW is the intersection of all <λ<\lambda grounds of WW. We write 𝕄<λW\mathbb{M}^{W}_{<\lambda} for the <λ{<\lambda}-mantle of WW.

The main result of this subsection is that []\mathcal{M}_{\infty}[*] has universe 𝕄<κ0M\mathbb{M}^{M}_{<\kappa_{0}}; see 4.8. The following fact and its proof are similar to parts of [22, ***Lemmas 3.11 and 4.1] and [17, ***Lemmas 5.4 and 5.12]; in particular, we make use of the condensation stacks from [22].

Let μ<κ0\mu<\kappa_{0} be a cardinal strong cutpoint of MM, and η=μ+M\eta=\mu^{+M}. Let gg be Coll(ω,μ)\mathrm{Coll}(\omega,\mu)-generic over MM. Let 𝒫MM[g]\mathscr{P}^{M[g]}_{M} denote the set of all NM[g]N\in M[g] such that:

  1. NN is a premouse of ordinal height η\eta,

  2. NN has a largest cardinal λ<η\lambda<\eta, and λ\lambda is a strong cutpoint of NN,

  3. M[g]M[g]\vDashNN is fully iterable above λ\lambda

  4. there is a proper class premouse NN^{\prime} with NNN\triangleleft N^{\prime} and M[g]M[g]\vDash𝔼N<η𝔼M\mathbb{E}^{N^{\prime}}\sim^{<\eta}\mathbb{E}^{M}”.

Note that because of the restriction on 𝔼N\mathbb{E}^{N^{\prime}} above η\eta, we don’t actually need to quantify over proper classes here, and clearly 𝒫MM[g]\mathscr{P}_{M}^{M[g]} is definable over M[g]M[g] from the class MM. We now refine this fact:

Lemma 4.9.

Let gg be Coll(ω,μ)\mathrm{Coll}(\omega,\mu)-generic over MM. Then (i) 𝒫MM[g]\mathscr{P}^{M[g]}_{M} is definable over M[g]M[g] from no parameters, uniformly in μ,g\mu,g. Further, (ii) for all N,NN,N^{\prime} as in the definition of 𝒫MM[g]\mathscr{P}^{M[g]}_{M}, NN^{\prime} is definable over M[g]M[g] from the parameter NN, uniformly in μ,g,N,N\mu,g,N,N^{\prime}.

Proof.

Note that η=ω1M[g]\eta=\omega_{1}^{M[g]} and HCM[g]\mathrm{HC}^{M[g]} is the universe of (M|η)[g](M|\eta)[g]. Now working in M[g]M[g], let 𝒫\mathscr{P}^{\prime} be the set of all premice NN of height η\eta such that for some hh,

  1. NN has a largest cardinal, λ\lambda, which is a strong cutpoint of NN,

  2. NN is fully iterable above λ\lambda,

  3. hh is Coll(ω,λ)\mathrm{Coll}(\omega,\lambda)-generic over NN and N[h]N[h] has universe HC{\rm HC},

  4. the condensation stack (N[h])+(N[h])^{+} above N[h]N[h] (relativized as a premouse over (N|λ,h)(N|\lambda,h)) is well-defined, hence is proper class with universe VV.303030Recall we are working in M[g]M[g], so “VV” refers to M[g]M[g] here. Because we relativize over (N|λ,h)(N|\lambda,h), N[h]N[h] plays the role that P|ω1PP|\omega_{1}^{P} plays in the unrelativized condensation stack for a premouse PP.

For N𝒫N\in\mathscr{P}^{\prime}, we write λN\lambda^{N} for the largest cardinal of NN, and with hh as above, we consider N[h]N[h] as an (N|λN,h)(N|\lambda^{N},h)-premouse. Now 𝒫\mathscr{P}^{\prime}\neq\emptyset, and in fact M|η𝒫M|\eta\in\mathscr{P}^{\prime}, as witnessed by gg. For by [22], the condensation stack above (M|η)[g](M|\eta)[g], as computed in M[g]M[g], is just M[g]M[g] (arranged as a premouse over (M|μ,g)(M|\mu,g)).

We will show that 𝒫MM[g]=𝒫\mathscr{P}^{M[g]}_{M}=\mathscr{P}^{\prime}, which gives part (i). The first direction is basically as in [17, Lemma 5.4 part 1]:

Claim 1.

𝒫MM[g]𝒫\mathscr{P}^{M[g]}_{M}\subseteq\mathscr{P}^{\prime}.

Proof.

Let N𝒫MM[g]N\in\mathscr{P}^{M[g]}_{M}, as witnessed by NN^{\prime}. Everything is clear enough except for the fact that, in M[g]M[g], the condensation stack N[h]+N[h]^{+} is well-defined. But N[h]N^{\prime}[h] has universe that of M[g]M[g], and there is α<η\alpha<\eta such that N[h]N^{\prime}[h] is iterable above α\alpha (in VV), and we can take α\alpha here such that N|αN|\alpha projects to λN\lambda^{N}. By this iterability, N[h]N^{\prime}[h], when considered as an (N|α,h)(N|\alpha,h)-premouse, therefore is just the condensation stack above N[h]N[h]. But N[h]|η=N[h]N^{\prime}[h]|\eta=N[h] is also iterable in M[g]M[g] (above λN\lambda^{N}; that is, as an (N|λN,h)(N|\lambda^{N},h)-premouse). So N[h]N[h] satisfies all standard condensation facts (as an (N|λN,h)(N|\lambda^{N},h)-premouse). So we can argue as in the proof of [17, Lemma 5.4 part 1] to see that N[h]N^{\prime}[h], when considered as an (N|λN,h)(N|\lambda^{N},h)-premouse, is also the condensation stack above N[h]N[h], as computed in M[g]M[g], as desired. ∎

Claim 2.

Let N𝒫N\in\mathscr{P}^{\prime}, witnessed by hh. Then there is α\alpha such that μ,λN<α<η\mu,\lambda^{N}<\alpha<\eta and M[g]||αM[g]||\alpha and N[h]||αN[h]||\alpha have the same universe, with largest cardinal ω1M[g]||α<α\omega_{1}^{M[g]||\alpha}<\alpha, and the two structures M[g]||αM[g]||\alpha and N[h]||αN[h]||\alpha are inter-definable from parameters and project ω1M[g]||α\leq\omega_{1}^{M[g]||\alpha}.

Proof.

We basically follow the proof of [22, Lemma 3.11]. Let MM^{\prime} be M[g]M[g] arranged as a premouse over (M|μ,g)(M|\mu,g), and NN^{\prime} be the condensation stack over N[h]N[h] as computed in M[g]M[g].

So M,NM^{\prime},N^{\prime} both have universe M[g]M[g], and in particular, η=ω1M=ω1N\eta=\omega_{1}^{M^{\prime}}=\omega_{1}^{N^{\prime}} and (ω2)M=(ω2)N(\mathcal{H}_{\omega_{2}})^{M^{\prime}}=(\mathcal{H}_{\omega_{2}})^{N^{\prime}}. We first find α<ω2M[g]\alpha^{\prime}<\omega_{2}^{M[g]} such that M||αM^{\prime}||\alpha^{\prime} and N||αN^{\prime}||\alpha^{\prime} have the same universe and are inter-definable from parameters (and some more). Define Mn,Nnn<ω\left<M_{n},N_{n}\right>_{n<\omega} as follows. Let M0=M||ηM_{0}=M^{\prime}||\eta and N0=N||ηN_{0}=N^{\prime}||\eta. Now given Mn,NnM_{n},N_{n}, let Nn+1N_{n+1} be the least SNS\triangleleft N^{\prime} such that NnSNN_{n}\triangleleft S\triangleleft N^{\prime} and MnSM_{n}\in S and ρωS=η\rho_{\omega}^{S}=\eta. Define Mn+1M_{n+1} symmetrically.

Let M~=stackn<ωMn\widetilde{M}=\mathrm{stack}_{n<\omega}M_{n} and N~=stackn<ωNn\widetilde{N}=\mathrm{stack}_{n<\omega}N_{n}. Note that M~,N~\widetilde{M},\widetilde{N} have the same universe UU, which has largest cardinal η\eta, and therefore M~M\widetilde{M}\triangleleft M^{\prime} and N~N\widetilde{N}\triangleleft N^{\prime} (that is, M||ORUM^{\prime}||\mathrm{OR}^{U} and N||ORUN^{\prime}||\mathrm{OR}^{U} are both passive, as η\eta is a strong cutpoint of M,NM^{\prime},N^{\prime}). Note that M~\widetilde{M} is definable from the parameter M0M_{0} over UU; in fact, M~\widetilde{M} is the Jensen stack above M0M_{0} there; cf. [22]. It follows that M~\widetilde{M} is Σ1U({M0})\Sigma_{1}^{U}(\{M_{0}\}). Likewise for N~\widetilde{N} and N0N_{0}. Using this, note that also Mn,Nnn<ω\left<M_{n},N_{n}\right>_{n<\omega} is Σ1U({(M0,N0)})\Sigma_{1}^{U}(\{(M_{0},N_{0})\}), and so ρ1M~=ρ1N~=η\rho_{1}^{\widetilde{M}}=\rho_{1}^{\widetilde{N}}=\eta.

Now as in [22], we can find η¯<η\bar{\eta}<\eta and xUx\in U such that μ,λN<η¯\mu,\lambda^{N}<\bar{\eta} and the hulls Hull1M~(η¯{x})\mathrm{Hull}_{1}^{\widetilde{M}}(\bar{\eta}\cup\{x\}) and Hull1N~(η¯{x})\mathrm{Hull}_{1}^{\widetilde{N}}(\bar{\eta}\cup\{x\}) have the same elements, and letting M¯,N¯\bar{M},\bar{N} be the transitive collapses and π:M¯M~\pi:\bar{M}\to\widetilde{M} and σ:N¯N~\sigma:\bar{N}\to\widetilde{N} the uncollapse maps (so M¯,N¯\bar{M},\bar{N} have the same universe U¯\bar{U} and π,σ\pi,\sigma the same graphs), and such that M0,N0rg(π)M_{0},N_{0}\in\mathrm{rg}(\pi) and crit(π)=η¯{\rm crit}(\pi)=\bar{\eta} and π(η¯)=η\pi(\bar{\eta})=\eta and M¯,N¯\bar{M},\bar{N} are 11-sound with ρ1M¯=η¯=ρ1N¯\rho_{1}^{\bar{M}}=\bar{\eta}=\rho_{1}^{\bar{N}}, so M¯M\bar{M}\triangleleft M^{\prime} and N¯N\bar{N}\triangleleft N^{\prime}. Note that the Σ1U({N0})\Sigma_{1}^{U}(\{N_{0}\}) definition of N~\widetilde{N} reflects down to a Σ1U¯({N¯0})\Sigma_{1}^{\bar{U}}(\{\bar{N}_{0}\}) definition of N¯\bar{N}, where π(N¯0)=N0\pi(\bar{N}_{0})=N_{0}. Likewise vice versa. Therefore M¯,N¯\bar{M},\bar{N} have the same universe and are inter-definable from parameters. So letting α=ORM¯=ORN¯\alpha=\mathrm{OR}^{\bar{M}}=\mathrm{OR}^{\bar{N}}, we are done. ∎

Claim 3.

𝒫𝒫MM[g]\mathscr{P}^{\prime}\subseteq\mathscr{P}^{M[g]}_{M}.

Proof.

Let N,h,αN,h,\alpha be as in Claim 2. Then note that α\alpha is a strong cutpoint of MM and of NN and of the condensation stack N[h]+N[h]^{+} above N[h]N[h] (as an (N|λN,h)(N|\lambda^{N},h)-premouse, as computed in M[g]M[g]). So the iterability of M|ηM|\eta and NN above α\alpha (in M[g]M[g]) implies that (𝔼νM)g=(𝔼νN)h(\mathbb{E}^{M}_{\nu})^{g}=(\mathbb{E}_{\nu}^{N})^{h} for each ν>α\nu>\alpha. Thus, the extender sequences of M|ηM|\eta and NN are intertranslatable (modulo a generic) above α\alpha. So by a proof almost identical to [17, ***Lemma 5.4 part 1], N[h]+N[h]^{+} and M[g]M[g] (as an (M|μ,g)(M|\mu,g)-premouse) have the same extender sequence above α\alpha. Now let N+N^{+} be the result of the P-construction of N[h]+N[h]^{+} above NN. Because η=ω1N[h]+\eta=\omega_{1}^{N[h]^{+}}, this works fine structurally, giving a proper class premouse N+N^{+} extending NN. But since N[h]+N[h]^{+} and M[g]M[g] agree above α\alpha, it follows that 𝔼N+<η𝔼M\mathbb{E}^{N^{+}}\sim^{<\eta}\mathbb{E}^{M}. So N𝒫N\in\mathscr{P}. ∎

This proves part (i). For (ii), working in M[g]M[g], given N𝒫MM[g]=𝒫N\in\mathscr{P}^{M[g]}_{M}=\mathscr{P}^{\prime}, we first define the condensation stack N[h]+N[h]^{+} above N[h]N[h], and then the P-construction NN of N[h]+N[h]^{+} above NN, which gives the desired NN^{\prime}. ∎

Lemma 4.9.

\mathscr{F} is dense in the <κ0{<\kappa_{0}}-grounds of MM, so =𝕄<κ0M\bigcap\mathscr{F}=\mathbb{M}_{<\kappa_{0}}^{M}.

Proof.

Let μ<κ0\mu<\kappa_{0} be a regular cardinal strong cutpoint of MM, and let WW be a <μ<\mu-ground of MM, via a generic filter kk (so W[k]MW[k]\cong M). Let gg be (M,Coll(ω,μ))(M,\mathrm{Coll}(\omega,\mu))-generic and hh be (W,Coll(ω,μ))(W,\mathrm{Coll}(\omega,\mu))-generic, with W[h]M[g]W[h]\cong M[g]. Let W~\widetilde{W} be the model produced by the P-construction of MM over (μ+)W(\mathcal{H}_{\mu^{+}})^{W}. By Lemma 4.8, W~W\widetilde{W}\subseteq W and W~\widetilde{W} is definable from parameters over WW. And W~\widetilde{W} is a ground of MM; in fact W~[k]M\widetilde{W}[k]\cong M, as M|(μ+)MM|(\mu^{+})^{M} is definable over (μ+)M=(μ+)W[k](\mathcal{H}_{\mu^{+}})^{M}=(\mathcal{H}_{\mu^{+}})^{W}[k] from the parameter M|μM|\mu, via the Jensen stack.313131It follows by the standard forcing argument that WW is the actually the universe of W~\widetilde{W}.

Now working in W~\widetilde{W}, we can compute some NN\in\mathscr{F} by forming a Boolean-valued comparison/genericity iteration above (μ+)W(\mu^{+})^{W}, to compute N|δ0NN|\delta_{0}^{N}, and then using P-construction to compute the rest of NN. ∎

Theorem 4.9.

[]\mathcal{M}_{\infty}[*] has universe =𝕄<κ0M\bigcap{\mathscr{F}}=\mathbb{M}_{<\kappa_{0}}^{M}.

Proof.

We already know []=𝕄<κ0M\mathcal{M}_{\infty}[*]\subseteq\bigcap\mathscr{F}=\mathbb{M}_{<\kappa_{0}}^{M} by Lemma 4.8.

Let us verify 𝕄<κ0M[]\mathbb{M}^{M}_{<\kappa_{0}}\subseteq\mathcal{M}_{\infty}[*].323232The original argument used for the proof that 𝕄<κ0M[]\mathbb{M}^{M}_{<\kappa_{0}}\subseteq\mathcal{M}_{\infty}[*], found by the 3rd author, was slightly different; that argument is sketched for the analogous result Corollary 5.8. The 2nd author then adapted that one to yield the one presented here. In either form, the argument is related to Usuba’s ZFC proof of the fact that if κ\kappa is extendible then 𝕄<κ=𝕄\mathbb{M}_{<\kappa}=\mathbb{M}. Related arguments have since been used by the second author in [9] and the third author in [21], [16]. Let U𝔼MU\in\mathbb{E}^{M} be the order 0 total measure on κ0\kappa_{0}. Let

j:MM=Ult(M,U)j\colon M\rightarrow M^{\prime}=\mathrm{Ult}(M,U)

be the ultrapower map. For PP\in{\mathscr{F}}, iMP(U)=UP𝔼Pi_{MP}(U)=U\cap P\in\mathbb{E}^{P} is the order 0 total measure on κ0\kappa_{0} in PP. Let jP:PUlt(P,iMP(U))j^{P}:P\to\mathrm{Ult}(P,i_{MP}(U)) be the ultrapower map. Note jOR=jPORj{\upharpoonright}\mathrm{OR}=j^{P}{\upharpoonright}\mathrm{OR}. Let U=iM(U)U_{\infty}=i_{M\infty}(U) and j:=Ult(,U)j_{\infty}:\mathcal{M}_{\infty}\to\mathcal{M}^{\prime}_{\infty}=\mathrm{Ult}(\mathcal{M}_{\infty},U_{\infty}) be the ultrapower map.

Arguing much as in the proof of Lemma 4.5, jORj\upharpoonright{\rm OR} is definable over []\mathcal{M}_{\infty}[*]: for all η,ξOR\eta,\xi\in\mathrm{OR} and PP\in\mathscr{F}, we have

η=j(ξ)η=jP(ξ)η=j(ξ).\eta=j(\xi)\Longleftrightarrow\eta=j^{P}(\xi)\Longleftrightarrow\eta^{*}=j_{\infty}(\xi^{*}).

(For the second equivalence, just take PP such that η,ξ\eta,\xi are PP-stable.)

Now let X𝕄<κ0MX\in\mathbb{M}_{<\kappa_{0}}^{M} be a set of ordinals. By the preceding paragraph,

jsup(X)[].j\upharpoonright\sup(X)\in\mathcal{M}_{\infty}[*]. (18)

By elementarity, j(X)𝕄<j(κ0)Mj(X)\in\mathbb{M}^{M^{\prime}}_{<j(\kappa_{0})}. It is straightforward to verify that \mathcal{M}_{\infty}^{\prime} is the direct limit of a system \mathscr{F}^{\prime} of uniform grounds of MM^{\prime} in much the same way as {{\cal M}_{\infty}} is the direct limit of the system {\mathscr{F}} of uniform grounds of MM; here the models PP^{\prime}\in\mathscr{F}^{\prime} are exactly those of the form P=Ult(P,iMP(U))P^{\prime}=\mathrm{Ult}(P,i_{MP}(U)) for some PP\in\mathscr{F}. So by Theorem 2,

Q=[]Q=\mathcal{M}_{\infty}^{\prime}[*]

is a <j(κ0)<j(\kappa_{0})-ground of MM^{\prime}. So j(X)Qj(X)\in Q, but note Q[]Q\subseteq\mathcal{M}_{\infty}[*], so j(X)[]j(X)\in\mathcal{M}_{\infty}[*], but then using line (18) we get X[]X\in\mathcal{M}_{\infty}[*], since

αXj(α)j(X).\alpha\in X\Longleftrightarrow j(\alpha)\in j(X).\qed

4.9 The first Varsovian model as the strategy mouse 𝒱1\mathscr{V}_{1}

We will now give another presentation of []\mathcal{M}_{\infty}[*], as a strategy mouse 𝒱1\mathscr{V}_{1} in a fine structural hierarchy 𝒱1||ννOR\left<\mathscr{V}_{1}||\nu\right>_{\nu\in\mathrm{OR}}, as sketched at the beginning of §4.5. To motivate this, first notice the following.

A routine first observation is:

Lemma 4.9.

Let PP be an active (Jensen indexed) premouse. Then FPF^{P} is Σ1\Sigma_{1}-definable over (Ppv,FPOR)(P^{\mathrm{pv}},F^{P}{\upharpoonright}\mathrm{OR}), uniformly in PP.

We remark that it is important here that we have the universe and (internal) extender sequence 𝔼P\mathbb{E}^{P} of PP available.

Let 𝕃=𝕃[](κ0){\mathbb{L}}=\mathbb{L}^{\mathcal{M}_{\infty}[*]}(\kappa_{0}) for the poset of Definition 2.3, for adding generic subset of κ0\kappa_{0}.

Lemma 4.9.

M|κ0M|\kappa_{0} is 𝕃{\mathbb{L}}-generic over []\mathcal{M}_{\infty}[*] and [][M|κ0]=^M\mathcal{M}_{\infty}[*][M|\kappa_{0}]\ \widehat{=}\ M.

Proof.

Since we have verified the properties for uniform grounds, that M|κ0M|\kappa_{0} is 𝕃{\mathbb{L}}-generic over []\mathcal{M}_{\infty}[*] follows from §2. We aim to show that [][M|κ0]=^M\mathcal{M}_{\infty}[*][M|\kappa_{0}]\ \widehat{=}\ M by performing a “PP-construction.”

We identify the sequence M|ν,M||ννOR\left<M|\nu,M||\nu\right>_{\nu\in\mathrm{OR}} inside [][M|κ0]\mathcal{M}_{\infty}[*][M|\kappa_{0}], from the parameter M|κ0M|\kappa_{0} and classes ,\mathcal{M}_{\infty},*, as follows. We start with M|κ0M|\kappa_{0} given. Fix ν\nu with κ0<νOR\kappa_{0}<\nu\in{\rm OR}. The sequence M||ββ<ν\left<M||\beta\right>_{\beta<\nu} determines M|νM|\nu. By Lemma 4.5, []\mathcal{M}_{\infty}[*] knows whether 𝔼νM\mathbb{E}_{\nu}^{M}\neq\emptyset, and if 𝔼νM\mathbb{E}_{\nu}^{M}\neq\emptyset, knows 𝔼νMOR\mathbb{E}_{\nu}^{M}\upharpoonright\mathrm{OR}, uniformly in ν\nu (definably from ,\mathcal{M}_{\infty},*). But from the pair (M|ν,𝔼νMOR)(M|\nu,\mathbb{E}_{\nu}^{M}{\upharpoonright}\mathrm{OR}) we can compute 𝔼νM\mathbb{E}_{\nu}^{M}, also uniformly in ν\nu, by Lemma 4.9. ∎

Definition 4.10.

We now define a class structure 𝒱1\mathscr{V}_{1}, structured analogously to a premouse, built from a sequence 𝔼𝒱1=𝔼ν𝒱1νOR\mathbb{E}^{\mathscr{V}_{1}}=\left<\mathbb{E}^{\mathscr{V}_{1}}_{\nu}\right>_{\nu\in\mathrm{OR}} of extenders. However, some of the extenders will be (properly) long, and will not cohere the sequence. We write 𝒱1||ν\mathscr{V}_{1}||\nu and 𝒱1|ν\mathscr{V}_{1}|\nu with the usual meaning. For those segments 𝒱1||ν\mathscr{V}_{1}||\nu active with long extenders, some of the premouse axioms will fail (in particular, coherence).333333The segments 𝒱1||ν\mathscr{V}_{1}||\nu where ν=γ𝒱1\nu=\gamma^{\mathscr{V}_{1}} or [ν>γ𝒱1\nu>\gamma^{\mathscr{V}_{1}} and crit(𝔼νM)=κ0{\rm crit}(\mathbb{E}^{M}_{\nu})=\kappa_{0}] do not satisfy the usual premouse axioms with respect to their active extender. Write γ𝒱1=κ0+\gamma^{\mathscr{V}_{1}}=\kappa_{0}^{+\mathcal{M}_{\infty}}.

The map π:\pi_{\infty}:\mathcal{M}_{\infty}\to\mathcal{M}_{\infty}^{\mathcal{M}_{\infty}} (see (5) and the preceding discussion) is an iteration map. We define (recursively on ν\nu):

𝔼ν𝒱1={𝔼ν if ν<γ𝒱1π(|δ0) if ν=γ𝒱1𝔼νM(𝒱1|ν) if ν>γ𝒱1.\displaystyle\mathbb{E}_{\nu}^{\mathscr{V}_{1}}=\begin{cases}\mathbb{E}_{\nu}^{{\cal M}_{\infty}}&\mbox{ if }\nu<\gamma^{\mathscr{V}_{1}}\\ \pi_{\infty}\upharpoonright({\cal M}_{\infty}|\delta_{0}^{{\cal M}_{\infty}})&\mbox{ if }\nu=\gamma^{\mathscr{V}_{1}}\\ \mathbb{E}^{M}_{\nu}\upharpoonright(\mathscr{V}_{1}|\nu)&\mbox{ if }\nu>\gamma^{\mathscr{V}_{1}}.\end{cases} (19)

(We will verify in Lemma 4.9 that this definition makes sense; in particular, that 𝔼νM(𝒱1|ν)𝒱1|ν\mathbb{E}^{M}_{\nu}``(\mathscr{V}_{1}|\nu)\subseteq\mathscr{V}_{1}|\nu when ν>γ𝒱1\nu>\gamma^{\mathscr{V}_{1}}.) Let us also write

𝔼𝒱1\displaystyle\mathbb{E}^{\mathscr{V}_{1}} =\displaystyle= {(ν,x,y):𝔼ν𝒱1 and y=𝔼ν𝒱1(x)},\displaystyle\{(\nu,x,y)\colon\mathbb{E}_{\nu}^{\mathscr{V}_{1}}\not=\emptyset\text{ and }y=\mathbb{E}_{\nu}^{\mathscr{V}_{1}}(x)\}, (20)
𝔼𝒱1ν\displaystyle\mathbb{E}^{\mathscr{V}_{1}}{\upharpoonright}\nu =\displaystyle= {(ν¯,x,y)𝔼𝒱1:ν¯<ν}.\displaystyle\{({\bar{\nu}},x,y)\in{\mathbb{E}}^{\mathscr{V}_{1}}\colon{\bar{\nu}}<\nu\}. (21)

We define the structure

𝒱1=(L[𝔼𝒱1];,𝔼𝒱1).\mathscr{V}_{1}=(L[{\mathbb{E}}^{\mathscr{V}_{1}}];\in,\mathbb{E}^{\mathscr{V}_{1}}).

Like with []\mathcal{M}_{\infty}[*], when we discuss definability or write an equation with 𝒱1\mathscr{V}_{1}, or some similar structure, then we refer to the structure itself, not just its universe 𝒱1=L[𝔼𝒱1]\left\lfloor\mathscr{V}_{1}\right\rfloor=L[\mathbb{E}^{\mathscr{V}_{1}}]. In particular, definability over 𝒱1\mathscr{V}_{1} has the class predicate 𝔼𝒱1\mathbb{E}^{\mathscr{V}_{1}} available by default, just like for premice. (But when no confusion can arise, such as with expressions like “x𝒱1x\in\mathscr{V}_{1}” or “x𝒱1x\subseteq\mathscr{V}_{1}”, we really mean “x𝒱1x\in\left\lfloor\mathscr{V}_{1}\right\rfloor” or “x𝒱1x\subseteq\left\lfloor\mathscr{V}_{1}\right\rfloor”, etc.)

Write e𝒱1=𝔼γ𝒱1𝒱1e^{\mathscr{V}_{1}}=\mathbb{E}^{\mathscr{V}_{1}}_{\gamma^{\mathscr{V}_{1}}}, so e𝒱1e^{\mathscr{V}_{1}} is the least (properly) long extender of 𝔼𝒱\mathbb{E}^{\mathscr{V}}, which is just the extender induced by *.

Definition 4.11 (Fine structure of 𝒱1\mathscr{V}_{1}).

The fine structural concepts (rΣn+1\mathrm{r}\Sigma_{n+1}, ρn+1\rho_{n+1}, pn+1p_{n+1}, (n+1)(n+1)-solidity, etc, for n<ωn<\omega) are defined for segments P𝒱1P\trianglelefteq\mathscr{V}_{1}, and also for PpvP^{\mathrm{pv}}, just as for standard premice with Jensen indexing below superstrong: rΣ1P=Σ1P\mathrm{r}\Sigma_{1}^{P}=\Sigma_{1}^{P} (without any constant symbols in the fine structural language), which determines everything else via the usual recursion.

We will show that all segments of 𝒱1\mathscr{V}_{1} are well-defined, sound, and establish a fine structural correspondence between segments of 𝒱1\mathscr{V}_{1} and segments of MM, above a certain starting point. The first non-trivial instance of these facts is given by 4.9 together with the next lemma; it uses techniques reminiscent of those in [22]. It results in a tighter bound on κ0+=γ𝒱1\kappa_{0}^{+\mathcal{M}_{\infty}}=\gamma^{\mathscr{V}_{1}} than that given by Corollary 4.7.

Lemma 4.11.

Let 𝒱¯=𝒱1||γ𝒱1\bar{\mathscr{V}}=\mathscr{V}_{1}||\gamma^{\mathscr{V}_{1}} (so 𝒱¯\bar{\mathscr{V}} has e𝒱1e^{\mathscr{V}_{1}} active). Then:

  1. (a)

    𝕃{\mathbb{L}} is Σ1\Sigma_{1}-definable over 𝒱¯\bar{\mathscr{V}}.

  2. (b)

    𝒱¯\bar{\mathscr{V}} is isomorphic to a structure which is definable without parameters over M|κ0+MM|\kappa_{0}^{+M}.

  3. (c)

    𝒱¯\bar{\mathscr{V}} is sound, with ρω𝒱¯=ρ1𝒱¯=δ\rho_{\omega}^{\bar{\mathscr{V}}}=\rho_{1}^{\bar{\mathscr{V}}}=\delta_{\infty} and p1𝒱¯=p_{1}^{\bar{\mathscr{V}}}=\emptyset.

  4. (d)

    OR𝒱¯<ξ0\mathrm{OR}^{\bar{\mathscr{V}}}<\xi_{0}, where ξ0\xi_{0} is the least ξ>κ0+M\xi>\kappa_{0}^{+M} such that M|ξM|\xi is admissible. Therefore 𝒱1||ν\mathscr{V}_{1}||\nu is passive for every ν(γ𝒱1,ξ0]\nu\in(\gamma^{\mathscr{V}_{1}},\xi_{0}].

Proof.

Part (a) follows from an inspection of §2.

Part (b): Let ¯+\overline{\mathscr{F}}^{+} be like +\mathscr{F}^{+}, but consisting of pairs (P,s)(P,s) such that there is PP^{\prime} with (P,s)+(P^{\prime},s)\in\mathscr{F}^{+} and P=P|κ0+MP=P^{\prime}|\kappa_{0}^{+M} and sκ0+Ms\subseteq\kappa_{0}^{+M}. (Let the associated ordering, models and embeddings be the corresponding ones of +\mathscr{F}^{+}.) Let ¯\overline{{\cal M}}_{\infty} be the direct limit of ¯+\overline{\mathscr{F}}^{+}, and ¯\bar{*} the associated *-map. Let

σ¯:¯|(κ0)+\overline{\sigma}:\overline{\cal M}_{\infty}\to{{\cal M}_{\infty}}|(\kappa_{0}^{{\cal M}_{\infty}})^{+\mathcal{M}_{\infty}}

be the natural map determined by how ¯+\overline{\mathscr{F}}^{+} sits within +\mathscr{F}^{+}. Noting that ¯+\overline{\mathscr{F}}^{+} is definable over M|κ0+MM|\kappa_{0}^{+M}, it suffices to see that σ¯\bar{\sigma} is the identity.

Fix s[M]<ωs\in[\mathscr{I}^{M}]^{<\omega} with ss\neq\emptyset. For PP\in\mathscr{F}, let KPK^{P} be the transitive collapse of

HP=HullP|max(s)(sκ0M),H^{P}=\mathrm{Hull}^{P|\max(s)}(s^{-}\cup\kappa_{0}^{M}),

and let τP:KPHP\tau^{P}:K^{P}\to H^{P} be the uncollapse map, and s¯P=t{OR(KP)}\bar{s}^{P}=t\cup\{\mathrm{OR}(K^{P})\} where τP(t)=s\tau^{P}(t)=s^{-}.

We claim that πMP(s¯M)=s¯M\pi_{MP}(\bar{s}^{M})=\bar{s}^{M}, and therefore (P|κ0+M,s¯P)¯+(P|\kappa_{0}^{+M},\bar{s}^{P})\in\overline{\mathscr{F}}^{+}. For this, note πMP(s,κ0)=(s,κ0)\pi_{MP}(s,\kappa_{0})=(s,\kappa_{0}), so πMP(s¯M)=s¯P\pi_{MP}(\bar{s}^{M})=\bar{s}^{P}. But MM is a small (of size <κ0<\kappa_{0}) forcing extension of PP, which implies HMOR=HPORH^{M}\cap\mathrm{OR}=H^{P}\cap\mathrm{OR}, so s¯P=s¯M\bar{s}^{P}=\bar{s}^{M}, as required.

So write s¯\bar{s} for the common value of s¯P\bar{s}^{P}. One can now use the argument of the proof of Lemma 2 (which showed that the natural map χ:+\chi:\mathcal{M}_{\infty}^{+}\to\mathcal{M}_{\infty} is the identity), but replacing the use of ss there with s¯\bar{s}. It follows that σ¯=id\bar{\sigma}=\mathrm{id}.

Part (c): Since 𝒱¯[]\bar{\mathscr{V}}\in\mathcal{M}_{\infty}[*], it suffices that 𝒱¯=Hull1𝒱¯(δ)\bar{\mathscr{V}}=\mathrm{Hull}_{1}^{\bar{\mathscr{V}}}(\delta_{\infty}).343434Let 𝒬\mathcal{Q} be the structure defined in §4.7. We already know 𝒬=Hull1𝒬(δ)\mathcal{Q}=\mathrm{Hull}_{1}^{\mathcal{Q}}(\delta), but it seems that the branch through the genericity tree involved there might not be computable from *. So the soundness of 𝒱¯\bar{\mathscr{V}} is not an obvious corollary. Let α<γ𝒱1=OR𝒱¯\alpha<\gamma^{\mathscr{V}_{1}}=\mathrm{OR}^{\bar{\mathscr{V}}}; we want to see that γHull1𝒱¯(δ)\gamma\in\mathrm{Hull}_{1}^{\bar{\mathscr{V}}}(\delta_{\infty}). Fix a non-empty s[M]<ωs\in[\mathscr{I}^{M}]^{<\omega} and NN\in\mathscr{F} such that αrg(πNs,)\alpha\in\mathrm{rg}(\pi_{Ns,\infty}). Let s¯\bar{s} be as above. As before, s¯\bar{s} is NN-stable, and note that αrg(πNs¯,)\alpha\in\mathrm{rg}(\pi_{N\bar{s},\infty}) (because α<κ0+M\alpha<\kappa_{0}^{+M}, if πNs,(α¯)=α\pi_{Ns,\infty}(\bar{\alpha})=\alpha then πNs¯,(α¯)=α\pi_{N\bar{s},\infty}(\bar{\alpha})=\alpha). But then, as desired, we have

αHull|max(s¯)((s¯)δ)Hull1𝒱¯(δ).\alpha\in\mathrm{Hull}^{\mathcal{M}_{\infty}|\max(\bar{s})^{*}}((\bar{s}^{-})^{*}\cup\delta_{\infty})\subseteq\mathrm{Hull}_{1}^{\bar{\mathscr{V}}}(\delta_{\infty}).

Part (d) follows from (b) and the definition of 𝔼𝒱1\mathbb{E}^{\mathscr{V}_{1}} above γ𝒱1\gamma^{\mathscr{V}_{1}}. ∎

The levels of 𝒱1\mathscr{V}_{1} correspond tightly to the levels of MM, as follows.

Lemma 4.11.

Let g=gM|κ0g=g_{M|\kappa_{0}} be the ([],𝕃)(\mathcal{M}_{\infty}[*],{\mathbb{L}})-generic determined by M|κ0M|\kappa_{0}. (so [][g]=^M\mathcal{M}_{\infty}[*][g]\ \widehat{=}\ M). For every νOR\nu\in\mathrm{OR} we have:

  1. 1.

    𝒱1|ν\mathscr{V}_{1}|\nu and 𝒱1||ν\mathscr{V}_{1}||\nu are in []\mathcal{M}_{\infty}[*],

  2. 2.

    𝒱1|ν\mathscr{V}_{1}|\nu and 𝒱1||ν\mathscr{V}_{1}||\nu are sound,

  3. 3.

    Suppose νξ0\nu\geq\xi_{0}.353535 Also, M|θ0MM|\theta_{0}^{M} and 𝒱1||γ𝒱1\mathscr{V}_{1}||\gamma^{\mathscr{V}_{1}} are “generically equivalent in the codes”, and letting f:(θ0M,ξ0)(γ𝒱1,ξ0)f:(\theta_{0}^{M},\xi_{0})\to(\gamma^{\mathscr{V}_{1}},\xi_{0}) be the unique surjective order-preserving map, then M|α=M||αM|\alpha=M||\alpha are likewise equivalent with 𝒱1|f(α)=𝒱1||f(α)\mathscr{V}_{1}|f(\alpha)=\mathscr{V}_{1}||f(\alpha) for all αdom(f)\alpha\in{\rm dom}(f), but we will not need this. Then

    1. (a)

      𝕃𝒱1|ν{\mathbb{L}}\in\mathscr{V}_{1}|\nu and gg is (𝒱1|ν,𝕃)(\mathscr{V}_{1}|\nu,\mathbb{L})-generic,

    2. (b)

      (𝒱1|ν)[g]=M|ν(\mathscr{V}_{1}|\nu)[g]=^{*}M|\nu,363636The notation is explained in 4.9.

    3. (c)

      (𝒱1||ν)[g]=M||ν(\mathscr{V}_{1}||\nu)[g]=^{*}M||\nu,

    4. (d)

      if 𝔼νM\mathbb{E}^{M}_{\nu}\neq\emptyset and crit(𝔼νM)>κ0{\rm crit}(\mathbb{E}^{M}_{\nu})>\kappa_{0} then 𝒱1||ν\mathscr{V}_{1}||\nu satisfies the usual premouse axioms with respect to its active predicate (with Jensen indexing; in particular, 𝔼ν𝒱1\mathbb{E}^{\mathscr{V}_{1}}_{\nu} is an extender over 𝒱1|ν\mathscr{V}_{1}|\nu), and

    5. (e)

      if E=𝔼νME=\mathbb{E}^{M}_{\nu}\neq\emptyset and crit(E)=κ0{\rm crit}(E)=\kappa_{0} then 𝔼ν𝒱1\mathbb{E}^{\mathscr{V}_{1}}_{\nu} is a long (δ,ν)(\delta_{\infty},\nu)-extender over \mathcal{M}_{\infty} and

      Ult(|δ,𝔼ν𝒱1)=iEM(|δ)=Ult(M,E)|iEM(δ)\mathrm{Ult}(\mathcal{M}_{\infty}|\delta_{\infty},\mathbb{E}^{\mathscr{V}_{1}}_{\nu})=i^{M}_{E}(\mathcal{M}_{\infty}|\delta_{\infty})=\mathcal{M}_{\infty}^{\mathrm{Ult}(M,E)}|i^{M}_{E}(\delta_{\infty})

      is a lightface proper class of 𝒱1|ν\mathscr{V}_{1}|\nu, uniformly in ν\nu.

Remark 4.11.

Here the notation ==^{*} is the usual one in this context, meaning that (i) the two structures have the same universe, (ii) for each α[ξ0,ν)\alpha\in[\xi_{0},\nu) (or [ξ0,ν][\xi_{0},\nu]), 𝔼α𝒱1=𝔼αM(𝒱1|α)\mathbb{E}^{\mathscr{V}_{1}}_{\alpha}=\mathbb{E}^{M}_{\alpha}{\upharpoonright}(\mathscr{V}_{1}|\alpha) (which is already true by definition), and conversely, if crit(𝔼αM)>κ0{\rm crit}(\mathbb{E}^{M}_{\alpha})>\kappa_{0} then 𝔼αM\mathbb{E}^{M}_{\alpha} is the canonical small forcing extension of 𝔼α𝒱1\mathbb{E}^{\mathscr{V}_{1}}_{\alpha} to M|αM|\alpha and if crit(𝔼αM)=κ0{\rm crit}(\mathbb{E}^{M}_{\alpha})=\kappa_{0} then 𝔼αM\mathbb{E}^{M}_{\alpha} is determined by 𝔼αMOR=𝔼α𝒱1OR\mathbb{E}^{M}_{\alpha}{\upharpoonright}\mathrm{OR}=\mathbb{E}^{\mathscr{V}_{1}}_{\alpha}{\upharpoonright}\mathrm{OR} and M|αM|\alpha as usual for a premouse, and (iii) the structures 𝒱1|ν\mathscr{V}_{1}|\nu and M|νM|\nu (or 𝒱1||ν\mathscr{V}_{1}||\nu and M||νM||\nu) have corresponding fine structure in the manner usual for P-constructions as in [12], with matching projecta and parameters, etc.

Proof.

The lemma holds for ν<γ𝒱1\nu<\gamma^{\mathscr{V}_{1}} directly by definition, for ν=γ𝒱1\nu=\gamma^{\mathscr{V}_{1}} by 4.9. For γ𝒱1<νξ0\gamma^{\mathscr{V}_{1}}<\nu\leq\xi_{0} it is a straightforward consequence: we have 𝒱1||ξ0[]\mathscr{V}_{1}||\xi_{0}\in\mathcal{M}_{\infty}[*] since A[]A\in\mathcal{M}_{\infty}[*], and therefore 𝒱1||ν\mathscr{V}_{1}||\nu cannot project <δ<\delta_{\infty}. Note that γ𝒱1Hull1𝒱1|ν()\gamma^{\mathscr{V}_{1}}\in\mathrm{Hull}_{1}^{\mathscr{V}_{1}|\nu}(\emptyset), just because 𝒱1||γ𝒱1\mathscr{V}_{1}||\gamma^{\mathscr{V}_{1}} is the least segment with an active extender of its kind. Using 4.9, therefore γ𝒱1+1Hull1𝒱1|ν(δ)\gamma^{\mathscr{V}_{1}}+1\subseteq\mathrm{Hull}_{1}^{\mathscr{V}_{1}|\nu}(\delta_{\infty}). If ν<ωγ𝒱1\nu<\omega\cdot\gamma^{\mathscr{V}_{1}} then we therefore get 𝒱1|νHull1𝒱1|ν(δ)\mathscr{V}_{1}|\nu\subseteq\mathrm{Hull}_{1}^{\mathscr{V}_{1}|\nu}(\delta_{\infty}), and hence 𝒱1|ν\mathscr{V}_{1}|\nu is sound. If instead ωγ𝒱1ν\omega\cdot\gamma^{\mathscr{V}_{1}}\leq\nu then note that (𝒱1|ν)[g](\mathscr{V}_{1}|\nu)[g] has universe that of M|νM|\nu, and the Σ0M|ν\Sigma_{0}^{M|\nu} forcing relation is Δ1𝒱1|ν\Delta_{1}^{\mathscr{V}_{1}|\nu} (lightface, as γ𝒱1Hull1𝒱1|ν()\gamma^{\mathscr{V}_{1}}\in\mathrm{Hull}_{1}^{\mathscr{V}_{1}|\nu}(\emptyset)). But M|ν=Hull1M|ν(κ0+M+1)M|\nu=\mathrm{Hull}_{1}^{M|\nu}(\kappa_{0}^{+M}+1), and since all of the Σ1\Sigma_{1} facts witnessing this get forced, it follows that 𝒱1|ν=Hull1𝒱1|ν(δ)\mathscr{V}_{1}|\nu=\mathrm{Hull}_{1}^{\mathscr{V}_{1}|\nu}(\delta_{\infty}), so 𝒱1|ν\mathscr{V}_{1}|\nu is sound.

For ν>ξ0\nu>\xi_{0} we discuss parts 1 and 33(d),3(e); for the rest one mostly uses standard calculations as for P-constructions. Suppose we have established that (𝒱1|ν)[g]=M|ν[](\mathscr{V}_{1}|\nu)[g]=^{*}M|\nu\in\mathcal{M}_{\infty}[*], and 𝔼νM\mathbb{E}^{M}_{\nu}\neq\emptyset, so 𝔼ν𝒱1=𝔼νM(𝒱1|ν)\mathbb{E}^{\mathscr{V}_{1}}_{\nu}=\mathbb{E}^{M}_{\nu}{\upharpoonright}(\mathscr{V}_{1}|\nu)\neq\emptyset. We already know that 𝔼ν𝒱1OR[]\mathbb{E}^{\mathscr{V}_{1}}_{\nu}{\upharpoonright}\mathrm{OR}\in\mathcal{M}_{\infty}[*] (by Lemma 4.5). We must verify that 𝔼ν𝒱1[]\mathbb{E}^{\mathscr{V}_{1}}_{\nu}\in\mathcal{M}_{\infty}[*] (and uniformly so), and hence 𝒱1||ν[]\mathscr{V}_{1}||\nu\in\mathcal{M}_{\infty}[*], and that 𝒱1||ν\mathscr{V}_{1}||\nu has the right properties.

Suppose κ0<crit(𝔼νM)\kappa_{0}<{\rm crit}(\mathbb{E}^{M}_{\nu}). Then 𝔼ν𝒱1\mathbb{E}^{\mathscr{V}_{1}}_{\nu} is an extender over 𝒱1|ν\mathscr{V}_{1}|\nu satisfying the usual requirements for premice, by the usual proof (using induction and that M|νM|\nu is a small forcing extension of 𝒱1|ν\mathscr{V}_{1}|\nu). It follows that 𝔼ν𝒱1\mathbb{E}^{\mathscr{V}_{1}}_{\nu} can be computed from the pair (𝒱1|ν,𝔼ν𝒱1OR)(\mathscr{V}_{1}|\nu,\mathbb{E}^{\mathscr{V}_{1}}_{\nu}{\upharpoonright}\mathrm{OR}), as usual. But 𝒱1|ν\mathscr{V}_{1}|\nu is in []\mathcal{M}_{\infty}[*] by induction.

Now suppose that κ0=crit(𝔼νM)\kappa_{0}={\rm crit}(\mathbb{E}^{M}_{\nu}). Then E=𝔼ν𝒱1E=\mathbb{E}^{\mathscr{V}_{1}}_{\nu} is a (long) (δ,ν)(\delta_{\infty},\nu)-extender over |δ\mathcal{M}_{\infty}|\delta_{\infty}, but this time EE does not cohere 𝒱1|ν\mathscr{V}_{1}|\nu. In order to compute the full EE from EORE{\upharpoonright}\mathrm{OR}, one also needs the target model

U=Ult(|δ,E)=Ult(M,𝔼νM)|ν.U=\mathrm{Ult}(\mathcal{M}_{\infty}|\delta_{\infty},E)=\mathcal{M}_{\infty}^{\mathrm{Ult}(M,\mathbb{E}^{M}_{\nu})}|\nu.

By 4.9, this is computed by the local covering system of M|νM|\nu (as defined in that proof, but over M|νM|\nu, not M|(κ0+M)M|(\kappa_{0}^{+M})). But since 𝒱1|ν=M|ν\mathscr{V}_{1}|\nu=^{*}M|\nu and the forcing 𝕃𝒱1|λ\mathbb{L}\in\mathscr{V}_{1}|\lambda where λ\lambda is the largest cardinal of 𝒱1|ν\mathscr{V}_{1}|\nu, and |δ𝒱1|λ\mathcal{M}_{\infty}|\delta_{\infty}\in\mathscr{V}_{1}|\lambda, there is a canonical definition of UU over 𝒱1|ν\mathscr{V}_{1}|\nu (uniform in all such ν\nu). That is, although we don’t have the full M|νM|\nu directly available, the agreement between 𝔼M\mathbb{E}^{M} and 𝔼𝒱1\mathbb{E}^{\mathscr{V}_{1}} ensures that the short tree strategy for \mathcal{M}_{\infty} is computed almost like when we do have M|νM|\nu: Given a strong cutpoint γ\gamma of 𝒱1|ν\mathscr{V}_{1}|\nu with δ+(𝒱1|ν)<γ\delta_{\infty}^{+(\mathscr{V}_{1}|\nu)}<\gamma, let GG be (𝒱1|ν,Coll(ω,γ))(\mathscr{V}_{1}|\nu,\mathrm{Coll}(\omega,\gamma))-generic. Then (𝒱1|ν)[G](\mathscr{V}_{1}|\nu)[G] can be arranged as a premouse over (𝒱1||γ,G)(\mathscr{V}_{1}||\gamma,G), and note that we can also take GG such that there is an (M,Coll(ω,γ))(M,\mathrm{Coll}(\omega,\gamma))-generic GG^{\prime} such that (M|ν)[G]=(𝒱1|ν)[G](M|\nu)[G^{\prime}]=^{*}(\mathscr{V}_{1}|\nu)[G] (with (M||γ,G)(M||\gamma,G^{\prime}) equivalent intercomputable with (𝒱1||γ,G)(\mathscr{V}_{1}||\gamma,G)). Therefore we can use (𝒱1|ν)[G](\mathscr{V}_{1}|\nu)[G] to compute short tree strategy for |δ\mathcal{M}_{\infty}|\delta_{\infty} in the same manner we use (M|ν)[G](M|\nu)[G^{\prime}] (working above γ\gamma), and by homogeneity, this computation restricted to trees in 𝒱1|ν\mathscr{V}_{1}|\nu is independent of the choice of GG. The computation of maximal trees (above γ\gamma) is similarly absolute, and note that the P-constructions determined by these trees also agree between M|νM|\nu and 𝒱1|ν\mathscr{V}_{1}|\nu. The system computed in 𝒱1|ν\mathscr{V}_{1}|\nu is also easily dense in that of M|νM|\nu. Therefore 𝒱1|ν\mathscr{V}_{1}|\nu computes Ult(M,E)|ν\mathcal{M}_{\infty}^{\mathrm{Ult}(M,E)}|\nu, as desired.373737Note that the foregoing proof did not use Lemmas 4.3.2 or 4.3.2, which we are yet to actually prove; it does not matter here whether Ult(M,𝔼νM)|ν\mathcal{M}_{\infty}^{\mathrm{Ult}(M,\mathbb{E}^{M}_{\nu})}|\nu is a correct iterate of |δ0\mathcal{M}_{\infty}|\delta_{0}^{\mathcal{M}_{\infty}}. But in any case, we could have proved those lemmas at the point they appeared in the text.

Lemma 4.11.

[]\mathcal{M}_{\infty}[*] and 𝒱1\mathscr{V}_{1} (as defined in 4.8 and 4.10) have the same universe.

Proof.

We have 𝒱1[]\mathscr{V}_{1}\subseteq\mathcal{M}_{\infty}[*] by Lemma 4.9 part 1.

Let us show []𝒱1\mathcal{M}_{\infty}[*]\subseteq\mathscr{V}_{1}. Write 𝕃=𝕃θ0M𝒱1\mathbb{L}=\mathbb{L}_{\theta_{0}^{M}}^{\mathscr{V}_{1}}. By 4.9 part 3, 𝕃𝒱1\mathbb{L}\in\mathscr{V}_{1}, and since 𝒱1[]\mathscr{V}_{1}\subseteq\mathcal{M}_{\infty}[*], therefore g=gM|θ0Mg=g_{M|\theta_{0}^{M}} is 𝕃\mathbb{L}-generic over both []\mathcal{M}_{\infty}[*] and 𝒱1\mathscr{V}_{1}. But then as in the proof of Lemma 4.9, 𝒱1[g]\mathscr{V}_{1}[g] has universe M\left\lfloor M\right\rfloor (as does [][g]\mathcal{M}_{\infty}[*][g]).

Now let x[]x\in\mathcal{M}_{\infty}[*] be a set of ordinals. We show that x𝒱1x\in\mathscr{V}_{1}. Let τ\tau be an 𝕃{{\mathbb{L}}}-name in 𝒱1\mathscr{V}_{1} such that x=τgx=\tau^{g}. Let pgp\in g be such that p[]𝕃τ=xˇp\Vdash_{\mathcal{M}_{\infty}[*]}^{{\mathbb{L}}}\tau={\check{x}}. It is easy to see that then

x={ξ:p𝒱1𝕃ξˇτ}𝒱1.x=\{\xi\colon p\Vdash_{\mathscr{V}_{1}}^{{\mathbb{L}}}{\check{\xi}}\in\tau\}\in\mathscr{V}_{1}.

So the two models have the same universe. ∎

The preceding fact will be refined later in Lemma 4.10.

Remark 4.11.

We may also reorganize 𝒱1\mathscr{V}_{1} as a strategy premouse, by representing the information contained in the long extenders in 𝔼𝒱1\mathbb{E}^{\mathscr{V}_{1}} differently. These extenders are easily seen to be intertranslatable with fragments of Σ\Sigma_{\mathcal{M}_{\infty}} for trees based on |δ\mathcal{M}_{\infty}|\delta_{\infty}. Namely, let us define a sequence (𝔽ν𝒱1:νOR)(\mathbb{F}_{\nu}^{\mathscr{V}_{1}}\colon\nu\in{\rm OR}) as follows. Except for those ν\nu where 𝔼ν𝒱1\mathbb{E}^{\mathscr{V}_{1}}_{\nu} is long, we set 𝔽ν𝒱1=𝔼ν𝒱1\mathbb{F}^{\mathscr{V}_{1}}_{\nu}=\mathbb{E}^{\mathscr{V}_{1}}_{\nu}. If 𝔼ν𝒱1\mathbb{E}^{\mathscr{V}_{1}}_{\nu} is long, then 𝔽ν𝒱1=Σ(𝒯)\mathbb{F}^{\mathscr{V}_{1}}_{\nu}=\Sigma_{\mathcal{M}_{\infty}}(\mathcal{T}), where 𝒯\mathcal{T} is the normal tree on \mathcal{M}_{\infty} leading from |δ\mathcal{M}_{\infty}|\delta_{\infty} to iEM(|δ)i^{M}_{E}(\mathcal{M}_{\infty}|\delta_{\infty}). Then easily, Lemma 4.9 holds also after replacing 𝔼𝒱1\mathbb{E}^{\mathscr{V}_{1}} with 𝔽𝒱1\mathbb{F}^{\mathscr{V}_{1}}, and 𝔼𝒱1,𝔽𝒱1\mathbb{E}^{\mathscr{V}_{1}},\mathbb{F}^{\mathscr{V}_{1}} are level-by-level intertranslatable. So L[𝔽𝒱1]=^𝒱1L[{\mathbb{F}}^{\mathscr{V}_{1}}]\ \widehat{=}\ \mathscr{V}_{1}.383838However, it is not clear whether 𝒱1\mathscr{V}_{1} can be arranged as a strategy mouse in one of the more traditional hierarchies, like those used for HOD mice, or the least (tree) branch hierarchy.

Lemma 4.11.

We have:

  1. (a)

    The restriction of Σ\Sigma_{{{\cal M}_{\infty}}} to trees in 𝒱1\mathscr{V}_{1} and based on |δ{{\cal M}_{\infty}}|\delta_{\infty}, is lightface definable over 𝒱1\mathscr{V}_{1} (so by Lemma 4.10 below, it is also lightface definable over []\mathcal{M}_{\infty}[*]).

  2. (b)

    Let gg be in some set generic extension of VV and be set-generic over 𝒱1\mathscr{V}_{1}. Let Σ\Sigma^{\prime}_{\mathcal{M}_{\infty}} be the restriction of Σ\Sigma_{{{\cal M}_{\infty}}} to trees in 𝒱1[g]\mathscr{V}_{1}[g] and based on |δ{{\cal M}_{\infty}}|\delta_{\infty}. Then Σ\Sigma^{\prime}_{\mathcal{M}_{\infty}} is definable over the universe of 𝒱1[g]\mathscr{V}_{1}[g] from the predicate 𝒱1\mathscr{V}_{1}.393939Regarding trees V\notin V, cf. Footnote 27.

Proof.

This is much like the proof of Lemma 4.3.2 (whose complete proof will rely on Lemma 4.11, still to come), although now we don’t have MM itself available. The computation of short tree strategy is as in the proof of Lemma 4.9 part 33(e). The computation of branches at maximal stages is like in the proof of Lemma 4.3.2. ∎

To summarize, we have isolated several representations of the universe of 𝒱1\mathscr{V}_{1}, indicating that 𝒱1\mathscr{V}_{1} is a natural object:

𝒱1\displaystyle\mathscr{V}_{1} =^\displaystyle\ \widehat{=}\ L[𝔼𝒱1] (Definition 4.10)\displaystyle L[{\mathbb{E}}^{\mathscr{V}_{1}}]\mbox{ (Definition \ref{dfn:vV_1}})
=^\displaystyle\ \widehat{=}\ L[𝔽𝒱1] (Remark 4.9)\displaystyle L[{\mathbb{F}}^{\mathscr{V}_{1}}]\mbox{ (Remark \ref{rem:vV_1_as_strategy_premouse})}
=^\displaystyle\ \widehat{=}\ [] (see (13), Lemma 4.9)\displaystyle{{\cal M}_{\infty}}[*]\mbox{ (see (\ref{defn_first_varsovian_model}), Lemma \ref{lem:vV_1_M_infty[*]_same_univ})}
=^\displaystyle\ \widehat{=}\ HODM[G] (Lemma 4.5)\displaystyle\mathrm{HOD}_{\mathscr{E}}^{M[G]}\mbox{ (Lemma \ref{tm:M_infty[*]=HOD_E})}
=^\displaystyle\ \widehat{=}\ =the <κ0 mantle of M (Proposition 4.8)\displaystyle\bigcap{\mathscr{F}}=\mbox{the }<\kappa_{0}\mbox{ mantle of }M\mbox{ (Proposition \ref{prop:vV_1_is_<kappa_0-mantle})}

4.10 Varsovian strategy premice

In this section we will introduce an axiomatization for premice in the hierarchy of 𝒱1\mathscr{V}_{1}. But first, we refine Lemma 4.9 as follows:

Lemma 4.11.
  1. 1.

    Ult(𝒱1,e𝒱1)=𝒱1\mathrm{Ult}(\mathscr{V}_{1},e^{\mathscr{V}_{1}})=\mathscr{V}_{1}^{\mathcal{M}_{\infty}}.

  2. 2.

    𝒱1\mathscr{V}_{1} is a lightface class of []\mathcal{M}_{\infty}[*],

  3. 3.

    []\mathcal{M}_{\infty}[*] is a lightface class of 𝒱1\mathscr{V}_{1}.

Proof.

Part 2: Argue as in the proof of Lemma 4.9, using again Lemma 4.5.

Part 1: Let e=e𝒱1e=e^{\mathscr{V}_{1}}. We have =Ult(,e)\mathcal{M}_{\infty}^{\mathcal{M}_{\infty}}=\mathrm{Ult}(\mathcal{M}_{\infty},e) and π:\pi_{\infty}:\mathcal{M}_{\infty}\to\mathcal{M}_{\infty}^{\mathcal{M}_{\infty}} is the ultrapower map, so eπe\subseteq\pi_{\infty}. By Lemma 2, π\pi_{\infty} extends elementarily to

π+:[][],\pi_{\infty}^{+}:\mathcal{M}_{\infty}[*]\to\mathcal{M}_{\infty}^{\mathcal{M}_{\infty}}[*^{\mathcal{M}_{\infty}}],

so considering how 𝒱1\mathscr{V}_{1} is defined over []\mathcal{M}_{\infty}[*], and 𝒱1\mathscr{V}_{1}^{\mathcal{M}_{\infty}} over []\mathcal{M}_{\infty}^{\mathcal{M}_{\infty}}[*^{\mathcal{M}_{\infty}}],

π+:𝒱1𝒱1\pi_{\infty}^{+}:\mathscr{V}_{1}\to\mathscr{V}_{1}^{\mathcal{M}_{\infty}}

is also elementary. Since Vδ=Vδ𝒱1V_{\delta_{\infty}}^{\mathcal{M}_{\infty}}=V_{\delta_{\infty}}^{\mathscr{V}_{1}}, it follows that ee is also derived from π+\pi_{\infty}^{+}. Let 𝒱=Ult(𝒱1,e)\mathscr{V}^{\prime}=\mathrm{Ult}(\mathscr{V}_{1},e) and j+:𝒱1𝒱j^{+}:\mathscr{V}_{1}\to\mathscr{V}^{\prime} be the ultrapower map and k+:𝒱𝒱1k^{+}:\mathscr{V}^{\prime}\to\mathscr{V}_{1}^{\mathcal{M}_{\infty}} the factor map, so k+j+=π+k^{+}\circ j^{+}=\pi_{\infty}^{+}. Since ππ+\pi_{\infty}\subseteq\pi_{\infty}^{+} and π\pi_{\infty} is the ultrapower map, we have k+OR=idk^{+}{\upharpoonright}\mathrm{OR}=\mathrm{id} (and j+ORπ+j^{+}{\upharpoonright}\mathrm{OR}\subseteq\pi_{\infty}^{+}). So in fact k+=idk^{+}=\mathrm{id} and 𝒱=𝒱1\mathscr{V}^{\prime}=\mathscr{V}_{1}^{\mathcal{M}_{\infty}}.404040Here is a slightly alternate argument. We have =Ult(,e)\mathcal{M}_{\infty}^{\mathcal{M}_{\infty}}=\mathrm{Ult}(\mathcal{M}_{\infty},e) and π\pi_{\infty} is the ultrapower map. Let N[e]=Ult([e],e)N[e^{\prime}]=\mathrm{Ult}(\mathcal{M}_{\infty}[e],e) and j:[e]N[e]j:\mathcal{M}_{\infty}[e]\to N[e^{\prime}] be the ultrapower map. Then as before, in fact N=N=\mathcal{M}_{\infty}^{\mathcal{M}_{\infty}} and πj=π+\pi_{\infty}\subseteq j=\pi_{\infty}^{+}. Moreover, by considering some fixed indiscernibles, e=π+(e)=α<δπ(eα)e^{\prime}=\pi_{\infty}^{+}(e)=\bigcup_{\alpha<\delta_{\infty}}\pi_{\infty}(e{\upharpoonright}\alpha) is the correct extender of the iteration map ()\mathcal{M}_{\infty}^{\mathcal{M}_{\infty}}\to(\mathcal{M}_{\infty})^{\mathcal{M}_{\infty}^{\mathcal{M}_{\infty}}}. Now 𝒱1\mathscr{V}_{1} and [e]\mathcal{M}_{\infty}[e] have the same universe, and 𝒱1\mathscr{V}_{1} is defined over [e]\mathcal{M}_{\infty}[e] via the procedure mentioned for part 2 of the lemma. So Ult(𝒱1,e)\mathrm{Ult}(\mathscr{V}_{1},e) is defined over [e]\mathcal{M}_{\infty}^{\mathcal{M}_{\infty}}[e^{\prime}] in the same manner. But ee^{\prime} agrees with *^{\mathcal{M}_{\infty}}, so this definition actually yields 𝒱1\mathscr{V}_{1}^{\mathcal{M}_{\infty}}.

Part 3: It suffices to define \mathcal{M}_{\infty} and δ0*{\upharpoonright}\delta_{0}^{\mathcal{M}_{\infty}}. But δ0*{\upharpoonright}\delta_{0}^{\mathcal{M}_{\infty}} is just the active extender of 𝒱1||γ𝒱1\mathscr{V}_{1}||\gamma^{\mathscr{V}_{1}}. To define \mathcal{M}_{\infty}, we first have ||κ0+=𝒱1|γ𝒱1\mathcal{M}_{\infty}||\kappa_{0}^{+\mathcal{M}_{\infty}}=\mathscr{V}_{1}|\gamma^{\mathscr{V}_{1}}. But 𝒱1\mathscr{V}_{1}^{\mathcal{M}_{\infty}} is a lightface class of 𝒱1\mathscr{V}_{1} by part 1. And 𝔼[κ0+,)\mathbb{E}^{\mathcal{M}_{\infty}}{\upharpoonright}[\kappa_{0}^{+\mathcal{M}_{\infty}},\infty) is determined by M||κ0+M||\kappa_{0}^{+\mathcal{M}_{\infty}} and 𝔼𝒱1(γ𝒱1,)\mathbb{E}^{\mathscr{V}_{1}^{\mathcal{M}_{\infty}}}{\upharpoonright}(\gamma^{\mathscr{V}_{1}^{\mathcal{M}_{\infty}}},\infty), since the two sequences agree over the ordinals. ∎

Definition 4.12.

For an MswswM_{\mathrm{swsw}}-like NN, N\mathcal{M}_{\infty}^{N}, N*^{N}, []N\mathcal{M}_{\infty}[*]^{N} and 𝒱1N\mathscr{V}_{1}^{N} denote the lightface NN-classes defined over NN just as the corresponding classes are defined over MM.

Also given an MswswM_{\mathrm{swsw}}-like NN and N¯N\bar{N}\trianglelefteq N with κ0+NORN¯\kappa_{0}^{+N}\leq\mathrm{OR}^{\bar{N}}, we define 𝒱1N¯\mathscr{V}_{1}^{\bar{N}} by recursion on ORN¯\mathrm{OR}^{\bar{N}} by setting 𝒱1N||(κ0+N+α)=𝒱1N||(γ+α)\mathscr{V}_{1}^{N||(\kappa_{0}^{+N}+\alpha)}=\mathscr{V}_{1}^{N}||(\gamma+\alpha), where γ=γ𝒱1N\gamma=\gamma^{\mathscr{V}_{1}^{N}}. Noting that this definition is level-by-level, we similarly define 𝒱1N¯(κ)\mathscr{V}_{1}^{\bar{N}}(\kappa) whenever N¯\bar{N} is MswswM_{\mathrm{swsw}}-small and κ\kappa is an inaccessible limit of cutpoints and Woodins of N¯\bar{N} and κ<ORN¯\kappa<\mathrm{OR}^{\bar{N}}, level-by-level (starting by defining 𝒱1N¯|κ+N¯\mathscr{V}_{1}^{\bar{N}|\kappa^{+\bar{N}}} as 𝒱1||γ𝒱1\mathscr{V}_{1}||\gamma^{\mathscr{V}_{1}} is defined (in the codes) over M|κ0+MM|\kappa_{0}^{+M}). We will often suppress the κ\kappa from the notation, writing just 𝒱1N¯\mathscr{V}_{1}^{\bar{N}}.

We now want to axiomatize structures in the hierarchy of 𝒱1\mathscr{V}_{1} to some extent:

Definition 4.13.

A base Vsp is an amenable transitive structure 𝒱=(P,F)\mathscr{V}=(P_{\infty},F) such that in some forcing extension there is PP such that:

  1. 1.

    P,PP,P_{\infty} are premice which model ZFC\mathrm{ZFC}^{-} and are MswswM_{\mathrm{swsw}}-small; that is, they have no active segments which satisfy “There are κ0<δ1<κ1\kappa_{0}<\delta_{1}<\kappa_{1} with δ1\delta_{1} Woodin and κ0,κ1\kappa_{0},\kappa_{1} strong”.

  2. 2.

    PP has a least Woodin cardinal δ0P\delta_{0}^{P} and a largest cardinal κ0P>δ0P\kappa_{0}^{P}>\delta_{0}^{P}, and κ0P\kappa_{0}^{P} is inaccessible in PP and a limit of cutpoints of PP; likewise for P,δ0P,κ0PP_{\infty},\delta_{0}^{P_{\infty}},\kappa_{0}^{P_{\infty}},

  3. 3.

    ORP=δ0P\mathrm{OR}^{P}=\delta_{0}^{P_{\infty}}, κ0P\kappa_{0}^{P} is the least measurable of PP_{\infty}, and 𝒱1P=cHull1𝒱(δ0P)\mathscr{V}_{1}^{P}=\mathrm{cHull}_{1}^{\mathscr{V}}(\delta_{0}^{P_{\infty}}),

  4. 4.

    P\mathcal{M}_{\infty}^{P_{\infty}} (defined over PP_{\infty} like |γ𝒱1\mathcal{M}_{\infty}|\gamma^{\mathscr{V}_{1}} is defined over M|κ0+MM|\kappa_{0}^{+M}) is well-defined, and has least measurable κ0P\kappa_{0}^{P_{\infty}} and least Woodin δ0P=ORP\delta_{0}^{\mathcal{M}_{\infty}^{P_{\infty}}}=\mathrm{OR}^{P_{\infty}},

  5. 5.

    P|δ0P\mathcal{M}_{\infty}^{P_{\infty}}|\delta_{0}^{\mathcal{M}_{\infty}^{P_{\infty}}} is obtained by iterating P|δ0PP_{\infty}|\delta_{0}^{P_{\infty}}, via a normal tree 𝒯\mathcal{T} of length δ0P\delta_{0}^{\mathcal{M}_{\infty}^{P_{\infty}}},

  6. 6.

    FF is a cofinal Σ1\Sigma_{1}-elementary (hence fully elementary, by ZFC\mathrm{ZFC}^{-}) embedding

    P|δ0PP|δ0P,P_{\infty}|\delta_{0}^{P_{\infty}}\to\mathcal{M}_{\infty}^{P_{\infty}}|\delta_{0}^{\mathcal{M}_{\infty}^{P_{\infty}}},

    and there is a 𝒯\mathcal{T}-cofinal branch bb such that Fib𝒯F\subseteq i^{\mathcal{T}}_{b}, and ib𝒯(δ0P)=δ0Pi^{\mathcal{T}}_{b}(\delta_{0}^{P_{\infty}})=\delta_{0}^{\mathcal{M}_{\infty}^{P_{\infty}}} (so bb is intercomputable with FF, and note that by amenability of 𝒱\mathscr{V}, FF is amenable to PP_{\infty}, and hence so is bb),

  7. 7.

    ρ1𝒱=δ0P\rho_{1}^{\mathscr{V}}=\delta_{0}^{P_{\infty}} and p1𝒱=p_{1}^{\mathscr{V}}=\emptyset and δ0P\delta_{0}^{P_{\infty}} is Woodin in 𝒥(1(𝒱))\mathcal{J}(\mathfrak{C}_{1}(\mathscr{V})), as witnessed by 𝔼P\mathbb{E}^{P_{\infty}},

  8. 8.

    PP is (𝒥(1(𝒱)),𝕃𝒱)(\mathcal{J}(\mathfrak{C}_{1}(\mathscr{V})),\mathbb{L}^{\mathscr{V}})-generic, where 𝕃𝒱\mathbb{L}^{\mathscr{V}} is defined over 𝒱\mathscr{V} as 𝕃\mathbb{L} above was defined over 𝒱1||γ𝒱1\mathscr{V}_{1}||\gamma^{\mathscr{V}_{1}}.

Remark 4.13.

Let C=1(𝒱)C=\mathfrak{C}_{1}(\mathscr{V}) and π:C𝒱\pi:C\to\mathscr{V} be the core map. Then

rg(π)=Hull1P(δ0PFδ0P).\mathrm{rg}(\pi)=\mathrm{Hull}_{1}^{P_{\infty}}(\delta_{0}^{P_{\infty}}\cup F``\delta_{0}^{P_{\infty}}). (22)

For we have ρ1𝒱=δ0P\rho_{1}^{\mathscr{V}}=\delta_{0}^{P_{\infty}} and p1𝒱=p_{1}^{\mathscr{V}}=\emptyset by hypothesis. So \supseteq is clear, and \subseteq is because for each α<δ0P\alpha<\delta_{0}^{P_{\infty}}, FαF{\upharpoonright}\alpha is in the hull on the right, by calculations like with the Zipper Lemma.

Now because δ0P\delta_{0}^{P_{\infty}} is Woodin in 𝒥(1(𝒱))\mathcal{J}(\mathfrak{C}_{1}(\mathscr{V})), and in particular regular, we have that 1(𝒱)\mathfrak{C}_{1}(\mathscr{V}) is sound with ρω1(𝒱)=δ0P\rho_{\omega}^{\mathfrak{C}_{1}(\mathscr{V})}=\delta_{0}^{P_{\infty}}, and in particular Vδ0P𝒥(1(𝒱))=Vδ0PPV_{\delta_{0}^{P_{\infty}}}^{\mathcal{J}(\mathfrak{C}_{1}(\mathscr{V}))}=V_{\delta_{0}^{P_{\infty}}}^{P_{\infty}}.

Note also that 𝕃\mathbb{L} is (lightface) Σ1𝒱1||γ𝒱1\Sigma_{1}^{\mathscr{V}_{1}||\gamma^{\mathscr{V}_{1}}}, and we use the natural Σ1\Sigma_{1} definition above to define 𝕃𝒱\mathbb{L}^{\mathscr{V}}, so 𝕃𝒱=𝕃1(𝒱)\mathbb{L}^{\mathscr{V}}=\mathbb{L}^{\mathfrak{C}_{1}(\mathscr{V})}. Moreover, like for 𝕃\mathbb{L}, 𝕃𝒱\mathbb{L}^{\mathscr{V}} is a sub-algebra of the extender algebra of PP_{\infty} at δ0P\delta_{0}^{P_{\infty}} and 𝒥(1(𝒱))\mathcal{J}(\mathfrak{C}_{1}(\mathscr{V}))\vDash𝕃𝒱\mathbb{L}^{\mathscr{V}} is a δ0P\delta_{0}^{P_{\infty}}-cc complete Boolean algebra”.

The definition is actually specified by an (infinite) first-order theory satisfied by 𝒱\mathscr{V}, modulo the wellfoundedness of 𝒱\mathscr{V}. (The theory needs to be infinite because of the assertion of Woodinness in 𝒥(1(𝒱))\mathcal{J}(\mathfrak{C}_{1}(\mathscr{V})) in condition 7.) To see this, observe that the (generic) existence of PP is first-order: Working in 𝒱\mathscr{V}, we can say that there is some condition of 𝕃𝒱\mathbb{L}^{\mathscr{V}} forcing over 1(𝒱)\mathfrak{C}_{1}(\mathscr{V}) that the generic object is a premouse PP such that the conditions above hold (and by the preceding discussion, all relevant antichains are in PP_{\infty}); a small subtlety here is that we need to refer to FF and the hull in (22) in order to talk about 1(𝒱)\mathfrak{C}_{1}(\mathscr{V}) and assert that it is isomorphic to 𝒱P\mathscr{V}^{P}; note that we can just talk about the relevant theories to assert this. (We don’t demand that P\mathcal{M}_{\infty}^{P_{\infty}} be wellfounded, but only what was asserted above, which gives that it is wellfounded through δ0P+1\delta_{0}^{\mathcal{M}_{\infty}^{P_{\infty}}}+1.)

Unsound base Vsps naturally arise from iterating sound ones.

Definition 4.14.

A Varsovian strategy premouse (Vsp) is a structure

𝒱=(𝒥α𝔼,𝔼,F)\mathscr{V}=(\mathcal{J}_{\alpha}^{\mathbb{E}},\mathbb{E},F)

for some sequence 𝔼\mathbb{E} of extenders, where either 𝒱\mathscr{V} is a premouse, or:

  1. 1.

    αOR\alpha\leq\mathrm{OR} and 𝒱\mathscr{V} is an amenable acceptable J-structure,

  2. 2.

    𝒱\mathscr{V} has a least Woodin cardinal δ0𝒱\delta_{0}^{\mathscr{V}}, and an initial segment 𝒱||γ\mathscr{V}||\gamma which is a base Vsp,

  3. 3.

    δ0𝒱<γ\delta_{0}^{\mathscr{V}}<\gamma, so δ0𝒱\delta_{0}^{\mathscr{V}} is the least Woodin of 𝒱||γ\mathscr{V}||\gamma,

  4. 4.

    if FF\neq\emptyset and γ<OR𝒱\gamma<\mathrm{OR}^{\mathscr{V}} then either:

    1. (a)

      𝒱\mathscr{V} satisfies the premouse axioms (for Jensen indexing) with respect to FF, and γ<crit(F)\gamma<{\rm crit}(F), or

    2. (b)

      We have:

      1. i.

        𝒱pv=(𝒥α𝔼,𝔼,)ZFC\mathscr{V}^{\mathrm{pv}}=(\mathcal{J}_{\alpha}^{\mathbb{E}},\mathbb{E},\emptyset)\vDash\mathrm{ZFC}^{-},

      2. ii.

        𝒱\mathscr{V} has largest cardinal μ\mu, which is inaccessible in 𝒱\mathscr{V} and a limit of cutpoints of 𝒱\mathscr{V} (where cutpoint is with regard to all kinds of extenders),

      3. iii.

        𝒩=𝒱pv\mathcal{N}=\mathcal{M}_{\infty}^{\mathscr{V}^{\mathrm{pv}}} is well-defined, and satisfies the axioms of a premouse (but is possibly illfounded) with a Woodin cardinal δ0𝒩\delta_{0}^{\mathcal{N}}, and is (OR𝒱+1)(\mathrm{OR}^{\mathscr{V}}+1)-wellfounded with δ0𝒩=OR𝒱\delta_{0}^{\mathcal{N}}=\mathrm{OR}^{\mathscr{V}},

      4. iv.

        𝒩|δ0𝒩\mathcal{N}|\delta_{0}^{\mathcal{N}} is a proper class of 𝒱pv\mathscr{V}^{\mathrm{pv}} and has least measurable μ\mu,

      5. v.

        FF is a cofinal Σ1\Sigma_{1}-elementary embedding F:𝒱|δ0𝒱𝒩|δ0𝒩F:\mathscr{V}|\delta_{0}^{\mathscr{V}}\to\mathcal{N}|\delta_{0}^{\mathcal{N}},

      6. vi.

        𝒩|δ0𝒩\mathcal{N}|\delta_{0}^{\mathcal{N}} is pseudo-normal iterate of 𝒱|δ0𝒱\mathscr{V}|\delta_{0}^{\mathscr{V}}, via tree 𝒯\mathcal{T}, and there is a 𝒯\mathcal{T}-cofinal branch bb such that Fib𝒯F\subseteq i^{\mathcal{T}}_{b} (hence bb is amenable to 𝒱\mathscr{V} and inter-definable with FF over 𝒱pv\mathscr{V}^{\mathrm{pv}}),

  5. 5.

    each proper segment of 𝒱\mathscr{V} is a sound Vsp (defining Vsp recursively), where the fine structural language for base Vsps and segments as in 4b is just that with symbols for ,𝔼,F\in,\mathbb{E},F,

  6. 6.

    some p𝕃𝒱=𝕃𝒱||γp\in\mathbb{L}^{\mathscr{V}}=\mathbb{L}^{\mathscr{V}||\gamma} forces that the generic object is a premouse NN of height δ0𝒱\delta_{0}^{\mathscr{V}} with 𝒱N=𝒱||γ\mathscr{V}^{N}=\mathscr{V}||\gamma, and there is an extension of NN to a premouse N+N^{+} such that 𝒱N+=𝒱\mathscr{V}^{N^{+}}=\mathscr{V} (and note then that N+N^{+} is level-by-level definable over 𝒱[N]\mathscr{V}[N], via inverse P-construction).

We write γ𝒱=γ\gamma^{\mathscr{V}}=\gamma above (if 𝒱\mathscr{V} is not a premouse).

Definition 4.15.

A Vsp 𝒱\mathscr{V} is 𝒱1\mathscr{V}_{1}-like iff it is proper class and in some set-generic extension, 𝒱=𝒱N\mathscr{V}=\mathscr{V}^{N} for some MswswM_{\mathrm{swsw}}-like premouse NN. (Note this is first-order over 𝒱\mathscr{V}.)

When talking about the extenders E𝔼+𝒱E\in\mathbb{E}_{+}^{\mathscr{V}}, for a Vsp 𝒱\mathscr{V}, we say that EE is short if 𝒱||lh(E)\mathscr{V}||{\rm lh}(E) satisfies the usual premouse axioms with respect to EE, and long otherwise; likewise for the corresponding segments. So 𝒱||γ𝒱\mathscr{V}||\gamma^{\mathscr{V}} is the least long segment.

We write =𝒱10\mathcal{M}_{\infty}=\mathscr{V}_{1}\downarrow 0. Let 𝒱\mathscr{V} be 𝒱1\mathscr{V}_{1}-like. We define 𝒱0\mathscr{V}\downarrow 0 analogously (first-order over 𝒱\mathscr{V} as in the proof of Lemma 4.10 part 3). In fact, let us define 𝒱0\mathscr{V}\downarrow 0 more generally, including the case that 𝒱\mathscr{V} is illfounded, but satisfies the first order properties of a 𝒱1\mathscr{V}_{1}-like structure. Also if NN is a premouse, let N0=NN\downarrow 0=N. We write 𝒱\mathscr{V}^{-} for (the premouse) 𝒱|δ0𝒱\mathscr{V}|\delta_{0}^{\mathscr{V}}. (So 𝒱1=|δ0\mathscr{V}_{1}^{-}=\mathcal{M}_{\infty}|\delta_{0}^{\mathcal{M}_{\infty}}.) We write Λ𝒱\Lambda^{\mathscr{V}} for the strategy for 𝒱0\mathscr{V}\downarrow 0 (for trees based on 𝒱\mathscr{V}^{-}) defined over 𝒱\mathscr{V} just as the corresponding restriction of Σ\Sigma_{\mathcal{M}_{\infty}} is defined over 𝒱1\mathscr{V}_{1}, via the proof of Lemma 4.9.

We write 𝒱1=𝒱(,)=𝒱(,δ)=𝒱(,e𝒱1)\mathscr{V}_{1}=\mathscr{V}(\mathcal{M}_{\infty},*)=\mathscr{V}(\mathcal{M}_{\infty},*{\upharpoonright}\delta_{\infty})=\mathscr{V}(\mathcal{M}_{\infty},e^{\mathscr{V}_{1}}). Given a pair (N,)(N,*^{\prime}) or (N,δ)(N,*^{\prime}{\upharpoonright}\delta) or (N,e)(N,e) where NN is MswswM_{\mathrm{swsw}}-like and the pair has similar first-order properties as does (,)(\mathcal{M}_{\infty},*) or (,δ)(\mathcal{M}_{\infty},*{\upharpoonright}\delta_{\infty}) or (,e𝒱1)(\mathcal{M}_{\infty},e^{\mathscr{V}_{1}}) respectively, we define 𝒱(N,)\mathscr{V}(N,*^{\prime}) or 𝒱(N,δ)\mathscr{V}(N,*^{\prime}{\upharpoonright}\delta) or 𝒱(N,e)\mathscr{V}(N,e) analogously (via the proof of Lemma 4.10 part 2).

4.11 The action of MM-iteration on \mathcal{M}_{\infty}

We now aim to extend Lemma 4.9, analyzing the nature of N\mathcal{M}_{\infty}^{N} for iterates NN of MM, and the partial iterability of N\mathcal{M}_{\infty}^{N} in NN.

Lemma 4.15.

Let NN be any non-dropping Σ\Sigma-iterate of MM. Let PNP\in\mathscr{F}^{N}. Let

P¯=cHullP(δ0PN).\bar{P}=\mathrm{cHull}^{P}(\delta_{0}^{P}\cup\mathscr{I}^{N}).

Then P¯\bar{P} is a δ0P¯\delta_{0}^{\overline{P}}-sound non-dropping Σ\Sigma-iterate of MM, P¯|δ0P¯=P|δ0P\bar{P}|\delta_{0}^{\overline{P}}=P|\delta_{0}^{P}, and letting π:P¯P\pi:\bar{P}\to P be the uncollapse map, then πP¯=N\pi``\mathscr{I}^{\bar{P}}=\mathscr{I}^{N}.414141But if NN is not δ0N\delta_{0}^{N}-sound then P¯\bar{P} is not a ΣN\Sigma_{N}-iterate of NN.

Proof.

We have P|δ0P=Mα𝒯|δ0Mα𝒯P|\delta_{0}^{P}=M^{\mathcal{T}}_{\alpha}|\delta_{0}^{M^{\mathcal{T}}_{\alpha}} for some tree 𝒯\mathcal{T} via Σ\Sigma, where [0,α]𝒯[0,\alpha]_{\mathcal{T}} does not drop; this is because the Q-structures used to guide the short tree strategy computing PP are correct. But P¯|δ0P¯=P|δ0P\bar{P}|\delta_{0}^{\bar{P}}=P|\delta_{0}^{P} and P¯\bar{P} is an iterable, δ0P¯\delta_{0}^{\bar{P}}-sound, MswswM_{\mathrm{swsw}}-like premouse, and with α\alpha above minimal, comparison gives P¯=Mα𝒯\bar{P}=M^{\mathcal{T}}_{\alpha}. Finally note that =π1N\mathscr{I}=\pi^{-1}``\mathscr{I}^{N} is a club class of generating indiscernibles for P¯\bar{P}, so =P¯\mathscr{I}=\mathscr{I}^{\bar{P}}. ∎

Definition 4.16.

Let NN be a non-dropping Σ\Sigma-iterate of MM. Define (ext¯)N(\mathcal{M}_{\infty}^{\overline{\mathrm{ext}}})_{N} as the direct limit of the iterates P¯\bar{P}, for PNP\in\mathscr{F}^{N} (the notation P¯\bar{P} as in Lemma 4.11). (Cf. Definition 4.7.) For PNP\in\mathscr{F}^{N} let πP¯P:P¯P\pi_{\bar{P}P}:\bar{P}\to P be the uncollapse map and

HP=Hull1P(δ0PN)=rg(πP¯P).H^{P}=\mathrm{Hull}_{1}^{P}(\delta_{0}^{P}\cup\mathscr{I}^{N})=\mathrm{rg}(\pi_{\bar{P}P}).

Suppose further that NN is κ0N\kappa_{0}^{N}-sound. Let αOR\alpha\in\mathrm{OR} and PNP\in\mathscr{F}^{N}. We say that α\alpha is (P,N)(P,\mathscr{F}^{N})-stable iff whenever PQNP\preceq Q\in\mathscr{F}^{N}, we have αHQ\alpha\in H^{Q} and

πQ¯QiP¯Q¯πP¯P1(α)=α.\pi_{\bar{Q}Q}\circ i_{\bar{P}\bar{Q}}\circ\pi_{\bar{P}P}^{-1}(\alpha)=\alpha.

The definition of stability above is more complicated than the version for MM, because it can be that PQNP\leq Q\in\mathscr{F}^{N} but QQ is not actually an iterate of PP (although Q|δ0QQ|\delta_{0}^{Q} is an iterate of P|δ0PP|\delta_{0}^{P}).

Lemma 4.16.

Let NN be a non-dropping Σ\Sigma-iterate of MM. Then:

  1. 1.

    P=(ext¯)NP=(\mathcal{M}_{\infty}^{\overline{\mathrm{ext}}})_{N} is a δ0P\delta_{0}^{P}-sound non-dropping Σ\Sigma-iterate of MM.

  2. 2.

    N|δN=P|δ0P\mathcal{M}_{\infty}^{N}|\delta_{\infty}^{N}=P|\delta_{0}^{P}.

  3. 3.

    If M|κ0MNM|\kappa_{0}^{M}\triangleleft N then |δN\mathcal{M}_{\infty}|\delta_{\infty}\in N and PP is a Σ\Sigma_{\mathcal{M}_{\infty}}-iterate of \mathcal{M}_{\infty}.

Proof.

Part 1 is immediate from the definitions. Part 2 follows from Lemma 4.11, since infinitely many indiscernibles are fixed by the iteration maps. For part 3, note that because M|κ0MNM|\kappa_{0}^{M}\triangleleft N and NN is a non-dropping iterate, in fact M|κ0+MNM|\kappa_{0}^{+M}\triangleleft N, so |δN\mathcal{M}_{\infty}|\delta_{\infty}\in N, and then it is an easy consequence of part 1. ∎

Lemma 4.16.

Let NN be a κ0N\kappa_{0}^{N}-sound non-dropping Σ\Sigma-iterate of MM. Then:

  1. 1.

    For each PQNP\preceq Q\in\mathscr{F}^{N}, we have HPORHQORH^{P}\cap\mathrm{OR}\subseteq H^{Q}\cap\mathrm{OR}.

  2. 2.

    For each αOR\alpha\in\mathrm{OR} there is PNP\in\mathscr{F}^{N} such that α\alpha is (P,N)(P,\mathscr{F}^{N})-stable.

Proof.

Part 1: We in fact that HPOR=Hull1N(δ0PN)H^{P}\cap\mathrm{OR}=\mathrm{Hull}_{1}^{N}(\delta_{0}^{P}\cup\mathscr{I}^{N}) (which immediately gives HPHQH^{P}\subseteq H^{Q}). This is just by extender algebra genericity and definability of P|δ0PP|\delta_{0}^{P} over N|δ0PN|\delta_{0}^{P}.

Part 2: Since NN is κ0N\kappa_{0}^{N}-sound, we can fix sNs\in\vec{\mathscr{I}^{N}} and β<κ0N\beta<\kappa_{0}^{N} and a term tt such that α=tN(s,β)\alpha=t^{N}(s,\beta). Then taking PNP\in\mathscr{F}^{N} with β<δ0P\beta<\delta_{0}^{P}, we get αHP\alpha\in H^{P}. Now since (ext¯)N(\mathcal{M}_{\infty}^{\overline{\mathrm{ext}}})^{N} is wellfounded, it suffices to see that

πQ¯QiP¯Q¯πP¯P1(α)α\pi_{\bar{Q}Q}\circ i_{\bar{P}\bar{Q}}\circ\pi_{\bar{P}P}^{-1}(\alpha)\geq\alpha

whenever PQNP\preceq Q\in\mathscr{F}^{N} and αHP\alpha\in H^{P}. So let sNs\in\vec{\mathscr{I}^{N}} with αHsP\alpha\in H^{P}_{s}. Then πPs,Qs(α)α\pi_{Ps,Qs}(\alpha)\geq\alpha whenever PQNP\preceq Q\in\mathscr{F}^{N}, because MM satisfies the same about iMN1(s)i_{MN}^{-1}(s) (because whenever RSMR\preceq S\in\mathscr{F}^{M}, SS is actually an iterate of RR, and these iterates are δ0\delta_{0}-sound, etc). But note that

πPs,Qs(α)=πQ¯QiP¯Q¯πP¯P1(α)\pi_{Ps,Qs}(\alpha)=\pi_{\bar{Q}Q}\circ i_{\bar{P}\bar{Q}}\circ\pi_{\bar{P}P}^{-1}(\alpha)

(because any generic branch witnessing the definition of πPs,QsN\pi_{Ps,Qs}^{N} must move the relevant theory of indiscernibles and elements <γsP{<\gamma^{P}_{s}} correctly, since these agree appropriately between P,P¯P,\bar{P} and Q,Q¯Q,\bar{Q}). This gives the desired conclusion. ∎

The following lemma is proved like a similar fact in [16], integrated with part of the argument for [8, Lemma 2.9]:

Lemma 4.16.

Let NN be a κ0N\kappa_{0}^{N}-sound non-dropping Σ\Sigma-iterate of MM and NN^{\prime} a κ0N\kappa_{0}^{N^{\prime}}-sound non-dropping ΣN\Sigma_{N}-iterate of NN. Let N¯\bar{N} be the δ0N\delta_{0}^{N}-core of NN. Then:

  1. 1.

    =M\mathscr{I}^{\mathcal{M}_{\infty}}=\mathscr{I}^{M} and iMM=id=Mi_{M\mathcal{M}_{\infty}}{\upharpoonright}\mathscr{I}^{M}=\mathrm{id}=*{\upharpoonright}\mathscr{I}^{M},

  2. 2.

    N=N\mathscr{I}^{\mathcal{M}_{\infty}^{N}}=\mathscr{I}^{N} and NN=id*^{N}{\upharpoonright}\mathscr{I}^{N}=\mathrm{id},

  3. 3.

    N=iMN()=(ext¯)N\mathcal{M}_{\infty}^{N}=i_{MN}(\mathcal{M}_{\infty})=(\mathcal{M}_{\infty}^{\overline{\mathrm{ext}}})_{N} is a δ0N\delta_{0}^{\mathcal{M}_{\infty}^{N}}-sound ΣN¯\Sigma_{\bar{N}}-iterate of N¯\bar{N}.

  4. 4.

    If N|κ0NNN|\kappa_{0}^{N}\triangleleft N^{\prime} then

    1. (a)

      N\mathcal{M}_{\infty}^{N^{\prime}} is a ΣN\Sigma_{\mathcal{M}_{\infty}^{N}}-iterate of N\mathcal{M}_{\infty}^{N}, and

    2. (b)

      iNNNi_{NN^{\prime}}{\upharpoonright}\mathcal{M}_{\infty}^{N} is just the ΣN\Sigma_{\mathcal{M}_{\infty}^{N}}-iteration map NN\mathcal{M}_{\infty}^{N}\to\mathcal{M}_{\infty}^{N^{\prime}}.

  5. 5.

    If N¯N\bar{N}\neq N then N\mathcal{M}_{\infty}^{N} is not a ΣN\Sigma_{N}-iterate of NN.

Proof.

Part 1: We have =iMM\mathscr{I}^{\mathcal{M}_{\infty}}=i_{M\mathcal{M}_{\infty}}``\mathscr{I}^{M}, and \mathcal{M}_{\infty} is δ0\delta_{0}^{\mathcal{M}_{\infty}}-sound. Suppose κM\kappa\in\mathscr{I}^{M} is least such that iM(κ)>κi_{M\mathcal{M}_{\infty}}(\kappa)>\kappa, fix a tuple κ\vec{\kappa}\in\mathscr{I}^{\mathcal{M}_{\infty}} and a term tt and α<δ0\alpha<\delta_{0}^{\mathcal{M}_{\infty}} such that κ=t(κ,α)\kappa=t^{\mathcal{M}_{\infty}}(\vec{\kappa},\alpha), and note we may assume that κ\κM\(κ+1)\vec{\kappa}\backslash\kappa\in\mathscr{I}^{M}\backslash(\kappa+1) by shifting this part up, but since κκM\vec{\kappa}\cap\kappa\subseteq\mathscr{I}^{M} and \mathcal{M}_{\infty} is a lightface MM-class, this gives a contradiction.

Part 3: Note that Lemma 4.11 applies. Like in §2, we will define an elementary χ:N(ext¯)N\chi:\mathcal{M}_{\infty}^{N}\to(\mathcal{M}_{\infty}^{\overline{\mathrm{ext}}})_{N} and show that χ=id\chi=\mathrm{id}. We can cover 𝒟N\mathscr{D}^{N} by with indices of the form (P,u)(P,u) with u[N]<ωu\in[\mathscr{I}^{N}]^{<\omega}. For given any (Q,s)𝒟N(Q,s)\in\mathscr{D}^{N}, by Lemma 4.11, we can fix PNP\in\mathscr{F}^{N} such that ss is (P,N)(P,\mathscr{F}^{N})-stable (see Definition 4.16) and QPQ\preceq P, and with δ0P\delta_{0}^{P} large enough that there is u[N]<ωu\in[\mathscr{I}^{N}]^{<\omega} such that sHuPs\in H^{P}_{u}, which suffices. Because of this covering, we can define χ:N(ext¯)N\chi:\mathcal{M}_{\infty}^{N}\to(\mathcal{M}_{\infty}^{\overline{\mathrm{ext}}})_{N} in the natural way; i.e. for each such (P,u)(P,u) and xHuPx\in H^{P}_{u}, set χ(πPu,N(x))=iP¯N(πP¯P1(x))\chi(\pi_{Pu,\infty}^{N}(x))=i_{\bar{P}\mathcal{M}_{\infty}^{N}}(\pi_{\bar{P}P}^{-1}(x)); note we have u,xrg(πP¯P)u,x\in\mathrm{rg}(\pi_{\bar{P}P}). It is now easy to see that N=(ext¯)N\mathcal{M}_{\infty}^{N}=(\mathcal{M}_{\infty}^{\overline{\mathrm{ext}}})_{N} and χ=id\chi=\mathrm{id}.

Part 2: By part 1 and since iMNM=Ni_{MN}``\mathscr{I}^{M}=\mathscr{I}^{N}, we get NN=id*^{N}{\upharpoonright}\mathscr{I}^{N}=\mathrm{id}. And by part 3 and its proof, N=Hull1N(δ0N(NN))\mathcal{M}_{\infty}^{N}=\mathrm{Hull}_{1}^{\mathcal{M}_{\infty}^{N}}(\delta_{0}^{\mathcal{M}_{\infty}^{N}}\cup(*^{N}``\mathscr{I}^{N})). Since N\mathcal{M}_{\infty}^{N} is also a lightface NN-class, N\mathscr{I}^{N} are model theoretic indiscernibles for N\mathcal{M}_{\infty}^{N}. Therefore N=N\mathscr{I}^{\mathcal{M}_{\infty}^{N}}=\mathscr{I}^{N}.

Part 4: 4a is an easy consequence of the fact that N\mathcal{M}_{\infty}^{N} and N\mathcal{M}_{\infty}^{N^{\prime}} are δN\delta_{\infty}^{N}- and δN\delta_{\infty}^{N^{\prime}}-sound respectively. For 4b, we argue partly like in [8, Lemma 2.9(a)], but somewhat differently.424242 Moreover, the proof of [8, Lemma 2.9(a)] has a bug: with notation as there, it talks about iteration maps πj(N),N\pi_{j(N),N^{*}} and πN,j()\pi_{N^{*},j(\mathcal{M}_{\infty})}, with the implication that j()j(\mathcal{M}_{\infty}) is in fact an iterate of j(N)j(N), but this is not true, as j(N)j(N) is not δ0j(N)\delta_{0}^{j(N)}-sound, whereas j()j(\mathcal{M}_{\infty}) is δ0j()\delta_{0}^{j(\mathcal{M}_{\infty})}-sound. So, note that by the preceding parts, N\mathcal{M}_{\infty}^{N^{\prime}} is indeed an iterate of N\mathcal{M}_{\infty}^{N}, and iNNN=iNNNi_{NN^{\prime}}{\upharpoonright}\mathscr{I}^{\mathcal{M}_{\infty}^{N}}=i_{\mathcal{M}_{\infty}^{N}\mathcal{M}_{\infty}^{N^{\prime}}}{\upharpoonright}\mathscr{I}^{\mathcal{M}_{\infty}^{N}}, so it just remains to see that

iNNδ0N=iNNδ0N.i_{NN^{\prime}}{\upharpoonright}\delta_{0}^{\mathcal{M}_{\infty}^{N}}=i_{\mathcal{M}_{\infty}^{N}\mathcal{M}_{\infty}^{N^{\prime}}}{\upharpoonright}\delta_{0}^{\mathcal{M}_{\infty}^{N}}.

So let α<δ0N\alpha<\delta_{0}^{\mathcal{M}_{\infty}^{N}}. Let s[N]<ω=[N]<ωs\in[\mathscr{I}^{\mathcal{M}_{\infty}^{N}}]^{<\omega}=[\mathscr{I}^{N}]^{<\omega} be such that α<γsN\alpha<\gamma^{\mathcal{M}_{\infty}^{N}}_{s}. Fix PNP\in\mathscr{F}^{N} with some α¯<γsP\bar{\alpha}<\gamma^{P}_{s} such that πPs,N(α¯)=α\pi_{Ps,\infty}^{N}(\bar{\alpha})=\alpha. Note that N\mathcal{M}_{\infty}^{N} is a ΣP¯\Sigma_{\bar{P}}-iterate of P¯\bar{P} and

iP¯N(α¯)=α.i_{\bar{P}\mathcal{M}_{\infty}^{N}}(\bar{\alpha})=\alpha. (23)

Now

iNN(α)=πPs,N(α¯)i_{NN^{\prime}}(\alpha)=\pi^{N^{\prime}}_{P^{\prime}s^{\prime},\infty}(\bar{\alpha})

where P=iNN(P)NP^{\prime}=i_{NN^{\prime}}(P)\in\mathscr{F}^{N^{\prime}} and s=iNN(s)Ns^{\prime}=i_{NN^{\prime}}(s)\in\vec{\mathscr{I}^{N^{\prime}}}. But then with the map χ\chi defined as earlier, but for NN^{\prime} instead of NN,

iNN(α)=χ(πPs,N(α¯))=iP¯N(πP¯P1(α¯))=iP¯N(α¯)=iNN(α),i_{NN^{\prime}}(\alpha)=\chi(\pi^{N^{\prime}}_{P^{\prime}s^{\prime},\infty}(\bar{\alpha}))=i_{\overline{P^{\prime}}\mathcal{M}_{\infty}^{N^{\prime}}}(\pi^{-1}_{\overline{P^{\prime}}P^{\prime}}(\bar{\alpha}))=i_{\bar{P}\mathcal{M}_{\infty}^{N^{\prime}}}(\bar{\alpha})=i_{\mathcal{M}_{\infty}^{N}\mathcal{M}_{\infty}^{N^{\prime}}}(\alpha),

using that χ=id\chi=\mathrm{id}, P¯=P¯\overline{P^{\prime}}=\bar{P}, α¯<crit(πP¯P)\bar{\alpha}<{\rm crit}(\pi_{\overline{P^{\prime}}P^{\prime}}), and line (23).

Part 5: If N¯N\bar{N}\neq N then NN is not δ0N\delta_{0}^{N}-sound, but then any non-dropping iterate OO of NN is non δ0O\delta_{0}^{O}-sound, so O(ext¯)N=NO\neq(\mathcal{M}_{\infty}^{\overline{\mathrm{ext}}})_{N}=\mathcal{M}_{\infty}^{N}. ∎

Note that with the preceding lemma, we have completed the proofs of Lemmas 4.3.2, 4.3.2 and 4.9.

4.12 Iterability of 𝒱1\mathscr{V}_{1}

In this subsection we will define a normal iteration strategy Σ𝒱1\Sigma_{\mathscr{V}_{1}} for 𝒱1\mathscr{V}_{1} in VV. We will first define and analyze the action of Σ𝒱1\Sigma_{\mathscr{V}_{1}} for trees based on |δ\mathcal{M}_{\infty}|\delta_{\infty}.

4.12.1 Tree translation from MM to 𝒱1\mathscr{V}_{1}

The iteration strategy for 𝒱1\mathscr{V}_{1} will be tightly connected to that for MM, as we describe now. But first the basic notion under consideration:

Definition 4.17.

Let NN be a 𝒱1\mathscr{V}_{1}-like Vsp. A 0-maximal iteration tree 𝒯\mathcal{T} on NN of length λ1\lambda\geq 1 is a system

(<𝒯,Mα,mαα<λ,Eαα+1<λ)\left(<_{\mathcal{T}},\left<M_{\alpha},m_{\alpha}\right>_{\alpha<\lambda},\left<E_{\alpha}\right>_{\alpha+1<\lambda}\right)

with the usual properties, except that when EαE_{\alpha} is a long extender (which is allowed), then pred𝒯(α+1)\mathrm{pred}^{\mathcal{T}}(\alpha+1) is the least βα\beta\leq\alpha such that [0,β]𝒯[0,\beta]_{\mathcal{T}} does not drop and δ0Mβ𝒯<lh(Eα𝒯)\delta_{0}^{M^{\mathcal{T}}_{\beta}}<{\rm lh}(E^{\mathcal{T}}_{\alpha}).

We say that 𝒯\mathcal{T} is short-normal iff 𝒯\mathcal{T} uses no long extenders.

Iteration strategies and iterability for NN are now defined in the obvious manner.

Definition 4.18.

A short-normal tree on a 𝒱1\mathscr{V}_{1}-like Vsp 𝒱\mathscr{V} is a 0-maximal tree that uses no long extenders. Note that a short-normal tree is of the form 𝒯^𝒮\mathcal{T}\ \widehat{\ }\ \mathcal{S}, where 𝒯\mathcal{T} is based on 𝒱|δ0𝒱\mathscr{V}|\delta_{0}^{\mathscr{V}}, and either

  1. (i)

    [𝒯\mathcal{T} has limit length or b𝒯b^{\mathcal{T}} drops] and 𝒮=\mathcal{S}=\emptyset, or

  2. (ii)

    𝒯\mathcal{T} has successor length, b𝒯b^{\mathcal{T}} does not drop and 𝒮\mathcal{S} is above δ0M𝒯0\delta_{0}^{M^{\mathcal{T}_{0}}_{\infty}}.

Say that 𝒯,𝒮\mathcal{T},\mathcal{S} are the lower, upper components respectively.

Definition 4.19.

Let NN be MswswM_{\mathrm{swsw}}-like. An iteration tree 𝒯\mathcal{T} on 𝒱1N\mathscr{V}_{1}^{N} is 𝒱1N\mathscr{V}_{1}^{N}-translatable iff:

  1. 1.

    𝒯\mathcal{T} is 0-maximal, and

  2. 2.

    κ0+Mα𝒯<lh(Eα𝒯)\kappa_{0}^{+M^{\mathcal{T}}_{\alpha}}<{\rm lh}(E^{\mathcal{T}}_{\alpha}) for all α+1<lh(𝒯)\alpha+1<{\rm lh}(\mathcal{T}) such that [0,α]𝒯𝒟𝒯=[0,\alpha]_{\mathcal{T}}\cap\mathscr{D}^{\mathcal{T}}=\emptyset.

Remark 4.19.

Under 0-maximality, condition 2 holds iff κ0+Mη𝒯<lh(Eη𝒯)\kappa_{0}^{+M^{\mathcal{T}}_{\eta}}<{\rm lh}(E^{\mathcal{T}}_{\eta}) for η=0\eta=0 and for all limits η\eta such that η+1<lh(𝒯)\eta+1<{\rm lh}(\mathcal{T}) and [0,η]𝒯𝒟𝒯=[0,\eta]_{\mathcal{T}}\cap\mathscr{D}^{\mathcal{T}}=\emptyset and i0η𝒯(κ0N)=δ(𝒯η)i^{\mathcal{T}}_{0\eta}(\kappa_{0}^{N})=\delta(\mathcal{T}{\upharpoonright}\eta). This follows easily from the fact that lh(Eα𝒯)<lh(Eβ𝒯){\rm lh}(E^{\mathcal{T}}_{\alpha})<{\rm lh}(E^{\mathcal{T}}_{\beta}) for α<β\alpha<\beta (using Jensen indexing).

Definition 4.20.

Let NN be MswswM_{\mathrm{swsw}}-like. Let 𝒯\mathcal{T} on NN be 𝒱1N\mathscr{V}_{1}^{N}-translatable. The 𝒱1N\mathscr{V}_{1}^{N}-translation of 𝒯\mathcal{T} is the 0-maximal tree 𝒰\mathcal{U} on 𝒱1N\mathscr{V}_{1}^{N} such that:

  1. 1.

    lh(𝒰)=lh(𝒯){\rm lh}(\mathcal{U})={\rm lh}(\mathcal{T}) and 𝒰,𝒯\mathcal{U},\mathcal{T} have the same tree, drop and degree structure,

  2. 2.

    lh(Eα𝒰)=lh(Eα𝒯){\rm lh}(E^{\mathcal{U}}_{\alpha})={\rm lh}(E^{\mathcal{T}}_{\alpha}) for all α+1<lh(𝒯)\alpha+1<{\rm lh}(\mathcal{T}).

Remark 4.20.

Let NN be MswswM_{\mathrm{swsw}}-like. Let 𝒯\mathcal{T} be a tree on NN and let α<𝒯ε+1𝒯β\alpha<_{\mathcal{T}}\varepsilon+1\leq_{\mathcal{T}}\beta be such that [0,α]𝒯[0,\alpha]_{\mathcal{T}} does not drop, ε+1𝒟𝒯\varepsilon+1\in\mathscr{D}^{\mathcal{T}}, pred𝒯(ε+1)=α\mathrm{pred}^{\mathcal{T}}(\varepsilon+1)=\alpha and κ0+Mα𝒯<crit(Eε𝒯)\kappa_{0}^{+M^{\mathcal{T}}_{\alpha}}<{\rm crit}(E^{\mathcal{T}}_{\varepsilon}). Note that

κ0+Mα𝒯<γ=γ𝒱1(Mα𝒯)<ξ<crit(Eε𝒯)\kappa_{0}^{+M^{\mathcal{T}}_{\alpha}}<\gamma=\gamma^{\mathscr{V}_{1}(M^{\mathcal{T}}_{\alpha})}<\xi<{\rm crit}(E^{\mathcal{T}}_{\varepsilon})

where ξ\xi is the least Mα𝒯|κ0+Mα𝒯M^{\mathcal{T}}_{\alpha}|\kappa_{0}^{+M^{\mathcal{T}}_{\alpha}}-admissible. Note here that 𝒱1Mβ𝒯=𝒱1(Mβ𝒯)\mathscr{V}_{1}^{M^{\mathcal{T}}_{\beta}}=\mathscr{V}_{1}(M^{\mathcal{T}}_{\beta}) is the set-sized model 𝒱\mathscr{V} such that 𝒱||γ=𝒱1Mα𝒯||γ\mathscr{V}||\gamma=\mathscr{V}_{1}^{M^{\mathcal{T}}_{\alpha}}||\gamma and above γ\gamma, 𝔼+𝒱\mathbb{E}_{+}^{\mathscr{V}} is the level-by-level translation of 𝔼+(Mβ𝒯)\mathbb{E}_{+}(M^{\mathcal{T}}_{\beta}). Note that because γ<OR𝒱1(Mβ𝒯)\gamma<\mathrm{OR}^{\mathscr{V}_{1}(M^{\mathcal{T}}_{\beta})}, Mβ𝒯M^{\mathcal{T}}_{\beta} is a κ0+Mα𝒯\kappa_{0}^{+M^{\mathcal{T}}_{\alpha}}-cc forcing extension of 𝒱1(Mβ𝒯)\mathscr{V}_{1}(M^{\mathcal{T}}_{\beta}).

Lemma 4.20.

Let 𝒯\mathcal{T} on NN be 𝒱1N\mathscr{V}_{1}^{N}-translatable, where NN is MswswM_{\mathrm{swsw}}-like. Then:

  1. 1.

    The 𝒱1N\mathscr{V}_{1}^{N}-translation 𝒰\mathcal{U} of 𝒯\mathcal{T} exists and is unique.

  2. 2.

    Mα𝒰=𝒱1Mα𝒯M^{\mathcal{U}}_{\alpha}=\mathscr{V}_{1}^{M^{\mathcal{T}}_{\alpha}} and degα𝒰=degα𝒯\deg^{\mathcal{U}}_{\alpha}=\deg^{\mathcal{T}}_{\alpha} and γMα𝒰<OR(Mα𝒰)\gamma^{M^{\mathcal{U}}_{\alpha}}<\mathrm{OR}(M^{\mathcal{U}}_{\alpha}) for all α<lh(𝒯)\alpha<{\rm lh}(\mathcal{T}).

  3. 3.

    iαβ𝒰=iαβ𝒯Mα𝒰i^{\mathcal{U}}_{\alpha\beta}=i^{\mathcal{T}}_{\alpha\beta}{\upharpoonright}M^{\mathcal{U}}_{\alpha} for all α<𝒯β\alpha<_{\mathcal{T}}\beta such that (α,β]𝒯(\alpha,\beta]_{\mathcal{T}} does not drop.

  4. 4.

    Mα+1𝒰=𝒱1Mα+1𝒯M^{*\mathcal{U}}_{\alpha+1}=\mathscr{V}_{1}^{M^{*\mathcal{T}}_{\alpha+1}} for all α+1<lh(𝒯)\alpha+1<{\rm lh}(\mathcal{T}).

  5. 5.

    iα+1𝒰=iα+1𝒯Mα+1𝒰i^{*\mathcal{U}}_{\alpha+1}=i^{*\mathcal{T}}_{\alpha+1}{\upharpoonright}M^{*\mathcal{U}}_{\alpha+1} for all α+1<lh(𝒯)\alpha+1<{\rm lh}(\mathcal{T}).

Proof.

This is partly via the usual translation of iteration trees between models and P-constructions thereof. However, there is a new feature here, when α+1<lh(𝒯)\alpha+1<{\rm lh}(\mathcal{T}) and is such that [0,α+1]𝒯[0,\alpha+1]_{\mathcal{T}} does not drop and letting β=pred𝒯(α+1)\beta=\mathrm{pred}^{\mathcal{T}}(\alpha+1), then crit(Eα𝒯)=κ=κ0(Mβ𝒯){\rm crit}(E^{\mathcal{T}}_{\alpha})=\kappa=\kappa_{0}(M^{\mathcal{T}}_{\beta}), so consider this situation.

Then Eα𝒰E^{\mathcal{U}}_{\alpha} is long with space δ=δ0(Mβ𝒰)=κ0+Mβ𝒯\delta=\delta_{0}(M^{\mathcal{U}}_{\beta})=\kappa_{0}^{+M^{\mathcal{T}}_{\beta}}, and Eα𝒰=Eα𝒯(Mβ𝒰|δ)E^{\mathcal{U}}_{\alpha}=E^{\mathcal{T}}_{\alpha}{\upharpoonright}(M^{\mathcal{U}}_{\beta}|\delta) and [0,β]𝒰[0,\beta]_{\mathcal{U}} does not drop, and Mβ𝒰=𝒱1(Mβ𝒯)M^{\mathcal{U}}_{\beta}=\mathscr{V}_{1}(M^{\mathcal{T}}_{\beta}). Let (a,f)(a,f) be such that fMβ𝒯f\in M^{\mathcal{T}}_{\beta} and a[ν(Eα𝒯)]<ωa\in[\nu(E^{\mathcal{T}}_{\alpha})]^{<\omega} and

f:[κ]|a|Mβ𝒰=𝒱1(Mβ𝒯).f:[\kappa]^{|a|}\to M^{\mathcal{U}}_{\beta}=\mathscr{V}_{1}(M^{\mathcal{T}}_{\beta}).

We need some (b,g)(b,g) with gMβ𝒰g\in M^{\mathcal{U}}_{\beta} and b[lh(Eα𝒰)]<ωb\in[{\rm lh}(E^{\mathcal{U}}_{\alpha})]^{<\omega} such that aba\subseteq b and fab(u)=g(u)f^{ab}(u)=g(u) for (Eα𝒯)b(E^{\mathcal{T}}_{\alpha})_{b}-measure one many uu. We may assume rg(f)OR\mathrm{rg}(f)\subseteq\mathrm{OR}.

If rg(f)δ\mathrm{rg}(f)\subseteq\delta, the existence of (b,g)(b,g) is just because Eα𝒰E^{\mathcal{U}}_{\alpha} is the restriction of Eα𝒯E^{\mathcal{T}}_{\alpha}, and this restriction is cofinal in lh(Eα𝒯){\rm lh}(E^{\mathcal{T}}_{\alpha}). In general we will reduce to this case.

Now Mβ𝒯M^{\mathcal{T}}_{\beta} is a δ\delta-cc forcing extension of Mβ𝒰M^{\mathcal{U}}_{\beta}, so rg(f)X\mathrm{rg}(f)\subseteq X for some XMβ𝒰X\in M^{\mathcal{U}}_{\beta}, where XX has cardinality <δ{<\delta} in Mβ𝒰M^{\mathcal{U}}_{\beta}. Let η\eta be the ordertype of XX, so η<δ\eta<\delta, let π:Xη\pi:X\to\eta be the collapse, and let f~=πf\widetilde{f}=\pi\circ f. So f~Mβ𝒯\widetilde{f}\in M^{\mathcal{T}}_{\beta} and rg(f~)δ\mathrm{rg}(\widetilde{f})\subseteq\delta, so we get a corresponding pair (b,g~)(b,\widetilde{g}), with g~Mβ𝒰\widetilde{g}\in M^{\mathcal{U}}_{\beta}. Letting g=π1g~g=\pi^{-1}\circ\widetilde{g}, then gMβ𝒰g\in M^{\mathcal{U}}_{\beta} and (b,g)(b,g) works. ∎

4.12.2 Trees based on |δ\mathcal{M}_{\infty}|\delta_{\infty}

We now transfer trees on \mathcal{M}_{\infty}, based on |δ\mathcal{M}_{\infty}|\delta_{\infty}, to trees on 𝒱1\mathscr{V}_{1}.

Definition 4.21.

Write Σ,𝒱1\Sigma_{\mathcal{M}_{\infty},\mathscr{V}_{1}^{-}} for the normal strategy for \mathcal{M}_{\infty} for trees based on 𝒱1\mathscr{V}_{1}^{-}, induced by Σ\Sigma_{\mathcal{M}_{\infty}}. We use analogous notation ΣN,N|α\Sigma_{N,N|\alpha} more generally. Let Ψ𝒱1,𝒱1\Psi_{\mathscr{V}_{1},\mathscr{V}_{1}^{-}} denote the putative normal strategy for trees on 𝒱1\mathscr{V}_{1} based on 𝒱1\mathscr{V}_{1}^{-}, induced by Σ,𝒱1\Sigma_{\mathcal{M}_{\infty},\mathscr{V}_{1}^{-}}. This makes sense by Lemma 4.6.

Remark 4.21.

Let 𝒰\mathcal{U} be a putative tree on 𝒱1\mathscr{V}_{1}, based on 𝒱1\mathscr{V}_{1}^{-}, via Ψ𝒱1,𝒱1\Psi_{\mathscr{V}_{1},\mathscr{V}_{1}^{-}}. Let α<lh(𝒰)\alpha<{\rm lh}(\mathcal{U}). Suppose [0,α]𝒰[0,\alpha]_{\mathcal{U}} does not drop. Then Mα𝒰0=i0α𝒰(){M^{\mathcal{U}}_{\alpha}\downarrow 0}=i^{\mathcal{U}}_{0\alpha}(\mathcal{M}_{\infty}), and if Mα𝒰M^{\mathcal{U}}_{\alpha} is wellfounded then it is 𝒱1\mathscr{V}_{1}-like. If instead [0,α]𝒰[0,\alpha]_{\mathcal{U}} drops, note that it drops below the image of δ0𝒱1\delta_{0}^{\mathscr{V}_{1}} and Mα𝒰M^{\mathcal{U}}_{\alpha} is a premouse (note that it is wellfounded in this case), so Mα𝒰0=Mα𝒰{M^{\mathcal{U}}_{\alpha}\downarrow 0}=M^{\mathcal{U}}_{\alpha}.

Definition 4.22.

Let 𝒱\mathscr{V} be a Vsp. Then Λ𝒱\Lambda^{\mathscr{V}} denotes the partial putative strategy for 𝒱|δ0𝒱\mathscr{V}|\delta_{0}^{\mathscr{V}} determined by the long extenders of 𝒱\mathscr{V}. That is, Λ𝒱(𝒯)=b\Lambda^{\mathscr{V}}(\mathcal{T})=b iff 𝒯𝒱\mathcal{T}\in\mathscr{V}, 𝒯\mathcal{T} is on 𝒱|δ0𝒱\mathscr{V}|\delta_{0}^{\mathscr{V}}, 𝒱\mathscr{V}\vDash𝒯\mathcal{T} is via Σsh\Sigma_{\mathrm{sh}}”, and either

  1. 𝒱\mathscr{V}\vDash𝒯\mathcal{T} is short and b=Σsh(𝒯)b=\Sigma_{\mathrm{sh}}(\mathcal{T})”, or

  2. 𝒱\mathscr{V}\vDash𝒯\mathcal{T} is maximal” and there is a long E𝔼+(𝒱)E\in\mathbb{E}_{+}(\mathscr{V}) such that 𝒯𝒱|λ(E)\mathcal{T}\in\mathscr{V}|\lambda(E) and bb is computed via factoring through cc as in Footnote 28, where cc is the cofinal branch through the tree from 𝒱|δ0𝒱\mathscr{V}|\delta_{0}^{\mathscr{V}} to j(𝒱|δ0𝒱)j(\mathscr{V}|\delta_{0}^{\mathscr{V}}) determined by j=iE𝒱|lh(E)j=i^{\mathscr{V}|{\rm lh}(E)}_{E}.

The following lemma, which is the main point of this subsubsection, is the analogue of [8, Lemma 2.17] and [19, Claim 12].

Lemma 4.22.

Ψ𝒱1,𝒱1\Psi_{\mathscr{V}_{1},\mathscr{V}_{1}^{-}} yields wellfounded models. Moreover, let 𝒯\mathcal{T} be on \mathcal{M}_{\infty}, via Σ,𝒱1\Sigma_{\mathcal{M}_{\infty},\mathscr{V}_{1}^{-}}, and let 𝒰\mathcal{U} be the corresponding tree on 𝒱1\mathscr{V}_{1} (so via Ψ𝒱1,𝒱1\Psi_{\mathscr{V}_{1},\mathscr{V}_{1}^{-}}). Let

πα:Mα𝒯Mα𝒰0Mα𝒰\pi_{\alpha}:M^{\mathcal{T}}_{\alpha}\to M^{\mathcal{U}}_{\alpha}\downarrow 0\subseteq M^{\mathcal{U}}_{\alpha}

be the natural copy map (where π0=id\pi_{0}=\mathrm{id}). Then:

  1. [0,α]𝒯[0,\alpha]_{\mathcal{T}} drops iff [0,α]𝒰[0,\alpha]_{\mathcal{U}} drops.

  2. If [0,α]𝒯[0,\alpha]_{\mathcal{T}} drops then Mα𝒯=Mα𝒰=Mα𝒰0M^{\mathcal{T}}_{\alpha}=M^{\mathcal{U}}_{\alpha}=M^{\mathcal{U}}_{\alpha}\downarrow 0.

  3. If [0,α]𝒯[0,\alpha]_{\mathcal{T}} does not drop then Mα𝒯=Mα𝒰0M^{\mathcal{T}}_{\alpha}=M^{\mathcal{U}}_{\alpha}\downarrow 0 and Mα𝒰=𝒱(Mα𝒯,)M^{\mathcal{U}}_{\alpha}=\mathscr{V}(M^{\mathcal{T}}_{\alpha},\ell) where :Mα𝒯Mα𝒯\ell:M^{\mathcal{T}}_{\alpha}\to\mathcal{M}_{\infty}^{M^{\mathcal{T}}_{\alpha}} is the ΣMα𝒯\Sigma_{M^{\mathcal{T}}_{\alpha}}-iteration map, and in fact, ΛMα𝒰ΣN,N|δ0N\Lambda^{M^{\mathcal{U}}_{\alpha}}\subseteq\Sigma_{N,N|\delta_{0}^{N}} where N=Mα𝒯N=M^{\mathcal{T}}_{\alpha}.

  4. πα=id\pi_{\alpha}=\mathrm{id}; therefore, iα𝒯iα𝒰i^{\mathcal{T}}_{\alpha}\subseteq i^{\mathcal{U}}_{\alpha}.

Proof.

We include the proof, mostly following that of [19]. Let 𝒯,𝒰\mathcal{T},\mathcal{U} be as above, of length α+1\alpha+1. The interesting case is the non-dropping one, so consider this.

Let P=Mα𝒯P=M^{\mathcal{T}}_{\alpha} and P=PP_{\infty}=\mathcal{M}_{\infty}^{P}. Let iPi_{\mathcal{M}_{\infty}P}, iPPi_{PP_{\infty}} and iPi_{\mathcal{M}_{\infty}P_{\infty}} be the iteration maps. We have

=Hull1(δ0);\mathcal{M}_{\infty}=\mathrm{Hull}^{\mathcal{M}_{\infty}}_{1}(\delta_{0}^{\mathcal{M}_{\infty}}\cup\mathscr{I}^{\mathcal{M}_{\infty}});

likewise for P,PP,P_{\infty} (maybe P\mathscr{I}^{P}\neq\mathscr{I}^{\mathcal{M}_{\infty}}, but P=P=iP{\mathscr{I}}^{P_{\infty}}=\mathscr{I}^{P}=i_{\mathcal{M}_{\infty}P}``\mathscr{I}^{\mathcal{M}_{\infty}}). We have

P=𝒱1P0𝒱1P.P_{\infty}=\mathscr{V}_{1}^{P}\downarrow 0\subseteq\mathscr{V}_{1}^{P}.

The analogue of the following claim was used in the proof of [19, Claim 12], where it was implicitly asserted but the proof not explicitly given. We give the proof here. It is just a slight generalization of the proofs of [19, Claims 8–10] (or see [8, Lemma 2.15]), the main conclusion of which is that if j:Mj:M\to\mathcal{M}_{\infty} is the iteration map, then

Hull[](rg(j))=Hull(rg(j))=rg(j).\mathcal{M}_{\infty}\cap\mathrm{Hull}^{\mathcal{M}_{\infty}[*]}(\mathrm{rg}(j))=\mathrm{Hull}^{\mathcal{M}_{\infty}}(\mathrm{rg}(j))=\mathrm{rg}(j).
Claim.

We have:

  1. (i)

    PHullP[P](rg(iP))=rg(iP)P_{\infty}\cap\mathrm{Hull}^{P_{\infty}[*^{P}]}(\mathrm{rg}(i_{\mathcal{M}_{\infty}P_{\infty}}))=\mathrm{rg}(i_{\mathcal{M}_{\infty}P_{\infty}}) and

  2. (ii)

    PHullP[P](rg(iPP))=rg(iPP)P_{\infty}\cap\mathrm{Hull}^{P_{\infty}[*^{P}]}(\mathrm{rg}(i_{PP_{\infty}}))=\mathrm{rg}(i_{PP_{\infty}}).

Proof.

Consider (i). Fix αOR\alpha\in\mathrm{OR} and s[]<ω\{}s\in[\mathscr{I}^{\mathcal{M}_{\infty}}]^{<\omega}\backslash\{\emptyset\} and β<δ0\beta<\delta_{0}^{\mathcal{M}_{\infty}} and a term tt such that

α=tP[P](iP(s,β))\alpha=t^{P_{\infty}[*^{P}]}(i_{\mathcal{M}_{\infty}P_{\infty}}(s^{-},\beta))

and β<γs\beta<\gamma^{\mathcal{M}_{\infty}}_{s}. We need to see αrg(iP)\alpha\in\mathrm{rg}(i_{\mathcal{M}_{\infty}P_{\infty}}). It suffices to see P(α)rg(iP)*^{P}(\alpha)\in\mathrm{rg}(i_{\mathcal{M}_{\infty}P_{\infty}}), by arguments in [19]. But this holds just as in [19], except that we have a fixed term uu such that for each NPN\in\mathscr{F}^{P},

α=uN(iN(s,β)).\alpha=u^{N}(i_{\mathcal{M}_{\infty}N}(s,\beta)).

This suffices. Part (ii) is analogous. ∎

Let P~=cHullP[P](rg(iPP))\widetilde{P}=\mathrm{cHull}^{P_{\infty}[*^{P}]}(\mathrm{rg}(i_{PP_{\infty}})) and ~=cHullP[P](rg(iP))\widetilde{\mathcal{M}_{\infty}}=\mathrm{cHull}^{P_{\infty}[*^{P}]}(\mathrm{rg}(i_{\mathcal{M}_{\infty}P_{\infty}})), let iPP+i_{PP_{\infty}}^{+} and iP+i_{\mathcal{M}_{\infty}P_{\infty}}^{+} the uncollapse maps, and iP+=(iPP+)1iMP+i_{\mathcal{M}_{\infty}P}^{+}=(i_{PP_{\infty}}^{+})^{-1}\circ i_{MP_{\infty}}^{+}. By the claim, iPiP+i_{\mathcal{M}_{\infty}P}\subseteq i_{\mathcal{M}_{\infty}P}^{+}.

Also, Ph*^{P}\subseteq h where h:PPh:P_{\infty}\to\mathcal{M}_{\infty}^{P_{\infty}} is the iteration map. Letting

iP+()=iPP+(′′)=Pδ0P,i^{+}_{\mathcal{M}_{\infty}P_{\infty}}(*^{\prime})=i^{+}_{PP_{\infty}}(*^{\prime\prime})=*^{P}{\upharpoonright}\delta_{0}^{P_{\infty}},

it easily follows that *^{\prime} and ′′*^{\prime\prime} agree with the iteration maps ()\mathcal{M}_{\infty}\to(\mathcal{M}_{\infty})^{\mathcal{M}_{\infty}} and PPP\to P_{\infty} respectively. Therefore ~=[]\widetilde{\mathcal{M}_{\infty}}=\mathcal{M}_{\infty}[*].

Let EE be the (δ0,δ0P)(\delta_{0}^{\mathcal{M}_{\infty}},\delta_{0}^{P})-extender derived from iPi_{\mathcal{M}_{\infty}P}, or equivalently from iP+i_{\mathcal{M}_{\infty}P}^{+}, also equivalently the [0,α]𝒯[0,\alpha]_{\mathcal{T}}-branch extender of 𝒯\mathcal{T}. So (recalling 𝒰\mathcal{U} is the corresponding tree on []\mathcal{M}_{\infty}[*])

Mα𝒰=Ult([],E)M^{\mathcal{U}}_{\alpha}=\mathrm{Ult}(\mathcal{M}_{\infty}[*],E)

and iα𝒰=iE[]i^{\mathcal{U}}_{\alpha}=i^{\mathcal{M}_{\infty}[*]}_{E}. We also have P=Mα𝒯=Ult(,E)P=M^{\mathcal{T}}_{\alpha}=\mathrm{Ult}(\mathcal{M}_{\infty},E) and iP=iα𝒯i_{\mathcal{M}_{\infty}P}=i^{\mathcal{T}}_{\alpha}. Let π:Mα𝒰P~\pi:M^{\mathcal{U}}_{\alpha}\to\widetilde{P} be the natural factor map, i.e.

π(iα𝒰(f)(a))=iP+(f)(a)\pi(i^{\mathcal{U}}_{\alpha}(f)(a))=i^{+}_{\mathcal{M}_{\infty}P}(f)(a)

whenever f[]f\in\mathcal{M}_{\infty}[*] and a[δ0P]<ωa\in[\delta_{0}^{P}]^{<\omega}. Then π\pi is surjective, because if αOR\alpha\in\mathrm{OR} then there is ff\in\mathcal{M}_{\infty} and a[δ0P]<ωa\in[\delta_{0}^{P}]^{<\omega} such that iP(f)(a)=αi_{\mathcal{M}_{\infty}P}(f)(a)=\alpha, and since iPiP+i_{\mathcal{M}_{\infty}P}\subseteq i_{\mathcal{M}_{\infty}P}^{+}, therefore iP+(f)(a)=α=π(α)i_{\mathcal{M}_{\infty}P}^{+}(f)(a)=\alpha=\pi(\alpha). So in fact Mα𝒰=P~M^{\mathcal{U}}_{\alpha}=\widetilde{P} and π=id\pi=\mathrm{id}, so iα𝒰=iP+i^{\mathcal{U}}_{\alpha}=i^{+}_{\mathcal{M}_{\infty}P}, so iα𝒯iα𝒰i^{\mathcal{T}}_{\alpha}\subseteq i^{\mathcal{U}}_{\alpha}, and letting πα:Mα𝒯(Mα𝒰0)\pi_{\alpha}:M^{\mathcal{T}}_{\alpha}\to(M^{\mathcal{U}}_{\alpha}\downarrow 0) be the natural copy map, then παπ=id\pi_{\alpha}\subseteq\pi=\mathrm{id}.

It just remains to see that ΛMα𝒰ΣP\Lambda^{M^{\mathcal{U}}_{\alpha}}\subseteq\Sigma_{P} (still with P=Mα𝒯P=M^{\mathcal{T}}_{\alpha}). First consider the case that for some correct normal above-κ0\kappa_{0} tree 𝒱\mathcal{V} on MM and E=Eα𝒱E=E^{\mathcal{V}}_{\alpha}, we have crit(E)=κ0{\rm crit}(E)=\kappa_{0} and EE is MM-total, and P=UP=\mathcal{M}_{\infty}^{U} where U=Ult(M,E)U=\mathrm{Ult}(M,E). Here by Lemma 4.11, U\mathcal{M}^{U}_{\infty} is indeed a δ0U\delta_{0}^{\mathcal{M}^{U}_{\infty}}-sound iterate of \mathcal{M}_{\infty}, and iEi_{E}{\upharpoonright}\mathcal{M}_{\infty} is just the iteration map. Moreover, by Lemma 4.12.1, 𝒱1U=iE(𝒱1)\mathscr{V}_{1}^{U}=i_{E}(\mathscr{V}_{1}) is the corresponding iterate of 𝒱1\mathscr{V}_{1}. But now the calculations that work for Λ𝒱1\Lambda^{\mathscr{V}_{1}} (the proof of Lemma 4.9, using Lemma 4.11) also work for Λ𝒱1U\Lambda^{\mathscr{V}_{1}^{U}}.

Now consider the general case. We will reduce this to the special case above via Lemma 3. Let E𝔼ME\in\mathbb{E}^{M} be MM-total with crit(F)=κ0{\rm crit}(F)=\kappa_{0}, and δ¯\bar{\delta} the least Woodin of M|lh(F)M|{\rm lh}(F) such that κ0<δ¯\kappa_{0}<\bar{\delta}. Form a genericity iteration at δ¯\bar{\delta}, above κ0\kappa_{0}, making P|δ0PP|\delta_{0}^{P} etc generic. Let EE be the eventual image of FF. Then EE is as in the previous case; let U=Ult(M,E)U=\mathrm{Ult}(M,E) and let U\mathcal{M}_{\infty}^{U}. Recall P~=Mα𝒰\widetilde{P}=M^{\mathcal{U}}_{\alpha} is an iterate of 𝒱1\mathscr{V}_{1}, and note 𝒱1U\mathscr{V}_{1}^{U} is the corresponding iterate of P~\widetilde{P}; let k:P~𝒱1k:\widetilde{P}\to\mathscr{V}_{1} be the iteration map. Let β\beta be such that P~|β\widetilde{P}|\beta is active with a long extender GG, β=k(β)\beta^{\prime}=k(\beta), and G=F𝒱1U|βG^{\prime}=F^{\mathscr{V}_{1}^{U}|\beta^{\prime}}. Note that kk is continuous at δ0P\delta_{0}^{P} and β\beta (as cofP(β)=δ0P\mathop{\rm cof}\nolimits^{P}(\beta)=\delta_{0}^{P}). Let j:PUlt(P,G)j:P\to\mathrm{Ult}(P,G) and j:UUlt(U,G)j^{\prime}:\mathcal{M}_{\infty}^{U}\to\mathrm{Ult}(\mathcal{M}_{\infty}^{U},G^{\prime}) be the ultrapower maps. Let 𝒯\mathcal{T} be the length β\beta tree from PP to Ult(P,G)\mathrm{Ult}(P,G) and 𝒯\mathcal{T}^{\prime} the length β\beta^{\prime} tree from U\mathcal{M}_{\infty}^{U} to Ult(U,G)\mathrm{Ult}(\mathcal{M}_{\infty}^{U},G^{\prime}); note that by first order considerations, these exist, and GG determines a 𝒯\mathcal{T}-cofinal branch bb such that Mb𝒯=Ult(P,G)M^{\mathcal{T}}_{b}=\mathrm{Ult}(P,G) and j=ib𝒯j=i^{\mathcal{T}}_{b}, and likewise for G,𝒯,b,U,jG^{\prime},\mathcal{T}^{\prime},b^{\prime},\mathcal{M}_{\infty}^{U},j^{\prime}. We know that 𝒯^b\mathcal{T}^{\prime}\ \widehat{\ }\ b^{\prime} is via ΣU\Sigma_{\mathcal{M}_{\infty}^{U}}, by the previous case. Note also that 𝒯\mathcal{T} is via ΣP\Sigma_{P}, because the Q-structure for each 𝒯λ\mathcal{T}{\upharpoonright}\lambda (for limit λ<β\lambda<\beta) does not overlap δ(𝒯λ)\delta(\mathcal{T}{\upharpoonright}\lambda), and is embedded into the Q-structure for 𝒯k(λ)\mathcal{T}^{\prime}{\upharpoonright}k(\lambda). But

kj(P|δ0P)=jk(P|δ0P)k\circ j{\upharpoonright}(P|\delta_{0}^{P})=j^{\prime}\circ k{\upharpoonright}(P|\delta_{0}^{P})

and j(δ0P)=βj(\delta_{0}^{P})=\beta and j(δU)=βj^{\prime}(\delta_{\infty}^{U})=\beta^{\prime}. So by Lemma 3, b=ΣP(𝒯)b=\Sigma_{P}(\mathcal{T}), as desired. ∎

Definition 4.23.

Given a non-dropping Ψ𝒱1,𝒱1\Psi_{\mathscr{V}_{1},\mathscr{V}_{1}^{-}}-iterate 𝒱\mathscr{V} of 𝒱1\mathscr{V}_{1}, let Ψ𝒱,𝒱\Psi_{\mathscr{V},\mathscr{V}^{-}} be induced by Σ𝒱0\Sigma_{\mathscr{V}\downarrow 0} just as Ψ𝒱1,𝒱1\Psi_{\mathscr{V}_{1},\mathscr{V}_{1}^{-}} is induced by Σ\Sigma_{\mathcal{M}_{\infty}} (this makes sense by Lemma 4.12.2).

4.12.3 Condensation properties for full normalization

The strategy Σ𝒱1\Sigma_{\mathscr{V}_{1}} (together with 𝒱1\mathscr{V}_{1}) will have the properties required for extending to a strategy for stacks with full normalization. We now lay out the properties of 𝒱1\mathscr{V}_{1} needed for this. Recall the notions nn-standard, (n+1)(n+1)-relevantly condensing and (n+1)(n+1)-sub-condensing from [15, ***Definition 2.1]. We adapt these in an obvious manner to Vsps.

Definition 4.24.

Let m<ωm<\omega and let 𝒱\mathscr{V} be an (m+1)(m+1)-sound Vsp. We say that 𝒱\mathscr{V} is (m+1)(m+1)-relevantly condensing iff either 𝒱\mathscr{V} is a premouse which is (m+1)(m+1)-relevantly condensing, or 𝒱\mathscr{V} is a sound base Vsp, or γ𝒱<OR𝒱\gamma^{\mathscr{V}}<\mathrm{OR}^{\mathscr{V}} and 𝒱\mathscr{V} satisfies the requirements of (m+1)(m+1)-relevantly condensing from [15, Definition 2.1] for π:P𝒱\pi:P\to\mathscr{V} such that PP is an (m+1)(m+1)-sound Vsp, γP<ORP\gamma^{P}<\mathrm{OR}^{P} and crit(π)>δ0𝒱{\rm crit}(\pi)>\delta_{0}^{\mathscr{V}} (so crit(π)>γ𝒱{\rm crit}(\pi)>\gamma^{\mathscr{V}}). Likewise for (m+1)(m+1)-sub-condensing.

For n<ωn<\omega, a Vsp 𝒱\mathscr{V} is nn-standard iff 𝒱\mathscr{V} is nn-sound and either 𝒱\mathscr{V} is an nn-standard premouse, or 𝒱\mathscr{V} is a base Vsp and 𝒱pv\mathscr{V}^{\mathrm{pv}} is ω\omega-standard, or γ𝒱<OR𝒱\gamma^{\mathscr{V}}<\mathrm{OR}^{\mathscr{V}} and 𝒱\mathscr{V} is (m+1)(m+1)-relevantly condensing for each m<nm<n, and every M𝒱M\triangleleft\mathscr{V} is (m+1)(m+1)-relevantly-condensing and (m+1)(m+1)-sub-condensing for each m<ωm<\omega.

A Vsp is ω\omega-standard iff nn-standard for each n<ωn<\omega.

Lemma 4.24.

𝒱1\mathscr{V}_{1} is ω\omega-standard. (Thus, we take 𝒱1\mathscr{V}_{1}-like to include ω\omega-standard.)

Proof.

Let α>γ𝒱\alpha>\gamma^{\mathscr{V}} and PP be a Vsp and π:P𝒱|α\pi:P\to\mathscr{V}|\alpha be an embedding as in the definition of (m+1)(m+1)-relevantly- or (m+1)(m+1)-sub-condensing. We want to know that P𝒱P\triangleleft\mathscr{V}. But note that there is a premouse NN such that M|κ0+MNM|\kappa_{0}^{+M}\triangleleft N and 𝒱N=P\mathscr{V}^{N}=P and π\pi extends to π+:NM|α\pi^{+}:N\to M|\alpha, which also satisfies the conditions of (m+1)(m+1)-relevantly- or (m+1)(m+1)-sub-condensing, respectively. So NMN\triangleleft M, so P𝒱P\triangleleft\mathscr{V}. ∎

Remark 4.24.

Let 𝒱\mathscr{V} be 𝒱1\mathscr{V}_{1}-like. Then as for premice, if 𝒯\mathcal{T} is a 0-maximal tree on 𝒱\mathscr{V} then Mα𝒯M^{\mathcal{T}}_{\alpha} is degα𝒯\deg^{\mathcal{T}}_{\alpha}-standard (see [15, ***Remark 2.2]).

4.12.4 Short-normal trees on 𝒱1\mathscr{V}_{1}

Recall that short-normal trees on 𝒱1\mathscr{V}_{1}-like Vsps were defined in Definition 4.18.

Definition 4.25.

Let 𝒱\mathscr{V} be a (possibly dropping, putative) iterate of 𝒱1\mathscr{V}_{1}, via a short-normal tree 𝒯^𝒮\mathcal{T}\ \widehat{\ }\ \mathcal{S} with lower and upper components 𝒯,𝒮\mathcal{T},\mathcal{S}. We say that 𝒱\mathscr{V} is good iff 𝒯\mathcal{T} is via Ψ𝒱1,𝒱1\Psi_{\mathscr{V}_{1},\mathscr{V}_{1}^{-}} and if b𝒯b^{\mathcal{T}} does not drop then 𝒱\mathscr{V} is wellfounded and for every long E𝔼+𝒱E\in\mathbb{E}_{+}^{\mathscr{V}}, 𝒱|lh(E)=N|δ0N\mathcal{M}_{\infty}^{\mathscr{V}|{\rm lh}(E)}=N|\delta_{0}^{N} for some Σ𝒱0\Sigma_{\mathscr{V}\downarrow 0}-iterate NN of 𝒱0\mathscr{V}\downarrow 0, and EE is the corresponding iteration map. Say that a (partial) iteration strategy Ψ\Psi is good iff all putative iterates via Ψ\Psi are good.

Note we have already shown that Ψ𝒱1,𝒱1\Psi_{\mathscr{V}_{1},\mathscr{V}_{1}^{-}} is good. We now want to extend Ψ𝒱1,𝒱1\Psi_{\mathscr{V}_{1},\mathscr{V}_{1}^{-}} to a good short-normal 0-maximal strategy Ψsn\Psi_{\mathrm{sn}} for 𝒱1\mathscr{V}_{1}. So we start by setting Ψ𝒱1,𝒱1Ψsn\Psi_{\mathscr{V}_{1},\mathscr{V}_{1}^{-}}\subseteq\Psi_{\mathrm{sn}}. As an easy next step, we deal with trees based on 𝒱1||γ𝒱1\mathscr{V}_{1}||\gamma^{\mathscr{V}_{1}}.

Definition 4.26.

Write Ψ𝒱1,γ𝒱1\Psi_{\mathscr{V}_{1},\gamma^{\mathscr{V}_{1}}} for the putative strategy Ψ\Psi for 𝒱1\mathscr{V}_{1}, for short-normal 0-maximal trees based on 𝒱1||γ𝒱1\mathscr{V}_{1}||\gamma^{\mathscr{V}_{1}}, as follows:

  1. 1.

    Ψ𝒱1,𝒱1Ψ\Psi_{\mathscr{V}_{1},\mathscr{V}_{1}^{-}}\subseteq\Psi, and

  2. 2.

    given 𝒯\mathcal{T} via Ψ𝒱1,𝒱1\Psi_{\mathscr{V}_{1},\mathscr{V}_{1}^{-}}, of successor length α+1\alpha+1, where [0,α]𝒯[0,\alpha]_{\mathcal{T}} does not drop, and given a putative 0-maximal tree 𝒰\mathcal{U} on Mα𝒯||γMα𝒯M^{\mathcal{T}}_{\alpha}||\gamma^{M^{\mathcal{T}}_{\alpha}}, which is above δ0Mα𝒯\delta_{0}^{M^{\mathcal{T}}_{\alpha}}, then 𝒯^𝒰\mathcal{T}\ \widehat{\ }\ \mathcal{U} is via Ψ\Psi iff there is a tree 𝒰\mathcal{U}^{\prime} on Mα𝒯0{M^{\mathcal{T}}_{\alpha}\downarrow 0}, via ΣMα𝒯0\Sigma_{M^{\mathcal{T}}_{\alpha}\downarrow 0}, with the same extenders and tree order as 𝒰\mathcal{U}.

Note here that by Lemma 4.9, ρ1Mα𝒯||γMα𝒯=δ0Mα𝒯\rho_{1}^{M^{\mathcal{T}}_{\alpha}||\gamma^{M^{\mathcal{T}}_{\alpha}}}=\delta_{0}^{M^{\mathcal{T}}_{\alpha}}, a strong cutpoint of (Mα𝒯||γMα𝒯)pv(M^{\mathcal{T}}_{\alpha}||\gamma^{M^{\mathcal{T}}_{\alpha}})^{\mathrm{pv}}, so 𝒯^𝒰\mathcal{T}\ \widehat{\ }\ \mathcal{U} is indeed a putative 0-maximal tree on 𝒱1\mathscr{V}_{1}.

Lemma 4.26.

Ψ𝒱1,γ𝒱1\Psi_{\mathscr{V}_{1},\gamma^{\mathscr{V}_{1}}} is a short-normal 0-maximal strategy (hence yields wellfounded models). Moreover, let 𝒯^𝒰\mathcal{T}\ \widehat{\ }\ \mathcal{U} and 𝒰\mathcal{U}^{\prime} be as in Definition 4.26, with 𝒰\mathcal{U}\neq\emptyset. Then:

  1. 1.

    M0𝒰=Mα𝒯||γMα𝒯M^{\mathcal{U}}_{0}=M^{\mathcal{T}}_{\alpha}||\gamma^{M^{\mathcal{T}}_{\alpha}} and deg0𝒰=0\deg^{\mathcal{U}}_{0}=0,

  2. 2.

    M0𝒰=Mα𝒯0M^{\mathcal{U}^{\prime}}_{0}={M^{\mathcal{T}}_{\alpha}\downarrow 0} and deg0𝒰=0\deg^{\mathcal{U}^{\prime}}_{0}=0, so (M0𝒰)pv=M0𝒰|κ0+M0𝒰(M^{\mathcal{U}}_{0})^{\mathrm{pv}}=M^{\mathcal{U}^{\prime}}_{0}|\kappa_{0}^{+M^{\mathcal{U}^{\prime}}_{0}},

  3. 3.

    for 0<β<lh(𝒰)0<\beta<{\rm lh}(\mathcal{U}), β𝒟deg𝒰β𝒟deg𝒰\beta\in\mathscr{D}_{\deg}^{\mathcal{U}}\Leftrightarrow\beta\in\mathscr{D}_{\deg}^{\mathcal{U}^{\prime}}, and degβ𝒰=degβ𝒰\deg^{\mathcal{U}}_{\beta}=\deg^{\mathcal{U}^{\prime}}_{\beta},

  4. 4.

    if 0<β<lh(𝒰)0<\beta<{\rm lh}(\mathcal{U}) and [0,β]𝒰[0,\beta]_{\mathcal{U}} drops then Mβ𝒰=Mβ𝒰M^{\mathcal{U}}_{\beta}=M^{\mathcal{U}}_{\beta^{\prime}},

  5. 5.

    if 0<β<lh(𝒰)0<\beta<{\rm lh}(\mathcal{U}) and [0,β]𝒰[0,\beta]_{\mathcal{U}} does not drop then (Mβ𝒰)pv=Mβ𝒰|κ0+Mβ𝒰(M^{\mathcal{U}}_{\beta})^{\mathrm{pv}}=M^{\mathcal{U}^{\prime}}_{\beta}|\kappa_{0}^{+M^{\mathcal{U}^{\prime}}_{\beta}},

  6. 6.

    if 0<β+1<lh(𝒰)0<\beta+1<{\rm lh}(\mathcal{U}) and [0,β+1]𝒰[0,\beta+1]_{\mathcal{U}} drops then Mβ+1𝒰=Mβ+1𝒰M^{*\mathcal{U}}_{\beta+1}=M^{*\mathcal{U}^{\prime}}_{\beta+1} and iβ+1𝒰=iβ+1𝒰i^{*\mathcal{U}}_{\beta+1}=i^{*\mathcal{U}^{\prime}}_{\beta+1},

  7. 7.

    if 0<β+1<lh(𝒰)0<\beta+1<{\rm lh}(\mathcal{U}) and [0,β+1]𝒰[0,\beta+1]_{\mathcal{U}^{\prime}} does not drop then iβ+1𝒰iβ+1𝒰i^{*\mathcal{U}}_{\beta+1}\subseteq i^{*\mathcal{U}^{\prime}}_{\beta+1},

  8. 8.

    if 0β<lh(𝒰)0\leq\beta<{\rm lh}(\mathcal{U}) and [0,β]𝒰[0,\beta]_{\mathcal{U}} does not drop then Mβ𝒰M^{\mathcal{U}^{\prime}}_{\beta} is a κ0Mβ𝒰\kappa_{0}^{M^{\mathcal{U}^{\prime}}_{\beta}}-sound ΣMα𝒯0\Sigma_{M^{\mathcal{T}}_{\alpha}\downarrow 0}-iterate of Mα𝒯0{M^{\mathcal{T}}_{\alpha}\downarrow 0}, Mβ𝒰\mathcal{M}_{\infty}^{M^{\mathcal{U}^{\prime}}_{\beta}} is a δ0Mβ𝒰\delta_{0}^{\mathcal{M}_{\infty}^{M^{\mathcal{U}^{\prime}}_{\beta}}}-sound ΣMα𝒯0\Sigma_{M^{\mathcal{T}}_{\alpha}\downarrow 0}-iterate of Mα𝒯0{M^{\mathcal{T}}_{\alpha}\downarrow 0},

    Ult(Mα𝒯0,F(Mβ𝒯))=Mβ𝒰\mathrm{Ult}(M^{\mathcal{T}}_{\alpha}\downarrow 0,F(M^{\mathcal{T}}_{\beta}))=\mathcal{M}_{\infty}^{M^{\mathcal{U}^{\prime}}_{\beta}}

    and F(Mβ𝒯)F(M^{\mathcal{T}}_{\beta}) is the extender of the ΣMα𝒯0\Sigma_{M^{\mathcal{T}}_{\alpha}\downarrow 0}-iteration map.

Therefore Ψ𝒱1,γ𝒱1\Psi_{\mathscr{V}_{1},\gamma^{\mathscr{V}_{1}}} is good.

Proof.

We omit most of the proof, as it follows from the usual calculations. However, for part 8, just note that the action of the 𝒰\mathcal{U}- and 𝒰\mathcal{U}^{\prime}-iteration maps jj and jj^{\prime} on M0𝒰=Mα𝒯||γMα𝒯M^{\mathcal{U}}_{0}=M^{\mathcal{T}}_{\alpha}||\gamma^{M^{\mathcal{T}}_{\alpha}} are identical (i.e. jjj\subseteq j^{\prime}), since (M0𝒰)pv=M0𝒰|κ0+M0𝒰(M^{\mathcal{U}}_{0})^{\mathrm{pv}}=M^{\mathcal{U}^{\prime}}_{0}|\kappa_{0}^{+M^{\mathcal{U}^{\prime}}_{0}}, and so

j(M0𝒰)=j(M0𝒰|δM0𝒰)=Mβ𝒰|δMβ𝒰;j(\mathcal{M}_{\infty}^{M^{\mathcal{U}}_{0}})=j^{\prime}(\mathcal{M}_{\infty}^{M^{\mathcal{U}^{\prime}}_{0}}|\delta_{\infty}^{M^{\mathcal{U}^{\prime}}_{0}})=\mathcal{M}_{\infty}^{M^{\mathcal{U}^{\prime}}_{\beta}}|\delta_{\infty}^{M^{\mathcal{U}^{\prime}}_{\beta}};

but then the fact that F(Mβ𝒯)F(M^{\mathcal{T}}_{\beta}) agrees with the ΣMα𝒯0\Sigma_{M^{\mathcal{T}}_{\alpha}\downarrow 0}-iteration map

(Mα𝒯0)|δ0Mα𝒯0Mβ𝒰({M^{\mathcal{T}}_{\alpha}\downarrow 0})|\delta_{0}^{M^{\mathcal{T}}_{\alpha}\downarrow 0}\to\mathcal{M}_{\infty}^{M^{\mathcal{U}^{\prime}}_{\beta}}

is a consequence, since F𝒱||γ𝒱F^{\mathscr{V}||\gamma^{\mathscr{V}}} is likewise correct, where 𝒱=Mα𝒯\mathscr{V}=M^{\mathcal{T}}_{\alpha} (by Lemma 4.12.2) and jj^{\prime} preserves indiscernibles. ∎

Note that if 𝒯^𝒰\mathcal{T}\ \widehat{\ }\ \mathcal{U} is as above, with last model Mβ𝒰M^{\mathcal{U}}_{\beta}, then applying F(Mβ𝒰)F(M^{\mathcal{U}}_{\beta}) as the next extender (giving a non-short-normal tree), the next model is again an iterate of 𝒱1\mathscr{V}_{1} via Ψ𝒱1,𝒱1\Psi_{\mathscr{V}_{1},\mathscr{V}_{1}^{-}}.

Definition 4.27.

Say that (𝒲,U,𝒯)(\mathcal{W},U,\mathcal{T}) is MM-standard iff 𝒲\mathcal{W} is a Σ\Sigma-tree on MM which is above κ0\kappa_{0}, lh(𝒲)=ξ+2{\rm lh}(\mathcal{W})=\xi+2 for some ξ\xi, and letting E=Eξ𝒲E=E^{\mathcal{W}}_{\xi}, then crit(E)=κ0{\rm crit}(E)=\kappa_{0} and EE is MM-total, U=Ult(M,E)=Mξ+1𝒲U=\mathrm{Ult}(M,E)=M^{\mathcal{W}}_{\xi+1}, and 𝒯\mathcal{T} is the tree leading from 𝒱1\mathscr{V}_{1} to 𝒱1U\mathscr{V}_{1}^{U}; so

M𝒯=𝒱1U=Ult(𝒱1,E𝒱1)M^{\mathcal{T}}_{\infty}=\mathscr{V}_{1}^{U}=\mathrm{Ult}(\mathscr{V}_{1},E{\upharpoonright}\mathscr{V}_{1})

and i𝒯i𝒲i^{\mathcal{T}}\subseteq i^{\mathcal{W}}.

Suppose (𝒲,U,𝒯)(\mathcal{W},U,\mathcal{T}) is MM-standard. We define a strategy Γ𝒲\Gamma_{\mathcal{W}} for above-δ0𝒱1U\delta_{0}^{\mathscr{V}_{1}^{U}} short-normal trees 𝒮\mathcal{S} on 𝒱1U\mathscr{V}_{1}^{U}. 434343We use subscript 𝒲\mathcal{W}, not 𝒯\mathcal{T}, as one can have MM-standard (𝒲,U,𝒯)(𝒲,U,𝒯)(\mathcal{W}^{\prime},U^{\prime},\mathcal{T}^{\prime})\neq(\mathcal{W},U,\mathcal{T}) with 𝒯=𝒯\mathcal{T}^{\prime}=\mathcal{T}. We will later see that, in this case however, Γ𝒲=Γ𝒲\Gamma_{\mathcal{W}}=\Gamma_{\mathcal{W}^{\prime}}. Let 𝒱=𝒱1U\mathscr{V}=\mathscr{V}_{1}^{U} and N=𝒱0=UN=\mathscr{V}\downarrow 0=\mathcal{M}_{\infty}^{U}.

If lh(E0𝒮)<γ𝒱{\rm lh}(E^{\mathcal{S}}_{0})<\gamma^{\mathscr{V}}, then Γ𝒲\Gamma_{\mathcal{W}} follows Ψ𝒱1,γ𝒱1\Psi_{\mathscr{V}_{1},\gamma^{\mathscr{V}_{1}}} (recalling that 𝒯\mathcal{T} is via Ψ𝒱1,𝒱1\Psi_{\mathscr{V}_{1},\mathscr{V}_{1}^{-}}).

Suppose lh(E0𝒮)>γ𝒱{\rm lh}(E^{\mathcal{S}}_{0})>\gamma^{\mathscr{V}}. Let Γ\Gamma be the above-κ0+U\kappa_{0}^{+U}-strategy for UU given by ΣU\Sigma_{U}. Then since 𝒱=𝒱1U\mathscr{V}=\mathscr{V}_{1}^{U} is defined by P-construction, Γ\Gamma induces a short-normal above-γ𝒱\gamma^{\mathscr{V}}-strategy for 𝒱\mathscr{V}, which Γ𝒲\Gamma_{\mathcal{W}} follows in this case.

We extend Γ\Gamma to ΓV[G]\Gamma^{V[G]}, for set-generic extensions V[G]V[G] of VV, using that Σ\Sigma extends canonically to ΣV[G]\Sigma^{V[G]}.

Lemma 4.27.

Γ𝒲\Gamma_{\mathcal{W}} is good, and hence so is each Γ𝒲V[G]\Gamma^{V[G]}_{\mathcal{W}}.

Proof.

Clearly Γ𝒲\Gamma_{\mathcal{W}} yields wellfounded models, and we already saw that Ψ𝒱1,γ𝒱1\Psi_{\mathscr{V}_{1},\gamma^{\mathscr{V}_{1}}} is good. So with notation as in Definition 4.27, suppose lh(E0𝒮)>γ𝒱{\rm lh}(E^{\mathcal{S}}_{0})>\gamma^{\mathscr{V}} and 𝒮\mathcal{S} has successor length, and let 𝒮\mathcal{S}^{\prime} be the corresponding above-κ0+U\kappa_{0}^{+U} tree on UU. Let βOR(M𝒮)\beta\leq\mathrm{OR}(M^{\mathcal{S}}_{\infty}) with F=F(M𝒮||β)F=F(M^{\mathcal{S}}_{\infty}||\beta) long, and β>γ𝒱\beta>\gamma^{\mathscr{V}}. Let F=F(M𝒮||β)F^{\prime}=F(M^{\mathcal{S}^{\prime}}_{\infty}||\beta). Then crit(F)=κ0U{\rm crit}(F^{\prime})=\kappa_{0}^{U} and FF^{\prime} is UU-total, and FFF\subseteq F^{\prime}. So goodness with respect to FF is an easy consequence of Lemma 4.11 (note that UU and U=Ult(U,F)U^{\prime}=\mathrm{Ult}(U,F^{\prime}) are κ0U\kappa_{0}^{U}- and κ0U\kappa_{0}^{U^{\prime}}-sound Σ\Sigma-iterates of MM). ∎

Lemma 4.27.

Let AA be a set of ordinals. Then there is an MM-standard (𝒲,U,𝒳)(\mathcal{W},U,\mathcal{X}) such that AA is (U,)(U,\mathbb{P})-generic for some U|κ0U\mathbb{P}\in U|\kappa_{0}^{U}. Moreover, if 𝒱\mathscr{V} is a non-dropping Ψ𝒱1,𝒱1\Psi_{\mathscr{V}_{1},\mathscr{V}_{1}^{-}}-iterate of 𝒱1\mathscr{V}_{1}, via maximal tree 𝒯=A\mathcal{T}=A, then 𝒱1U\mathscr{V}_{1}^{U} is a Ψ𝒱,𝒱\Psi_{\mathscr{V},\mathscr{V}^{-}}-iterate of 𝒱\mathscr{V} (see Definition 4.23).

Likewise if V[G]V[G] is a set-generic extension of VV and A𝒫(OR)V[G]A\in\mathcal{P}(\mathrm{OR})\cap V[G].

Proof.

Let F𝔼MF\in\mathbb{E}^{M} be MM-total with crit(F)=κ0{\rm crit}(F)=\kappa_{0}. Then λF\lambda_{F} is a limit of Woodin cardinals of M|lh(F)M|{\rm lh}(F), and νF<λF\nu_{F}<\lambda_{F}. Let δ(νF,λF)\delta\in(\nu_{F},\lambda_{F}) be Woodin in M|lh(F)M|{\rm lh}(F). Let 𝒲\mathcal{W}^{\prime} be an above-νF\nu_{F} genericity iteration of MM, for the extender algebra of M|lh(F)M|{\rm lh}(F) at δ\delta, making AA generic. Note that ρ1M||lh(F)νF\rho_{1}^{M||{\rm lh}(F)}\leq\nu_{F}, so 𝒲\mathcal{W}^{\prime} drops immediately to M||lh(F)M||{\rm lh}(F), at degree 0. Set 𝒲=𝒲^F(M𝒲)\mathcal{W}=\mathcal{W}^{\prime}\ \widehat{\ }\ \left<F(M^{\mathcal{W}^{\prime}}_{\infty})\right>. The “moreover” clause is a routine consequence, and the extension to V[G]V[G] is similar. ∎

We can now define the full short-normal strategy Ψsn\Psi_{\mathrm{sn}} for 𝒱1\mathscr{V}_{1}. In the end the method used to define the corresponding strategy for 𝒱2\mathscr{V}_{2}, in §5.6.4 (especially Definition 5.32), will be somewhat different, instead of being a direct generalization. One could probably use the methods of §5.6.4 to define a strategy for 𝒱1\mathscr{V}_{1} below, which would have benefit of making the construction more uniform. But historically, the approach below was found earlier, and the verification that it works involves ideas that do not come up for the methods of §5.6.4, which and seem of interest. So in order to record more information, we use the two different methods, as opposed to aiming for succinctness through uniformity.

Definition 4.28.

Let 𝒯\mathscr{T} be the class of all trees 𝒯\mathcal{T} on 𝒱1\mathscr{V}_{1} via Ψ𝒱1,𝒱1\Psi_{\mathscr{V}_{1},\mathscr{V}_{1}^{-}}, of successor length, with b𝒯b^{\mathcal{T}} non-dropping. For 𝒯𝒯\mathcal{T}\in\mathscr{T}, letting 𝒱=M𝒯\mathscr{V}=M^{\mathcal{T}}_{\infty}, we will define a good above-δ0𝒱\delta_{0}^{\mathscr{V}} short-normal strategy Ψ𝒯\Psi_{\mathcal{T}} for 𝒱\mathscr{V}. We will then define

Ψsn=Ψ𝒱1,𝒱1𝒯𝒯Ψ𝒯.\Psi_{\mathrm{sn}}=\Psi_{\mathscr{V}_{1},\mathscr{V}_{1}^{-}}\cup\bigcup_{\mathcal{T}\in\mathscr{T}}\Psi_{\mathcal{T}}.

So fix 𝒯\mathcal{T}. Let (𝒲,U,𝒳)(\mathcal{W},U,\mathcal{X}) be MM-standard and such that 𝒯\mathcal{T} is (U,)(U,\mathbb{P})-generic for some U|κ0U\mathbb{P}\in U|\kappa_{0}^{U}, which exists by Lemma 4.12.4. Let j:𝒱𝒱1Uj:\mathscr{V}\to\mathscr{V}_{1}^{U} be the correct iteration map. By 4.12.3, 𝒱1U\mathscr{V}_{1}^{U} is ω\omega-standard. We define

Ψ𝒯= the minimal j-pullback of Γ𝒲\Psi_{\mathcal{T}}=\text{ the minimal }j\text{-pullback of }\Gamma_{\mathcal{W}}

(see [15, 10.3, 10.4] and Remark 4.12.4 below; by ω\omega-standardness, the minimal jj-pullback is well-defined, but we verify below that Ψ𝒯\Psi_{\mathcal{T}} is independent of the choice of 𝒲\mathcal{W}444444Of course, we could have simply chosen 𝒲\mathcal{W} in a canonical fashion, and then Ψ𝒯\Psi_{\mathcal{T}} would be trivially well-defined. But the independence from 𝒲\mathcal{W} will be important later.).

We also generalize this to set-generic extensions V[G]V[G] of VV. Let 𝒯V[G]\mathscr{T}^{V[G]} be the class of all trees 𝒯\mathcal{T} on 𝒱1\mathscr{V}_{1} via Ψ𝒱1,𝒱1V[G]\Psi^{V[G]}_{\mathscr{V}_{1},\mathscr{V}_{1}^{-}} (determined by ΣV[G]\Sigma^{V[G]} just as Ψ𝒱1,𝒱1\Psi_{\mathscr{V}_{1},\mathscr{V}_{1}^{-}} is from Σ\Sigma), of successor length, with b𝒯b^{\mathcal{T}} non-dropping. Fix 𝒯𝒯V[G]\mathcal{T}\in\mathscr{T}^{V[G]}. Let (𝒲,U,𝒳)(\mathcal{W},U,\mathcal{X}) be as above with respect to 𝒯\mathcal{T} (but still with 𝒲V\mathcal{W}\in V, so UVU\subseteq V and 𝒳V\mathcal{X}\in V also). Let 𝒱=M𝒯\mathscr{V}=M^{\mathcal{T}}_{\infty}. and j:𝒱𝒱1Uj:\mathscr{V}\to\mathscr{V}_{1}^{U} be the correct iteration map. Define

ψ𝒯V[G]= the minimal j-pullback of Γ𝒲V[G].\psi_{\mathcal{T}}^{V[G]}=\text{ the minimal }j\text{-pullback of }\Gamma^{V[G]}_{\mathcal{W}}.
Remark 4.28.

Let us summarize how the minimal jj-pullback determining Ψ𝒯\Psi_{\mathcal{T}} is defined. It is like a standard copying construction, except that the method for copying extenders is different. Let EjE_{j} be the (δ0𝒱,δ0𝒱1U)(\delta_{0}^{\mathscr{V}},\delta_{0}^{\mathscr{V}_{1}^{U}})-extender derived from jj. For 𝒮\mathcal{S} via Ψ𝒯\Psi_{\mathcal{T}}, we will have a tree 𝒮\mathcal{S}^{\prime} via Γ𝒲\Gamma_{\mathcal{W}}, with the same length, tree order, drop and degree structure, and for α<lh(𝒮)\alpha<{\rm lh}(\mathcal{S}), a d=degα𝒮d=\deg^{\mathcal{S}}_{\alpha}-embedding

πα:Mα𝒮Mα𝒮,\pi_{\alpha}:M^{\mathcal{S}}_{\alpha}\to M^{\mathcal{S}^{\prime}}_{\alpha},

and moreover,

Mα𝒮=Ultd(Mα𝒮,Ej)M^{\mathcal{S}^{\prime}}_{\alpha}=\mathrm{Ult}_{d}(M^{\mathcal{S}}_{\alpha},E_{j})

and πα\pi_{\alpha} is the associated ultrapower map, and if α+1<lh(𝒯)\alpha+1<{\rm lh}(\mathcal{T}) then

Mα𝒮||lh(Eα𝒮)=Ult0(Mα𝒮||lh(Eα𝒮),Ej),M^{\mathcal{S}^{\prime}}_{\alpha}||{\rm lh}(E^{\mathcal{S}^{\prime}}_{\alpha})=\mathrm{Ult}_{0}(M^{\mathcal{S}}_{\alpha}||{\rm lh}(E^{\mathcal{S}}_{\alpha}),E_{j}),

and letting d=deg𝒮(α+1)d^{*}=\deg^{\mathcal{S}}(\alpha+1), then

Mα+1𝒮=Ultd(Mα+1𝒮,Ej).M^{*\mathcal{S}^{\prime}}_{\alpha+1}=\mathrm{Ult}_{d^{*}}(M^{*\mathcal{S}}_{\alpha+1},E_{j}).

The remaining details are essentially as in [24] and [15], using ω\omega-standardness for Vsps (the latter ensures that, for example, when Eα𝒮F(Mα𝒮)E^{\mathcal{S}}_{\alpha}\neq F(M^{\mathcal{S}}_{\alpha}) or degα𝒮>0\deg^{\mathcal{S}}_{\alpha}>0, the ultrapower above determining Eα𝒮E^{\mathcal{S}^{\prime}}_{\alpha} does indeed produce a segment of Mα𝒮M^{\mathcal{S}^{\prime}}_{\alpha}).

Lemma 4.28.
454545Although this lemma logically precedes later parts of the paper, its necessity and proof were actually found later, in particular after the proof of Theorem 5.8, which was found after the proof of Lemma 5.1.1.

We have:

  1. 1.

    Ψ𝒯\Psi_{\mathcal{T}} is well-defined for each 𝒯𝒯V[G]\mathcal{T}\in\mathscr{T}^{V[G]}.

  2. 2.

    ΨsnV[G]\Psi^{V[G]}_{\mathrm{sn}} is good.

Proof.

Since GG doesn’t make a significant difference, we assume G=G=\emptyset.

Part 2: Let 𝒮\mathcal{S} on 𝒱\mathscr{V} be via Ψ𝒯\Psi_{\mathcal{T}}, and 𝒮\mathcal{S}^{\prime} the minimal jj-copy, as in Remark 4.12.4. Using the copy maps πα:Mα𝒮Mα𝒮\pi_{\alpha}:M^{\mathcal{S}}_{\alpha}\to M^{\mathcal{S}^{\prime}}_{\alpha}, we can argue just like in the last part of the proof of Lemma 4.12.2 to see that the long extenders in 𝔼+(Mα𝒮)\mathbb{E}_{+}(M^{\mathcal{S}}_{\alpha}) are correct.

Part 1: Let (𝒲,U,𝒳)(\mathcal{W},U,\mathcal{X}) and (𝒲,U,𝒳)(\mathcal{W}^{\prime},U^{\prime},\mathcal{X}^{\prime}) be as in the definition, and let Ψ,Ψ\Psi,\Psi^{\prime} respectively be the induced strategies for 𝒱=M𝒯\mathscr{V}=M^{\mathcal{T}}_{\infty}.

Roughly, we would like to compare UU with UU^{\prime}, producing a common iterate U′′U^{\prime\prime} and corresponding 𝒲′′,𝒳′′\mathcal{W}^{\prime\prime},\mathcal{X}^{\prime\prime}, and show that Ψ,Ψ\Psi,\Psi^{\prime} both agree with Ψ𝒲′′\Psi_{\mathcal{W}^{\prime\prime}}, and hence are equal. However, a standard comparison of U,UU,U^{\prime} doesn’t work for this, as the resulting iteration map could have critical point κ0M\kappa_{0}^{M} on one side, which would cause problems. Instead, we form a modified kind of comparison, as follows.

Let D𝔼UD\in\mathbb{E}^{U} be the UU-total order 0 measure on κ0U\kappa_{0}^{U}. Let δ\delta be the least Woodin of Ult(U,D)\mathrm{Ult}(U,D) such that δ>κ0U\delta>\kappa_{0}^{U}. Let D,δD^{\prime},\delta^{\prime} be likewise for UU^{\prime}.

Recall from [20] that the meas-lim extender algebra of a premouse NN is like the usual extender algebra, except that we only induce axioms with extenders E𝔼NE\in\mathbb{E}^{N} such that νE\nu_{E} is a limit of measurable cardinals of NN. We will form a simultaneous genericity iteration (𝒴,𝒴)(\mathcal{Y},\mathcal{Y}^{\prime}) of Ult(U,D)\mathrm{Ult}(U,D) and Ult(U,D)\mathrm{Ult}(U^{\prime},D^{\prime}) for the meas-lim extender algebras at δ,δ\delta,\delta^{\prime}, above κ0U+1\kappa_{0}^{U}+1 and κ0U+1\kappa_{0}^{U^{\prime}}+1 respectively, arranging that M𝒴M^{\mathcal{Y}}_{\infty} and M𝒴M^{\mathcal{Y}^{\prime}}_{\infty} are generic over one another, and δ(𝒴)=i0𝒴(δ)=i0𝒴(δ)=δ(𝒴)\delta(\mathcal{Y})=i^{\mathcal{Y}}_{0\infty}(\delta)=i^{\mathcal{Y}^{\prime}}_{0\infty}(\delta^{\prime})=\delta(\mathcal{Y}^{\prime}). To help ensure the latter, we also (i) arrange genericity of (U|δ,U|δ)(U|\delta,U^{\prime}|\delta^{\prime}), which will allow 𝒴,𝒴\mathcal{Y},\mathcal{Y}^{\prime} to be recovered in the generic extensions, and (ii) insert short linear iterations which ensure that every measurable of M𝒴M^{\mathcal{Y}}_{\infty} below i0𝒴(δ)i^{\mathcal{Y}}_{0\infty}(\delta) is a cardinal of M𝒴M^{\mathcal{Y}^{\prime}}_{\infty}, and vice versa; this is like similar arguments in [17] and [16]. However, executing this process in the most obvious manner, using the process for genericity iteration with Jensen indexing on both sides (as described in [20, Theorem 5.8]) seems to lead to the possibility of the trees 𝒴,𝒴\mathcal{Y},\mathcal{Y}^{\prime} being non-normal. Thus, instead of this, we produce a sequence 𝒴α,𝒴ααι\left<\mathcal{Y}_{\alpha},\mathcal{Y}^{\prime}_{\alpha}\right>_{\alpha\leq\iota} of normal trees approximating the eventual desired trees 𝒴=𝒴ι\mathcal{Y}=\mathcal{Y}_{\iota} and 𝒴=𝒴ι\mathcal{Y}^{\prime}=\mathcal{Y}_{\iota}, with the sequence converging in a natural way.

Here are the details. We initially iterate linearly with the least measurable of Ult(U,D)\mathrm{Ult}(U,D) which is >κ0U>\kappa_{0}^{U} (hence <δ{<\delta}), and likewise >κ0U>\kappa_{0}^{U^{\prime}} for Ult(U,D)\mathrm{Ult}(U^{\prime},D^{\prime}), until they reach some common closure point >max(δ,δ)>\max(\delta,\delta^{\prime}). Suppose we have defined 𝒳=𝒴α,𝒳=𝒴α\mathcal{X}=\mathcal{Y}_{\alpha},\mathcal{X}^{\prime}=\mathcal{Y}^{\prime}_{\alpha}, at some point after this initial phase. These trees will be padded 0-maximal, of successor length, and if Eβ𝒳Eβ𝒳E^{\mathcal{X}}_{\beta}\neq\emptyset\neq E^{\mathcal{X}^{\prime}}_{\beta} then lh(Eβ𝒳)=lh(Eβ𝒳){\rm lh}(E^{\mathcal{X}}_{\beta})={\rm lh}(E^{\mathcal{X}^{\prime}}_{\beta}). We will determine some extenders Eα,EαE_{\alpha},E^{\prime}_{\alpha}, or stop the process. First let Gα𝔼+(Mα𝒳)G_{\alpha}\in\mathbb{E}_{+}(M^{\mathcal{X}}_{\alpha}) be the extender selected for the purposes of genericity iteration, for making (𝔼M𝒳,U|δ,U|δ)(\mathbb{E}^{M^{\mathcal{X}^{\prime}}_{\infty}},U|\delta,U^{\prime}|\delta^{\prime}) generic, and given current tree 𝒳\mathcal{X} (but not demanding that lh(Gα)>lh(Eβ𝒳){\rm lh}(G_{\alpha})>{\rm lh}(E^{\mathcal{X}}_{\beta}) for all β+1<lh(𝒳)\beta+1<{\rm lh}(\mathcal{X}); if lh(Gα)<lh(Eβ𝒳){\rm lh}(G_{\alpha})<{\rm lh}(E^{\mathcal{X}}_{\beta}) for some β\beta, that is okay); we follow the extender selection procedure for genericity iteration for Jensen indexing here (see [20, Theorem 5.8]), and if b𝒳b^{\mathcal{X}} drops then M𝒳M^{\mathcal{X}}_{\infty} will be active, and in this case F(M𝒳)F(M^{\mathcal{X}}_{\infty}) is automatically set as GαG_{\alpha}, if no extender with lower index is. (If there is no such extender, set Gα=G_{\alpha}=\emptyset.) Define GαG^{\prime}_{\alpha} symmetrically, for making (𝔼M𝒳,U|δ,U|δ)(\mathbb{E}^{M^{\mathcal{X}}_{\infty}},U|\delta,U^{\prime}|\delta^{\prime}) generic. If GαG_{\alpha}\neq\emptyset then let γ=lh(Gα)\gamma={\rm lh}(G_{\alpha}); if otherwise and b𝒳b^{\mathcal{X}} does not drop then let γ=i0𝒳(δ)\gamma=i^{\mathcal{X}}_{0\infty}(\delta), and otherwise let γ=OR(M𝒳)\gamma=\mathrm{OR}(M^{\mathcal{X}}_{\infty}). Define γ\gamma^{\prime} symmetrically. If there is F𝔼(M𝒳|γ)F\in\mathbb{E}(M^{\mathcal{X}}_{\infty}|\gamma) which is M𝒳M^{\mathcal{X}}_{\infty}-total and κ0U<crit(F)\kappa_{0}^{U}<{\rm crit}(F) and crit(F){\rm crit}(F) is not a cardinal of M𝒳M^{\mathcal{X}^{\prime}}_{\infty}, then let Fα=F_{\alpha}= the least such FF, and otherwise let Fα=GαF_{\alpha}=G_{\alpha}. (If crit(F){\rm crit}(F) is not a cardinal of M𝒳M^{\mathcal{X}^{\prime}}_{\infty} for the trivial reason that OR(M𝒳)crit(F)\mathrm{OR}(M^{\mathcal{X}^{\prime}}_{\infty})\leq{\rm crit}(F), and hence b𝒳b^{\mathcal{X}^{\prime}} drops, then it will follow from Claim 1 below that M𝒳M^{\mathcal{X}^{\prime}}_{\infty} is active, GαG^{\prime}_{\alpha}\neq\emptyset and so lh(Gα)lh(F){\rm lh}(G^{\prime}_{\alpha})\leq{\rm lh}(F), and in this case, FF will actually be irrelevant.) Define FαF^{\prime}_{\alpha} symmetrically. If FαF_{\alpha}\neq\emptyset and either Fα=F^{\prime}_{\alpha}=\emptyset or lh(Fα)lh(Fα){\rm lh}(F_{\alpha})\leq{\rm lh}(F^{\prime}_{\alpha}) then set Eα=FαE_{\alpha}=F_{\alpha}, and otherwise set Eα=E^{\prime}_{\alpha}=\emptyset; define EαE^{\prime}_{\alpha} symmetrically.

If Eα==EαE_{\alpha}=\emptyset=E^{\prime}_{\alpha} then we stop the process (setting ι=α\iota=\alpha). If EαE_{\alpha}\neq\emptyset then let β\beta be least such that Eα𝔼+(Mβ𝒳)E_{\alpha}\in\mathbb{E}_{+}(M^{\mathcal{X}}_{\beta}), and set 𝒴α+1=𝒴α(β+1)^Eα\mathcal{Y}_{\alpha+1}=\mathcal{Y}_{\alpha}{\upharpoonright}(\beta+1)\ \widehat{\ }\ E_{\alpha} (as a 0-maximal tree). If EαE^{\prime}_{\alpha}\neq\emptyset, define 𝒴α+1\mathcal{Y}^{\prime}_{\alpha+1} symmetrically. If Eα=EαE_{\alpha}\neq\emptyset=E^{\prime}_{\alpha} then set 𝒴α+1=𝒴α(β+1)\mathcal{Y}^{\prime}_{\alpha+1}=\mathcal{Y}_{\alpha}{\upharpoonright}(\beta+1), where β\beta is least such that either 𝒴α=𝒴α(β+1)\mathcal{Y}^{\prime}_{\alpha}=\mathcal{Y}^{\prime}_{\alpha}{\upharpoonright}(\beta+1) or lh(Eβ𝒴α)>lh(Eα){\rm lh}(E^{\mathcal{Y}^{\prime}_{\alpha}}_{\beta})>{\rm lh}(E_{\alpha}). And if Eα=EαE_{\alpha}=\emptyset\neq E^{\prime}_{\alpha}, proceed symmetrically.

Finally, given 𝒴α,𝒴α\mathcal{Y}_{\alpha},\mathcal{Y}^{\prime}_{\alpha} for all α<η\alpha<\eta, where η\eta is a limit, define 𝒴η\mathcal{Y}_{\eta} as the natural lim inf of the 𝒴α\mathcal{Y}_{\alpha} for α<η\alpha<\eta, extended with the relevant iteration strategy Ψ\Psi as necessary. That is, 𝒴η\mathcal{Y}_{\eta} is via Ψ\Psi, and 𝒴η\mathcal{Y}_{\eta} uses an extender EE iff 𝒴α\mathcal{Y}_{\alpha} uses EE for eventually all α<η\alpha<\eta, and if this yields a limit length tree, then we extend it using Ψ\Psi to successor length.

This determines the mutual genericity iteration. The first claim below is much as in [20, Theorem 5.8] and related arguments in [17]:

Claim 1.
  1. 1.

    𝒴α\mathcal{Y}_{\alpha} is 0-maximal and if b𝒴αb^{\mathcal{Y}_{\alpha}} drops then M𝒴αM^{\mathcal{Y}_{\alpha}}_{\infty} is active; likewise for 𝒴α\mathcal{Y}^{\prime}_{\alpha},

  2. 2.

    the process terminates at some ι<\iota<\infty, giving 𝒴=𝒴ι\mathcal{Y}=\mathcal{Y}_{\iota} and 𝒴=𝒴ι\mathcal{Y}^{\prime}=\mathcal{Y}^{\prime}_{\iota}, and

  3. 3.

    b𝒴,b𝒴b^{\mathcal{Y}},b^{\mathcal{Y}^{\prime}} do not drop (although there can be α<lh(𝒴,𝒴)\alpha<{\rm lh}(\mathcal{Y},\mathcal{Y}^{\prime}) such that [0,α]𝒴[0,\alpha]_{\mathcal{Y}} or [0,α]𝒴[0,\alpha]_{\mathcal{Y}^{\prime}} drops, because of Jensen indexing).

Proof.

Part 1: The 0-maximality is directly by definition; the rest is as in [20].

Part 2: Suppose not. Fix some large enough regular cardinal χ\chi. Assume for the sake of illustration that for all αOR\alpha\in\mathrm{OR} there are β,β>α\beta,\beta^{\prime}>\alpha such that EβE_{\beta}\neq\emptyset and EβE^{\prime}_{\beta^{\prime}}\neq\emptyset; the other case is similar. Let 𝒴=𝒴χ\mathcal{Y}=\mathcal{Y}_{\chi} and 𝒴=𝒴χ\mathcal{Y}^{\prime}=\mathcal{Y}^{\prime}_{\chi}, noting that χ+1=lh(𝒴)\chi+1={\rm lh}(\mathcal{Y}) and χ=δ(𝒴)\chi=\delta(\mathcal{Y}) and χ\chi is a limit cardinal of M𝒴M^{\mathcal{Y}}_{\infty}, and likewise for 𝒴\mathcal{Y}^{\prime}. Let Jχ+J\preccurlyeq\mathcal{H}_{\chi^{+}} with everything relevant in JJ and κ=Jχχ\kappa=J\cap\chi\in\chi, let HH be the transitive collapse of JJ and π:Hχ+\pi:H\to\mathcal{H}_{\chi^{+}} the uncollapse map. So π(κ)=χ\pi(\kappa)=\chi and we have 𝒴¯,𝒴¯H\bar{\mathcal{Y}},\bar{\mathcal{Y}}^{\prime}\in H with π(𝒴¯,𝒴¯)=(𝒴,𝒴)\pi(\bar{\mathcal{Y}},\bar{\mathcal{Y}}^{\prime})=(\mathcal{Y},\mathcal{Y}^{\prime}). Note that 𝒴¯=𝒴κ\bar{\mathcal{Y}}=\mathcal{Y}_{\kappa} and lh(𝒴¯)=κ+1{\rm lh}(\bar{\mathcal{Y}})=\kappa+1, δ(𝒴¯)=κ\delta(\bar{\mathcal{Y}})=\kappa is a limit cardinal of M𝒴¯M^{\bar{\mathcal{Y}}}_{\infty}, κb𝒴¯=b𝒴(κ+1)\kappa\in b^{\bar{\mathcal{Y}}}=b^{\mathcal{Y}}\cap(\kappa+1), and for all α[κ,χ]\alpha\in[\kappa,\chi], we have 𝒴¯=𝒴α(κ+1)\bar{\mathcal{Y}}=\mathcal{Y}_{\alpha}{\upharpoonright}(\kappa+1). Likewise for 𝒴¯\bar{\mathcal{Y}}^{\prime}.

As usual, iκχ𝒴𝒫(κ)πi^{\mathcal{Y}}_{\kappa\chi}{\upharpoonright}\mathcal{P}(\kappa)\subseteq\pi. Let EE be the first extender used forming iκχ𝒴i^{\mathcal{Y}}_{\kappa\chi}, so crit(E)=κ{\rm crit}(E)=\kappa. Let α[κ,χ)\alpha\in[\kappa,\chi) with E=EαE=E_{\alpha}. Since κ\kappa is a limit cardinal of M𝒴¯M^{\bar{\mathcal{Y}}^{\prime}}_{\infty}, and hence of M𝒴αM^{\mathcal{Y}^{\prime}_{\alpha}}_{\infty}, either (i) E=GαE=G_{\alpha} was chosen for genericity iteration purposes, and let β=α\beta=\alpha, or (ii) b𝒴αb^{\mathcal{Y}_{\alpha}} drops and Eα=F(M𝒴α)E_{\alpha}=F(M^{\mathcal{Y}_{\alpha}}_{\infty}). But if (ii) holds then as is usual for genericity iteration with λ\lambda-indexing (see [20]), there is β[κ,α)\beta\in[\kappa,\alpha) such that Eβ=GβE_{\beta}=G_{\beta} is used in 𝒴\mathcal{Y} (but not along b𝒴b^{\mathcal{Y}}), and used in 𝒴α\mathcal{Y}_{\alpha}, and Gβν(Gβ)=Eαν(Gβ)G_{\beta}{\upharpoonright}\nu(G_{\beta})=E_{\alpha}{\upharpoonright}\nu(G_{\beta}). So in either case (i) or (ii), GβG_{\beta} is used in 𝒴\mathcal{Y} and Gβν(Gβ)G_{\beta}{\upharpoonright}\nu(G_{\beta}) is derived from iκχ𝒴i^{\mathcal{Y}}_{\kappa\chi}. But note then that M𝒴β|ν(Gβ)=M𝒴|ν(Gβ)M^{\mathcal{Y}^{\prime}_{\beta}}_{\infty}|\nu(G_{\beta})=M^{\mathcal{Y}^{\prime}}_{\infty}|\nu(G_{\beta}), and therefore we obtain a contradiction like in the usual proof that genericity iteration terminates.

Part 3 is by construction and part 1. ∎

Let δ𝒴=i0𝒴(δ)\delta^{\mathcal{Y}}=i^{\mathcal{Y}}_{0\infty}(\delta) and δ𝒴=i0𝒴(δ)\delta^{\mathcal{Y}^{\prime}}=i^{\mathcal{Y}^{\prime}}_{0\infty}(\delta^{\prime}). Note that δ𝒴\delta^{\mathcal{Y}} is a strong cutpoint of M𝒴M^{\mathcal{Y}}_{\infty}, and M𝒴M^{\mathcal{Y}}_{\infty} is δ𝒴\delta^{\mathcal{Y}}-sound; likewise for δ𝒴\delta^{\mathcal{Y}^{\prime}} and M𝒴M^{\mathcal{Y}^{\prime}}_{\infty}.

Claim 2.

δ𝒴=δ𝒴\delta^{\mathcal{Y}}=\delta^{\mathcal{Y}^{\prime}}.

Proof.

We may assume δ𝒴<δ𝒴\delta^{\mathcal{Y}}<\delta^{\mathcal{Y}^{\prime}}. By minimality of δ\delta^{\prime}, δ𝒴\delta^{\mathcal{Y}} is not Woodin in M𝒴M^{\mathcal{Y}^{\prime}}_{\infty}. Let QM𝒴Q^{\prime}\triangleleft M^{\mathcal{Y}^{\prime}}_{\infty} be the Q-structure for δ𝒴\delta^{\mathcal{Y}}. Because of the inserted linear iterations at measurables, δ𝒴\delta^{\mathcal{Y}} is a cardinal of M𝒴M^{\mathcal{Y}^{\prime}}_{\infty}. Note then that by choice of D,δD^{\prime},\delta^{\prime} (and smallness), δ𝒴\delta^{\mathcal{Y}} is a strong cutpoint of QQ^{\prime}. But (M𝒴|δ𝒴,U|δ,U|δ)(M^{\mathcal{Y}^{\prime}}_{\infty}|\delta^{\mathcal{Y}},U|\delta,U^{\prime}|\delta^{\prime}) is meas-lim extender algebra generic over M𝒴M^{\mathcal{Y}}_{\infty} at δ𝒴\delta^{\mathcal{Y}}, and (M𝒴|δ𝒴,U|δ,U|δ)(M^{\mathcal{Y}}_{\infty}|\delta^{\mathcal{Y}},U|\delta,U^{\prime}|\delta^{\prime}) is likewise over QQ^{\prime}, also at δ𝒴\delta^{\mathcal{Y}}, because δ𝒴\delta^{\mathcal{Y}} is a cardinal of M𝒴M^{\mathcal{Y}^{\prime}}_{\infty}. Therefore these two premice can be lifted to premice (M𝒴)+(M^{\mathcal{Y}}_{\infty})^{+} and (Q)+(Q^{\prime})^{+} over (M𝒴|δ𝒴,M𝒴|δ𝒴,U|δ,U|δ)(M^{\mathcal{Y}}_{\infty}|\delta^{\mathcal{Y}},M^{\mathcal{Y}^{\prime}}_{\infty}|\delta^{\mathcal{Y}},U|\delta,U^{\prime}|\delta^{\prime}). Comparing (M𝒴)+(M^{\mathcal{Y}}_{\infty})^{+} with (Q)+(Q^{\prime})^{+} (so the comparison is above δ𝒴\delta^{\mathcal{Y}}) and considering smallness and δ𝒴\delta^{\mathcal{Y}}-soundness, we have (Q)+(M𝒴)+(Q^{\prime})^{+}\triangleleft(M^{\mathcal{Y}}_{\infty})^{+}.

Now working in (M𝒴)+(M^{\mathcal{Y}}_{\infty})^{+}, where we have U|δU|\delta, M𝒴|δ𝒴M^{\mathcal{Y}}_{\infty}|\delta^{\mathcal{Y}}, U|δU^{\prime}|\delta^{\prime}, M𝒴|δ𝒴M^{\mathcal{Y}^{\prime}}_{\infty}|\delta^{\mathcal{Y}} and QQ^{\prime}, we can recover 𝒴¯δ𝒴\bar{\mathcal{Y}}{\upharpoonright}\delta^{\mathcal{Y}} and 𝒴¯(δ𝒴+1)\bar{\mathcal{Y}^{\prime}}{\upharpoonright}(\delta^{\mathcal{Y}^{\prime}}+1), where 𝒴¯\bar{\mathcal{Y}} is just like 𝒴\mathcal{Y} but as a tree on U|δU|\delta, and 𝒴¯\bar{\mathcal{Y}^{\prime}} likewise. For (i) we have U|δU|\delta and U|δU^{\prime}|\delta^{\prime}, and we just proceed by comparing U|δU|\delta with M𝒴|δYM^{\mathcal{Y}}_{\infty}|\delta^{Y} and U|δU^{\prime}|\delta^{\prime} with QQ^{\prime}, (ii) QQ^{\prime} determines the branch of 𝒴¯\bar{\mathcal{Y}^{\prime}} at stage δ𝒴\delta^{\mathcal{Y}}, and (iii) the intermediate Q-structures used to guide 𝒴¯,𝒴¯\bar{\mathcal{Y}},\bar{\mathcal{Y}^{\prime}} are segments of M𝒴|δ𝒴M^{\mathcal{Y}}_{\infty}|\delta^{\mathcal{Y}} and M𝒴|δ𝒴M^{\mathcal{Y}^{\prime}}_{\infty}|\delta^{\mathcal{Y}} (for example if ξ=δ(𝒴¯ξ)\xi=\delta(\bar{\mathcal{Y}^{\prime}}{\upharpoonright}\xi) and the Q-structure for 𝒴¯ξ\bar{\mathcal{Y}^{\prime}}{\upharpoonright}\xi is non-trivial, then ξ\xi is a limit of measurable cardinals of M𝒴M^{\mathcal{Y}^{\prime}}_{\infty}, hence a limit cardinal of M𝒴M^{\mathcal{Y}}_{\infty}, so the Q-structures on both sides do not overlap ξ\xi, which implies that the next extenders used have index beyond the Q-structures (and likewise at all stages after ξ\xi), so the Q-structures are retained).

So in (M𝒴)+(M^{\mathcal{Y}}_{\infty})^{+}, where δ𝒴\delta^{\mathcal{Y}} is a regular cardinal, we can execute a slight variant of the termination-of-genericity-iteration proof used above for Claim 1 (with δ𝒴\delta^{\mathcal{Y}} in the role of χ\chi there). (We may not have the sequence of trees 𝒴α,𝒴αα<δ𝒴\left<\mathcal{Y}_{\alpha},\mathcal{Y}^{\prime}_{\alpha}\right>_{\alpha<\delta^{\mathcal{Y}}} in (M𝒴)+(M^{\mathcal{Y}}_{\infty})^{+}, but note that the trees we do have are enough.) ∎

Let δ=δ𝒴=δ𝒴\delta^{*}=\delta^{\mathcal{Y}}=\delta^{\mathcal{Y}^{\prime}} and Q=M𝒴Q=M^{\mathcal{Y}}_{\infty} and Q=M𝒴Q^{\prime}=M^{\mathcal{Y}^{\prime}}_{\infty}. Note now that (by δ\delta^{*}-soundness and as δ\delta^{*} is a strong cutpoint on both sides), Q,QQ,Q^{\prime} are equivalent modulo a generic above δ\delta^{*}, i.e. letting Q+Q^{+} be Q[Q|δ]Q[Q^{\prime}|\delta^{*}], considered as a premouse over (Q|δ,Q|δ)(Q|\delta^{*},Q^{\prime}|\delta^{*}), and (Q)+(Q^{\prime})^{+} likewise (we no longer need U|δU|\delta and U|δU^{\prime}|\delta^{\prime}), then Q+=(Q)+Q^{+}=(Q^{\prime})^{+}. It follows that κ0Q=κ0Q\kappa_{0}^{Q}=\kappa_{0}^{Q^{\prime}} and 𝒱1Q=𝒱1Q\mathscr{V}_{1}^{Q}=\mathscr{V}_{1}^{Q^{\prime}}, and by uniqueness of iteration strategies, the above-δ\delta^{*} strategy for QQ translates to that of QQ^{\prime}. Finally let 𝒵\mathcal{Z} be the normal tree equivalent to the stack (𝒲,D,𝒴)(\mathcal{W},D,\mathcal{Y}) and 𝒵\mathcal{Z}^{\prime} that to (𝒲,D,𝒴)(\mathcal{W}^{\prime},D^{\prime},\mathcal{Y}^{\prime}); it follows that Γ𝒵=Γ𝒵\Gamma_{\mathcal{Z}}=\Gamma_{\mathcal{Z}^{\prime}}.

Let j:𝒱𝒱1Uj:\mathscr{V}\to\mathscr{V}_{1}^{U} and j:𝒱𝒱1Uj^{\prime}:\mathscr{V}\to\mathscr{V}_{1}^{U^{\prime}} be the correct iteration maps. Now iD,𝒴𝒱1Ui^{D,\mathcal{Y}}{\upharpoonright}\mathscr{V}_{1}^{U} is the correct iteration map k:𝒱1U𝒱1Qk:\mathscr{V}_{1}^{U}\to\mathscr{V}_{1}^{Q} (because we wanted this, we couldn’t just compare UU with UU^{\prime} in the usual manner). Likewise k=iD,𝒴𝒱1Uk^{\prime}=i^{D^{\prime},\mathcal{Y}^{\prime}}{\upharpoonright}\mathscr{V}_{1}^{U^{\prime}}. So

kj=kj:𝒱𝒱1Q=𝒱1Qk\circ j=k^{\prime}\circ j^{\prime}:\mathscr{V}\to\mathscr{V}_{1}^{Q}=\mathscr{V}_{1}^{Q^{\prime}}

is also the correct iteration map. So the minimal kjk\circ j-pullback of Γ𝒵\Gamma_{\mathcal{Z}} equals the minimal kjk^{\prime}\circ j^{\prime}-pullback of Γ𝒵\Gamma_{\mathcal{Z}^{\prime}} (a strategy for 𝒱\mathscr{V}); denote this by Ψ\Psi^{*}. Recall that Ψ\Psi is the minimal jj-pullback of Γ𝒲\Gamma_{\mathcal{W}}, and Ψ\Psi the minimal jj^{\prime}-pullback of Γ𝒲\Gamma_{\mathcal{W}^{\prime}}. It suffices to see that Ψ=Ψ\Psi=\Psi^{*}, since then by symmetry, Ψ=Ψ\Psi^{\prime}=\Psi^{*} also.

Let ΣQ\Sigma^{Q} be the above-κ0Q\kappa_{0}^{Q} strategy for QQ given by ΣQ\Sigma_{Q}. Let ΣU\Sigma^{U} be likewise for UU. Then by κ0U\kappa_{0}^{U}-soundness and since κ0U\kappa_{0}^{U} is a cutpoint of UU, ΣU\Sigma^{U} is the minimal iD,𝒴i^{D,\mathcal{Y}}-pullback of ΣQ\Sigma^{Q}. But then Γ𝒲\Gamma_{\mathcal{W}} is the minimal kk-pullback of Γ𝒵\Gamma_{\mathcal{Z}}; for trees 𝒮\mathcal{S} on 𝒱1U\mathscr{V}_{1}^{U} with lh(E0𝒮)>γ𝒱1U{\rm lh}(E^{\mathcal{S}}_{0})>\gamma^{\mathscr{V}_{1}^{U}}, this uses that kiD,𝒴k\subseteq i^{D,\mathcal{Y}} and the fine structural translation of 𝒮\mathcal{S} to a tree on UU; for trees with lh(E0𝒮)<γ𝒱1U{\rm lh}(E^{\mathcal{S}}_{0})<\gamma^{\mathscr{V}_{1}^{U}}, it uses minimal hull condensation for ΣM\Sigma_{M}, and the fact that the action of Γ𝒲\Gamma_{\mathcal{W}} and Γ𝒵\Gamma_{\mathcal{Z}} on such trees in induced by ΣM\Sigma_{M}. Therefore Ψ=Ψ\Psi=\Psi^{*}, as desired. ∎

4.12.5 Normal trees on 𝒱1\mathscr{V}_{1}

So we have a good short-normal strategy Ψsn\Psi_{\mathrm{sn}}, extending Ψ𝒱1,𝒱1\Psi_{\mathscr{V}_{1},\mathscr{V}_{1}^{-}}. This extends easily to a normal strategy Σ𝒱1\Sigma_{\mathscr{V}_{1}}.

Definition 4.29.

We define a 0-maximal iteration strategy Σ𝒱1\Sigma_{\mathscr{V}_{1}} for 𝒱1\mathscr{V}_{1}, determined by the following properties:

  1. 1.

    ΨsnΣ𝒱1\Psi_{\mathrm{sn}}\subseteq\Sigma_{\mathscr{V}_{1}}.

  2. 2.

    Let 𝒯\mathcal{T} be on 𝒱1\mathscr{V}_{1}, 0-maximal, of length η+2\eta+2, with 𝒯η+1\mathcal{T}{\upharpoonright}\eta+1 short-normal and via Ψsn\Psi_{\mathrm{sn}}, and Eη𝒯E^{\mathcal{T}}_{\eta} long. Then (by goodness) Mη+1𝒯M^{\mathcal{T}}_{\eta+1} is a non-dropping iterate of 𝒱1\mathscr{V}_{1} via a tree 𝒰\mathcal{U} according to Ψ𝒱1,𝒱1\Psi_{\mathscr{V}_{1},\mathscr{V}_{1}^{-}}, and lh(Eη𝒯)=δ0Mη+1𝒯{\rm lh}(E^{\mathcal{T}}_{\eta})=\delta_{0}^{M^{\mathcal{T}}_{\eta+1}}. Then Σ𝒱1\Sigma_{\mathscr{V}_{1}} acts on trees normally extending 𝒯η+2\mathcal{T}{\upharpoonright}\eta+2 by following Ψ𝒰\Psi_{\mathcal{U}}, until another long extender is used.

  3. 3.

    Likewise, whenever 𝒯\mathcal{T} is on 𝒱1\mathscr{V}_{1}, via Σ𝒱1\Sigma_{\mathscr{V}_{1}}, and Eη𝒯E^{\mathcal{T}}_{\eta} is long, then Mη+1𝒯M^{\mathcal{T}}_{\eta+1} is a non-dropping Ψ𝒱1,𝒱1\Psi_{\mathscr{V}_{1},\mathscr{V}_{1}^{-}}-iterate, via a tree 𝒰\mathcal{U}, and Σ𝒱1\Sigma_{\mathscr{V}_{1}} extends 𝒯(η+2)\mathcal{T}{\upharpoonright}(\eta+2) by following Ψ𝒰\Psi_{\mathcal{U}}, until another long extender is used.

  4. 4.

    If λ\lambda is a limit and there are long extenders used cofinally in λ\lambda, there is a unique 𝒯λ\mathcal{T}{\upharpoonright}\lambda-cofinal branch, and Mλ𝒯M^{\mathcal{T}}_{\lambda} is again an iterate via Ψ𝒱1,𝒱1\Psi_{\mathscr{V}_{1},\mathscr{V}_{1}^{-}} (by normalization for transfinite stacks). In this case, δ(𝒯λ)\delta(\mathcal{T}{\upharpoonright}\lambda) is the least measurable of Mη𝒯M^{\mathcal{T}}_{\eta}, so we can have 𝒯[λ,α)\mathcal{T}{\upharpoonright}[\lambda,\alpha) based on Mλ𝒯|δ0Mλ𝒯M^{\mathcal{T}}_{\lambda}|\delta_{0}^{M^{\mathcal{T}}_{\lambda}}, with λ<α\lambda<\alpha. This interval is formed using Ψ𝒱,𝒱\Psi_{\mathscr{V},\mathscr{V}^{-}} (see Definition 4.23). Letting α\alpha be least such that (λ,α]𝒯(\lambda,\alpha]_{\mathcal{T}} does not drop and δ0Mα𝒯<lh(Eα𝒯)\delta_{0}^{M^{\mathcal{T}}_{\alpha}}<{\rm lh}(E^{\mathcal{T}}_{\alpha}), then (by normalization) there is a short-normal tree 𝒰\mathcal{U} via Ψ𝒱1,𝒱1\Psi_{\mathscr{V}_{1},\mathscr{V}_{1}^{-}} with last model Mα𝒯M^{\mathcal{T}}_{\alpha}, and Σ𝒱1\Sigma_{\mathscr{V}_{1}} extends 𝒯(α+1)\mathcal{T}{\upharpoonright}(\alpha+1) by following Ψ𝒰\Psi_{\mathcal{U}}, until the next long extender.

The following lemma is now easy to see:

Lemma 4.29.

Σ𝒱1\Sigma_{\mathscr{V}_{1}} is a good 0-maximal strategy for 𝒱1\mathscr{V}_{1}. Moreover, for every successor length tree 𝒯\mathcal{T} via Σ𝒱1\Sigma_{\mathscr{V}_{1}} there is a unique short-normal tree via Ψsn\Psi_{\mathrm{sn}} with the same last model.

Lemma 4.29.

Σ𝒱1\Sigma_{\mathscr{V}_{1}} has minimal inflation condensation (mic).

Proof.

We just consider short-normal trees; it is easy to extend this to arbitrary normal trees, and we leave this extension to the reader.

Let 𝒯,𝒰\mathcal{T},\mathcal{U} be short-normal trees on 𝒱1\mathscr{V}_{1}, via Ψsn\Psi_{\mathrm{sn}}, such that 𝒰\mathcal{U} has length λ+1\lambda+1 for some limit λ\lambda, 𝒯\mathcal{T} has successor length, and 𝒰λ\mathcal{U}{\upharpoonright}\lambda is a minimal inflation of 𝒯\mathcal{T}; we must show that 𝒰\mathcal{U} is also a minimal inflation of 𝒯\mathcal{T}. Let 𝒯=𝒯0^𝒯1\mathcal{T}=\mathcal{T}_{0}\ \widehat{\ }\ \mathcal{T}_{1} and 𝒰=𝒰0^𝒰1\mathcal{U}=\mathcal{U}_{0}\ \widehat{\ }\ \mathcal{U}_{1} with lower components 𝒯0,𝒰0\mathcal{T}_{0},\mathcal{U}_{0} and upper 𝒯1,𝒰1\mathcal{T}_{1},\mathcal{U}_{1}.

Now Ψ𝒱1,𝒱1\Psi_{\mathscr{V}_{1},\mathscr{V}_{1}^{-}} has mic, because it follows Σ\Sigma_{\mathcal{M}_{\infty}}, which has mic, since ΣM\Sigma_{M} does, and by [15, ***Theorem 10.2]. So we may assume 𝒯1\mathcal{T}_{1}\neq\emptyset. Therefore, 𝒯0\mathcal{T}_{0} has successor length α+1\alpha+1, [0,α]𝒯0[0,\alpha]_{\mathcal{T}_{0}} does not drop, and 𝒯1\mathcal{T}_{1} is based on Mα𝒯0M^{\mathcal{T}_{0}}_{\alpha} and is above δ0Mα𝒯0\delta_{0}^{M^{\mathcal{T}_{0}}_{\alpha}} and uses only short extenders. And 𝒰0,𝒰1,β\mathcal{U}_{0},\mathcal{U}_{1},\beta are likewise, and note that βIα𝒯min𝒰\beta\in I^{\mathcal{T}\rightsquigarrow_{\min}\mathcal{U}}_{\alpha}. Let

Π0=Πβ𝒯min𝒰:𝒯0min𝒰0\Pi_{0}=\Pi^{\mathcal{T}\rightsquigarrow_{\min}\mathcal{U}}_{\beta}:\mathcal{T}_{0}\hookrightarrow_{\min}\mathcal{U}_{0}

(the minimal tree embedding at stage β\beta of the inflation), and j:Mα𝒯0Mβ𝒰0j:M^{\mathcal{T}_{0}}_{\alpha}\to M^{\mathcal{U}_{0}}_{\beta} be the copy map determined by Π0\Pi_{0}. Then in fact, Mβ𝒰0M^{\mathcal{U}_{0}}_{\beta} is a Σ𝒱,𝒱\Sigma_{\mathscr{V},\mathscr{V}^{-}}-iterate of 𝒱\mathscr{V} where 𝒱=Mα𝒯0\mathscr{V}=M^{\mathcal{T}_{0}}_{\alpha}, and jj is the iteration map (see [15, ***Lemma 4.5]).

Now it suffices to see that Ψsn\Psi_{\mathrm{sn}} has minimal hull condensation (mhc) with respect to extensions of Π0\Pi_{0} “above δ0\delta_{0}”; that is, whenever 𝒯2,𝒰2\mathcal{T}_{2},\mathcal{U}_{2} are trees on Mα𝒯0M^{\mathcal{T}_{0}}_{\alpha} and Mβ𝒰0M^{\mathcal{U}_{0}}_{\beta}, above δ0Mα𝒯0\delta_{0}^{M^{\mathcal{T}_{0}}_{\alpha}} and δ0Mβ𝒰0\delta_{0}^{M^{\mathcal{U}_{0}}_{\beta}} respectively, with 𝒰0^𝒰2\mathcal{U}_{0}\ \widehat{\ }\ \mathcal{U}_{2} via Ψsn\Psi_{\mathrm{sn}}, and

Π:𝒯0^𝒯2min𝒰0^𝒰2\Pi:\mathcal{T}_{0}\ \widehat{\ }\ \mathcal{T}_{2}\hookrightarrow_{\min}\mathcal{U}_{0}\ \widehat{\ }\ \mathcal{U}_{2}

is a minimal tree embedding with Π0Π\Pi_{0}\subseteq\Pi, then 𝒯0^𝒯2\mathcal{T}_{0}\ \widehat{\ }\ \mathcal{T}_{2} is also via Ψsn\Psi_{\mathrm{sn}}.

Let 𝒯2=j𝒯2\mathcal{T}_{2}^{\prime}=j``\mathcal{T}_{2}, a (putative) tree on Mβ𝒰0M^{\mathcal{U}_{0}}_{\beta}. Then 𝒯2\mathcal{T}_{2}^{\prime} has wellfounded models, and in fact, there is a minimal tree embedding

Π:𝒰0^𝒯2min𝒰0^𝒰2\Pi^{\prime}:\mathcal{U}_{0}\ \widehat{\ }\ \mathcal{T}_{2}^{\prime}\hookrightarrow_{\min}\mathcal{U}_{0}\ \widehat{\ }\ \mathcal{U}_{2}

determined in the obvious manner: for α<lh(𝒰0)\alpha<{\rm lh}(\mathcal{U}_{0}), we have IαΠ=[α,α]I_{\alpha}^{\Pi^{\prime}}=[\alpha,\alpha], and for α<lh(𝒯2)\alpha<{\rm lh}(\mathcal{T}_{2}), we have Ilh(𝒰0)+αΠ=γlh(𝒯0)+αΠI^{\Pi^{\prime}}_{{\rm lh}(\mathcal{U}_{0})+\alpha}=\gamma^{\Pi}_{{\rm lh}(\mathcal{T}_{0})+\alpha}; this determines Π\Pi^{\prime}.

Claim 1.

𝒰0^𝒯2\mathcal{U}_{0}\ \widehat{\ }\ \mathcal{T}_{2}^{\prime} is via Ψsn\Psi_{\mathrm{sn}}.

Proof.

If lh(E0𝒯2)<γMβ𝒰0{\rm lh}(E^{\mathcal{T}_{2}^{\prime}}_{0})<\gamma^{M^{\mathcal{U}_{0}}_{\beta}} then this is just because Ψ𝒰0\Psi_{\mathcal{U}_{0}} follows the strategy induced by ΣMβ𝒰00\Sigma_{M^{\mathcal{U}_{0}}_{\beta}\downarrow 0} in this case, which has mhc.

So suppose γMβ𝒰0<lh(E0𝒯2)\gamma^{M^{\mathcal{U}_{0}}_{\beta}}<{\rm lh}(E^{\mathcal{T}_{2}^{\prime}}_{0}). Let (𝒲,U,𝒴)(\mathcal{W},U,\mathcal{Y}) be MM-standard for 𝒰0\mathcal{U}_{0}. Let :Mβ𝒰0𝒱1U\ell:M^{\mathcal{U}_{0}}_{\beta}\to\mathscr{V}_{1}^{U} be the iteration map. Since 𝒰2\mathcal{U}_{2} follows Ψ𝒰0\Psi_{\mathcal{U}_{0}}, the minimal \ell-copy 𝒰2~\widetilde{\mathcal{U}_{2}} of 𝒰2\mathcal{U}_{2} (a tree on 𝒱1U\mathscr{V}_{1}^{U}) follows Γ𝒲\Gamma_{\mathcal{W}}. Let 𝒯2~\widetilde{\mathcal{T}_{2}^{\prime}} be the minimal \ell-copy of 𝒯2\mathcal{T}_{2}^{\prime} (see [15, ***10.3, 10.4]). Then 𝒯2~\widetilde{\mathcal{T}_{2}^{\prime}} has wellfounded models, and in fact there is a minimal tree embedding

Π~:𝒯2~min𝒰2~,\widetilde{\Pi^{\prime}}:\widetilde{\mathcal{T}_{2}^{\prime}}\hookrightarrow_{\min}\widetilde{\mathcal{U}_{2}},

determined in the obvious manner. But since 𝒰2~\widetilde{\mathcal{U}_{2}} is via Γ𝒲\Gamma_{\mathcal{W}}, and this strategy has mhc, because ΣU\Sigma_{U} does, therefore 𝒯2~\widetilde{\mathcal{T}_{2}^{\prime}} is also via Γ𝒲\Gamma_{\mathcal{W}}, and therefore 𝒯2\mathcal{T}_{2}^{\prime} is via Ψ𝒰0\Psi_{\mathcal{U}_{0}}, as desired. ∎

Claim 2.

𝒯0^𝒯2\mathcal{T}_{0}\ \widehat{\ }\ \mathcal{T}_{2} is via Ψsn\Psi_{\mathrm{sn}}.

Proof.

If lh(E0𝒯2)<γMα𝒯0{\rm lh}(E^{\mathcal{T}_{2}}_{0})<\gamma^{M^{\mathcal{T}_{0}}_{\alpha}}, this is again easy, using mhc for ΣMα𝒯00\Sigma_{M^{\mathcal{T}_{0}}_{\alpha}\downarrow 0}. So suppose otherwise. Let (𝒲,U,𝒴)(\mathcal{W},U,\mathcal{Y}) be simultaneously MM-standard for 𝒯0\mathcal{T}_{0} and for 𝒰0\mathcal{U}_{0}. Let \ell be as before, and k:Mα𝒯0𝒱1Uk:M^{\mathcal{T}_{0}}_{\alpha}\to\mathscr{V}_{1}^{U} be the correct iteration map. So Ψ𝒯0\Psi_{\mathcal{T}_{0}} and Ψ𝒰0\Psi_{\mathcal{U}_{0}} are the minimal kk-pullback and \ell-pullback of Γ𝒲\Gamma_{\mathcal{W}} respectively. But j=k\ell\circ j=k, since these are correct iteration maps, and therefore Ψ𝒯0\Psi_{\mathcal{T}_{0}} is the minimal jj-pullback of Ψ𝒰0\Psi_{\mathcal{U}_{0}}, which, since 𝒯2\mathcal{T}_{2}^{\prime} is via Ψ𝒰0\Psi_{\mathcal{U}_{0}}, proves the claim. ∎

This completes the proof. ∎

The preceding proof does not seem to give that Σ𝒱1\Sigma_{\mathscr{V}_{1}} has mhc, because it relies heavily on the fact that j=k\ell\circ j=k, and if jj were instead just a copy map arising from an arbitrary minimal tree embedding, then it need not be an iteration map (and in fact Mβ𝒰0M^{\mathcal{U}_{0}}_{\beta} need not be an iterate of Mα𝒯0M^{\mathcal{T}_{0}}_{\alpha}).

5 The second Varsovian model 𝒱2\mathscr{V}_{2}

5.1 The δ1\delta_{1}-short tree strategy for 𝒱1\mathscr{V}_{1}

Definition 5.1.

Let 𝒱\mathscr{V} be a non-dropping Σ𝒱1\Sigma_{\mathscr{V}_{1}}-iterate of 𝒱1\mathscr{V}_{1}.

Let 𝒯\mathcal{T} be a short-normal tree on 𝒱\mathscr{V} via Σ𝒱\Sigma_{\mathscr{V}}, based on 𝒱|δ1𝒱\mathscr{V}|\delta_{1}^{\mathscr{V}}, of limit length. Let b=Σ𝒱(𝒯)b=\Sigma_{\mathscr{V}}(\mathcal{T}). Say that 𝒯\mathcal{T} is δ1\delta_{1}-short iff either bb drops or δ(𝒯)<ib𝒯(δ1𝒱)\delta(\mathcal{T})<i^{\mathcal{T}}_{b}(\delta_{1}^{\mathscr{V}}), and δ1\delta_{1}-maximal otherwise.

We define δ1\delta_{1}-short and δ1\delta_{1}-maximal analogously for trees on MM.

It will be shown in [13] that 𝒱1\mathscr{V}_{1} knows its own strategy for δ1\delta_{1}-short trees, and, moreover, has a modified P-construction which also computes the correct branch model Mb𝒯M^{\mathcal{T}}_{b} for δ1\delta_{1}-maximal 𝒯\mathcal{T}, given that 𝒯\mathcal{T} is appropriate for forming a P-construction.

In this paper we explain the main new idea needed to prove this, illustrated with a restricted class of trees 𝒯\mathcal{T} (P-illustrative trees) which suffice, for example, for genericity iterations at δ1𝒱1\delta_{1}^{\mathscr{V}_{1}}. This restriction will ensure that for such 𝒯\mathcal{T} and limits λ\lambda with 𝒯λ\mathcal{T}{\upharpoonright}\lambda being δ1\delta_{1}-short and QQ be the correct Q-structure for 𝒯λ\mathcal{T}{\upharpoonright}\lambda, the only overlaps of δ(𝒯λ)\delta(\mathcal{T}{\upharpoonright}\lambda) in QQ are long extenders, and this will mean that we have no need for *-translation. We will compute QQ via a modified P-construction; a key issue is that the P-construction has a new feature, due to the long extenders on the 𝒯\mathcal{T}-side, and the extenders with critical point κ0M\kappa_{0}^{M} on the MM-side. Similarly, for δ1\delta_{1}-maximal P-illustrative trees 𝒯\mathcal{T}, Mb𝒯M^{\mathcal{T}}_{b} will also be computed by a modified P-construction. We will need a new argument (5.1.1) to see that the P-construction does indeed compute the correct model. We will actually first consider analogous P-illustrative trees on MM, and then transfer these results to trees on 𝒱1\mathscr{V}_{1}. We will then adapt the results to δ1𝒱\delta_{1}^{\mathscr{V}}-sound non-dropping Σ𝒱1\Sigma_{\mathscr{V}_{1}}-iterates 𝒱\mathscr{V} of 𝒱1\mathscr{V}_{1}.

P-illustrative trees suffice to construct 𝒱2\mathscr{V}_{2}, and prove a significant amount about it. However, in order to prove that it fully knows how to iterate itself, and related facts, we need to consider arbitrary trees, including the full δ1\delta_{1}-short tree strategy. Such facts are moreover used our proof that 𝒱2\mathscr{V}_{2} is the mantle (because it uses a comparison argument, which seems needs iterability with respect to arbitrary trees). In order to deal with arbitrary trees, we need to deal with trees having overlapped Q-structures, and therefore need *-translation, adapted to incorporate the modified P-construction. This material is deferred to [13]; at certain points we summarize results from there we need.

5.1.1 P-illustrative trees on MM

Definition 5.2.

Given a (strategy) premouse NN and κηORN\kappa\leq\eta\in\mathrm{OR}^{N}, we say that η\eta is a κ\kappa-cutpoint of NN iff for all E𝔼+NE\in\mathbb{E}_{+}^{N}, if crit(E)<η<lh(E){\rm crit}(E)<\eta<{\rm lh}(E) then crit(E)=κ{\rm crit}(E)=\kappa, and a strong κ\kappa-cutpoint iff for all E𝔼+NE\in\mathbb{E}_{+}^{N}, if crit(E)η<lh(E){\rm crit}(E)\leq\eta<{\rm lh}(E) then crit(E)=κ{\rm crit}(E)=\kappa.

Definition 5.3.

Let 𝒯\mathcal{T} be an iteration tree on an MswswM_{\mathrm{swsw}}-like premouse NN and Σ\Sigma a partial strategy for NN. We say that 𝒯\mathcal{T} is P-illustrative iff there are E1,U,λ,η,α0,μE_{1},U,\lambda,\eta,\alpha_{0},\mu such that:

  1. 1.

    either

    1. (i)

      E1=E_{1}=\emptyset, U=NU=N and λ=κ1N\lambda=\kappa_{1}^{N}, or

    2. (ii)

      E1𝔼NE_{1}\in\mathbb{E}^{N}, E1E_{1} is NN-total, crit(E1)=κ1N{\rm crit}(E_{1})=\kappa_{1}^{N}, U=Ult(N,E1)U=\mathrm{Ult}(N,E_{1}) and λ=λ(E1)=κ1U\lambda=\lambda(E_{1})=\kappa_{1}^{U},

  2. 2.

    𝒯N\mathcal{T}\in N, 𝒯\mathcal{T} is normal, of limit length, is above κ0N\kappa_{0}^{N} and based on N|δ1NN|\delta_{1}^{N}, and letting 𝒯\mathcal{T}^{\prime} be the corresponding tree on N|δ1N|\delta_{1}, we have 𝒯U|λ\mathcal{T}^{\prime}\in U|\lambda,

  3. 3.

    κ0N<η<λ\kappa_{0}^{N}<\eta<\lambda and η\eta is a strong κ0N\kappa_{0}^{N}-cutpoint of UU, and η\eta is a UU-cardinal, and if E1E_{1}\neq\emptyset then κ1N<η\kappa_{1}^{N}<\eta464646Note there is no F𝔼UF\in\mathbb{E}^{U} with crit(F)=κ0N{\rm crit}(F)=\kappa_{0}^{N} and λ(F)=η\lambda(F)=\eta, since otherwise NN is past superstrong.

  4. 4.

    0α0<η0\leq\alpha_{0}<\eta and α0<lh(𝒯)\alpha_{0}<{\rm lh}(\mathcal{T}) and [0,α0]𝒯[0,\alpha_{0}]_{\mathcal{T}} does not drop and μ=κ0Mα0𝒯<η\mu=\kappa_{0}^{M^{\mathcal{T}}_{\alpha_{0}}}<\eta,

  5. 5.

    𝒯[α0,lh(𝒯))\mathcal{T}{\upharpoonright}[\alpha_{0},{\rm lh}(\mathcal{T})) is above (μ+)Mα0𝒯(\mu^{+})^{M^{\mathcal{T}}_{\alpha_{0}}},

  6. 6.

    for each β+1(α0,lh(𝒯))\beta+1\in(\alpha_{0},{\rm lh}(\mathcal{T})), every Woodin of Mβ𝒯|lh(Eβ𝒯)M^{\mathcal{T}}_{\beta}|{\rm lh}(E^{\mathcal{T}}_{\beta}) is <μ{<\mu},

  7. 7.

    η<δ=δ(𝒯)\eta<\delta=\delta(\mathcal{T}), η\eta is the largest cardinal of U|δU|\delta, 𝒯\mathcal{T} is definable from parameters over U|δU|\delta, and U|δU|\delta is extender algebra generic over M(𝒯)M(\mathcal{T}).

Condition 6 prevents us from requiring *-translation.

Definition 5.4.

Let 𝒯\mathcal{T} be P-illustrative and N,UN,U as in 5.3. We define the P-construction 𝒫U(M(𝒯))\mathscr{P}^{U}(M(\mathcal{T})) of UU over M(𝒯)M(\mathcal{T}). This is the largest premouse PP such that:

  1. 1.

    M(𝒯)PM(\mathcal{T})\trianglelefteq P\vDashδ\delta is Woodin”, where δ=δ(𝒯)\delta=\delta(\mathcal{T}),

  2. 2.

    for α[δ,ORP]\alpha\in[\delta,\mathrm{OR}^{P}], P||αP||\alpha is active iff U||αU||\alpha is active,474747 U||δU||\delta is passive, because η\eta is the largest cardinal of U||δU||\delta and by Footnote 46.

  3. 3.

    Let α0\alpha_{0} be as in 5.3, let α>δ\alpha>\delta be such that U||αU||\alpha is active and let E=FP||αE=F^{P||\alpha} and F=FU||αF=F^{U||\alpha}. Then either:

    1. (a)

      crit(F)>κ0M{\rm crit}(F)>\kappa_{0}^{M} (so crit(F)>δ{\rm crit}(F)>\delta) and EOR=FORE{\upharpoonright}\mathrm{OR}=F{\upharpoonright}\mathrm{OR}, or

    2. (b)

      crit(F)=κ0M{\rm crit}(F)=\kappa_{0}^{M} and Ei0α0𝒯κ0+M=Fκ0+ME\circ i^{\mathcal{T}}_{0\alpha_{0}}{\upharpoonright}\kappa_{0}^{+M}=F{\upharpoonright}\kappa_{0}^{+M}.

Remark 5.4.

A key point in the above definition is that in condition 3b, with j=i0α0𝒯j=i^{\mathcal{T}}_{0\alpha_{0}}, we only require EjE\circ j and FF to agree over ordinals, not the full model N|κ0+NN|\kappa_{0}^{+N} (although N|κ0+NN|\kappa_{0}^{+N} is an initial segment of both sides). In fact (as we require that PP is a premouse),

Ej(N|κ0+N)F(N|κ0+N),E\circ j{\upharpoonright}(N|\kappa_{0}^{+N})\neq F{\upharpoonright}(N|\kappa_{0}^{+N}),

because P|κ0=N|κ0=U|κ0P|\kappa_{0}=N|\kappa_{0}=U|\kappa_{0}, but P|λ(E)N|λ(F)P|\lambda(E)\neq N|\lambda(F), and because EE must cohere P|αP|\alpha, therefore E(j(N|κ0))F(N|κ0)E(j(N|\kappa_{0}))\neq F(N|\kappa_{0}). However, recall the following fact, which we leave as an exercise for the reader.

Fact 5.4.

Let NN be a passive premouse, κ\kappa be a cardinal of NN, Xκ+NX\subseteq\kappa^{+N} be unbounded in κ+N\kappa^{+N} and f:XORNf:X\to\mathrm{OR}^{N}. Then there is at most one active premouse NN^{\prime} whose reduct is NN and FNOR=fF^{N}{\upharpoonright}\mathrm{OR}=f, and in fact, NN^{\prime} is Σ1\Sigma_{1}-definable over (N,f)(N,f).

(Note though that it is important that NN is given; there can actually be another active N1N_{1}^{\prime} with NN1N\neq N_{1}, but FN1OR=fF^{N_{1}^{\prime}}{\upharpoonright}\mathrm{OR}=f.)

Remark 5.4.

It is not immediate that the P-construction PP is well-defined, as we have defined it directly as the largest premouse with the above properties, and one also needs one small observation to see that, if well-defined, then PP is unique (and appropriately locally definable).

Consider instead defining P|αP|\alpha and P||αP||\alpha by recursion on α\alpha. Note that j¯=jκ0+NU|ηU|δ\bar{j}=j{\upharpoonright}\kappa_{0}^{+N}\in U|\eta\subseteq U|\delta, so j¯\bar{j} is available as a parameter when making definitions over U||βU||\beta for some βδ\beta\geq\delta, and j¯\bar{j} is also in the generic extension (P||β)[N|δ](P||\beta)[N|\delta].

Now given P||βP||\beta for all β<α\beta<\alpha, α\alpha a limit, (all P||βP||\beta sound), we get a premouse P|αP|\alpha satisfying “δ\delta is Woodin”. Suppose U||αU||\alpha is active with FF. We need to see that we get a premouse P||αP||\alpha, fine structurally equivalent with U||αU||\alpha (modulo the generic). We need to in particular see that there is a unique premouse P||αP||\alpha with the right properties. If crit(FU||α)=κ0{\rm crit}(F^{U||\alpha})=\kappa_{0}, existence is not immediately clear, and will be verified in Lemma 5.1.1. Uniqueness and the manner in which FP||αF^{P||\alpha} is determined, requires a short argument. We have P|αP|\alpha and can compute FP||αrg(j¯)F^{P||\alpha}{\upharpoonright}\mathrm{rg}(\bar{j}), and rg(j¯)\mathrm{rg}(\bar{j}) is cofinal in μ+(P|α)\mu^{+(P|\alpha)} (where μ=κ0Mα0𝒯=crit(FP||α)\mu=\kappa_{0}^{M^{\mathcal{T}}_{\alpha_{0}}}={\rm crit}(F^{P||\alpha})). By Fact 5.1.1 this (very locally) determines FP||αF^{P||\alpha}. For the case that crit(FU||α)>δ{\rm crit}(F^{U||\alpha})>\delta, one makes the usual P-construction observations, although the generic equivalence here involves the parameter j¯\bar{j}.

Overall we maintain level by level that

P|β is Δ1U|β({P|δ,j¯}),P|\beta\text{ is }\Delta_{1}^{U|\beta}(\{P|\delta,\bar{j}\}),
P||β is Δ1U||β({P|δ,j¯}),P||\beta\text{ is }\Delta_{1}^{U||\beta}(\{P|\delta,\bar{j}\}),

uniformly in β>δ\beta>\delta (and recalling P|δ=M(𝒯)P|\delta=M(\mathcal{T})), and also that

U|β=δ(P|β)[U|δ] and U|β is Δ1(P|β)[U|δ]({U|δ,j¯}),U|\beta=^{*}_{\delta}(P|\beta)[U|\delta]\text{ and }U|\beta\text{ is }\Delta_{1}^{(P|\beta)[U|\delta]}(\{U|\delta,\bar{j}\}),
U||β=δ(P||β)[U|δ] and U||β is Δ1(P||β)[U|δ]({U|δ,j¯}),U||\beta=^{*}_{\delta}(P||\beta)[U|\delta]\text{ and }U||\beta\text{ is }\Delta_{1}^{(P||\beta)[U|\delta]}(\{U|\delta,\bar{j}\}),

uniformly in β\beta, where (P|β)[U|δ](P|\beta)[U|\delta] is a generic extension, which for definability purposes has has P|βP|\beta available as a predicate (and similarly for P||βP||\beta), and where ==^{*} means that U|βU|\beta is the premouse which extends U|δU|\delta, followed by the small forcing extension of extenders EE in 𝔼P|β\mathbb{E}^{P|\beta} or 𝔼+P||β\mathbb{E}_{+}^{P||\beta} when crit(E)>δ{\rm crit}(E)>\delta, and the extender determined by Ej¯E\circ\bar{j} otherwise, and also that the usual fine structural correspondence holds between the two sides (employing an extender algebra name for j¯\bar{j}).

Lemma 5.4.

Let 𝒯\mathcal{T} be P-illustrative on MM, via ΣM\Sigma_{M}, and b=ΣM(𝒯)b=\Sigma_{M}(\mathcal{T}), and let UU be as in Definition 5.3. If 𝒯\mathcal{T} is short let Q=Q(𝒯,b)Q=Q(\mathcal{T},b), and otherwise let Q=Mb𝒯Q=M^{\mathcal{T}}_{b}. Then 𝒫U(M(𝒯))=Q\mathscr{P}^{U}(M(\mathcal{T}))=Q.

Proof.

Let δ=δ(𝒯)\delta=\delta(\mathcal{T}). Working in VV, we “compare the phalanx Φ(𝒯,Q)\Phi(\mathcal{T},Q) with the phalanx ((M,δ),U)((M,\delta),U), modulo the generic at δ\delta”. That is, in the “comparison”, we only use extenders indexed above δ\delta, with least disagreements determined by the restrictions of extenders to the ordinals, and after composing extenders EE overlapping δ\delta on the Φ(𝒯,Q)\Phi(\mathcal{T},Q) side with j¯\bar{j} (notation as above). That is, we define normal padded trees 𝒰\mathcal{U} on Φ(𝒯,Q)\Phi(\mathcal{T},Q) and 𝒱\mathcal{V} on ((M,δ),U)((M,\delta),U), with both corresponding to trees on MM via ΣM\Sigma_{M},484848For ((M,δ),U)((M,\delta),U), the notation means that the exchange ordinal associated to MM is δ\delta, so in fact, since δ<lh(E0𝒱)\delta<{\rm lh}(E^{\mathcal{V}}_{0}), and δ\delta is a strong κ0\kappa_{0}-cutpoint of UU, if crit(Eα𝒱)<δ{\rm crit}(E^{\mathcal{V}}_{\alpha})<\delta then crit(Eα𝒱)=κ0{\rm crit}(E^{\mathcal{V}}_{\alpha})=\kappa_{0}. If U=MU=M then we 𝒱\mathcal{V} is directly equivalent to a tree on MM via ΣM\Sigma_{M}. If U=Ult(M,E)U=\mathrm{Ult}(M,E) where E𝔼ME\in\mathbb{E}^{M} and crit(E)=κ1{\rm crit}(E)=\kappa_{1}, then a simple instance of normalization produces the tree 𝒱\mathcal{V}^{\prime} on MM, via ΣM\Sigma_{M}, corresponding to 𝒱\mathcal{V}: If 𝒱β\mathcal{V}{\upharpoonright}\beta is above δ\delta but based on U|λ+U=U|κ1+UU|\lambda^{+U}=U|\kappa_{1}^{+U}, then 𝒱β\mathcal{V}^{\prime}{\upharpoonright}\beta is the tree on MM, via ΣM\Sigma_{M}, which uses the same extenders and has the same tree structure as does 𝒱β\mathcal{V}{\upharpoonright}\beta. Note that because η,δ\eta,\delta are strong κ0\kappa_{0}-cutpoints of UU, and by the Mitchell-Steel ISC, EE’s natural length ν(E)η\nu(E)\leq\eta, so ρ1M||lh(E)η\rho_{1}^{M||{\rm lh}(E)}\leq\eta, so for each α+1<β\alpha+1<\beta such that pred𝒱(α+1)=0\mathrm{pred}^{\mathcal{V}}(\alpha+1)=0 and α+1𝒟𝒰\alpha+1\notin\mathscr{D}^{\mathcal{U}}, we have that 𝒱\mathcal{V}^{\prime} drops in model and degree at α+1\alpha+1 to (Mα+1𝒱,degα+1𝒱)=(M||lh(E),0)(M^{*\mathcal{V}^{\prime}}_{\alpha+1},\deg^{\mathcal{V}^{\prime}}_{\alpha+1})=(M||{\rm lh}(E),0); 𝒱β\mathcal{V}{\upharpoonright}\beta and 𝒱β\mathcal{V}^{\prime}{\upharpoonright}\beta otherwise agree in drop and degree structure, and so their models and embeddings agree in a simple manner. If 𝒱β\mathcal{V}{\upharpoonright}\beta is as above but [0,β]𝒱[0,\beta]_{\mathcal{V}} does not drop and κ1+Mβ𝒱<lh(Eβ𝒰)\kappa_{1}^{+M^{\mathcal{V}}_{\beta}}<{\rm lh}(E^{\mathcal{U}}_{\beta}), then 𝒱\mathcal{V}^{\prime} uses first F(Mβ𝒱)F(M^{\mathcal{V}^{\prime}}_{\beta}) as an extra extender, and note then that Mβ𝒱=Mβ+1𝒱M^{\mathcal{V}}_{\beta}=M^{\mathcal{V}^{\prime}}_{\beta+1}. Since κ1Mβ𝒱\kappa_{1}^{M^{\mathcal{V}}_{\beta}} is a κ0\kappa_{0}-cutpoint of Mβ𝒱M^{\mathcal{V}}_{\beta}, if 𝒱[β,γ)\mathcal{V}{\upharpoonright}[\beta,\gamma) is above κ1Mβ𝒱\kappa_{1}^{M^{\mathcal{V}}_{\beta}} then 𝒱[β,γ)\mathcal{V}{\upharpoonright}[\beta,\gamma) is directly equivalent to 𝒱[β+1,γ)\mathcal{V}^{\prime}{\upharpoonright}[\beta+1,\gamma^{\prime}) where γ=γ+1\gamma^{\prime}=\gamma+1 or γ=γ\gamma=\gamma in the obvious manner. Finally if ξ\xi is least such that crit(Eξ𝒱)=κ0{\rm crit}(E^{\mathcal{V}}_{\xi})=\kappa_{0} (either with ξ<β\xi<\beta or β<ξ\beta<\xi as above) then 𝒱,𝒱\mathcal{V},\mathcal{V}^{\prime} are again directly equivalent thereafter. and such that, given (𝒰,𝒱)(α+1)(\mathcal{U},\mathcal{V}){\upharpoonright}(\alpha+1), letting γ>δ\gamma>\delta be least such that E=FMα𝒰||γE=F^{M^{\mathcal{U}}_{\alpha}||\gamma}\neq\emptyset or F=FMα𝒱||γF=F^{M^{\mathcal{V}}_{\alpha}||\gamma}\neq\emptyset and either:

  1. crit(E)=μ{\rm crit}(E)=\mu and Ejκ0+MFκ0+ME\circ j{\upharpoonright}\kappa_{0}^{+M}\neq F{\upharpoonright}\kappa_{0}^{+M}, or

  2. crit(E)>μ{\rm crit}(E)>\mu (so crit(E)>δ{\rm crit}(E)>\delta) and EORFORE{\upharpoonright}\mathrm{OR}\neq F{\upharpoonright}\mathrm{OR}, or

  3. E=FE=\emptyset\neq F,

then Eα𝒰=EE^{\mathcal{U}}_{\alpha}=E and Eα𝒱=FE^{\mathcal{V}}_{\alpha}=F (and the comparison terminates if there is no such γ>δ\gamma>\delta). We need to see that this comparison is trivial, i.e. no extenders are used. So suppose otherwise.

Claim 1.

The comparison terminates in set length.

Proof.

Note that if Eβ𝒰E^{\mathcal{U}}_{\beta} overlaps δ\delta then Mβ+1𝒰M^{\mathcal{U}}_{\beta+1} is proper class and

κ0Mβ+1𝒰=λ(Eβ𝒰)\kappa_{0}^{M^{\mathcal{U}}_{\beta+1}}=\lambda(E^{\mathcal{U}}_{\beta})

is a cutpoint of Mβ+1𝒰M^{\mathcal{U}}_{\beta+1}, so 𝒰[β+1,)\mathcal{U}{\upharpoonright}[\beta+1,\infty) is above λ(Eβ𝒰)\lambda(E^{\mathcal{U}}_{\beta}). Therefore there is at most one such β\beta. Likewise for 𝒱\mathcal{V}. But the comparison after these overlaps becomes standard comparison modulo the small generic at δ\delta, so the usual argument then shows that the comparison terminates. ∎

So say we get lh(𝒰,𝒱)=α+1{\rm lh}(\mathcal{U},\mathcal{V})=\alpha+1.

Claim 2.

At least one of the trees 𝒰,𝒱\mathcal{U},\mathcal{V} uses an extender overlapping δ\delta.

Proof.

Suppose otherwise. Suppose OR(Mα𝒰)=OR(Mα𝒱)\mathrm{OR}(M^{\mathcal{U}}_{\alpha})=\mathrm{OR}(M^{\mathcal{V}}_{\alpha}); the other case is similar. Then the level-by-level translation process described in 5.1.1 works between Mα𝒰M^{\mathcal{U}}_{\alpha} and Mα𝒱M^{\mathcal{V}}_{\alpha}, and we get fine structural correspondence above δ\delta. Suppose that OR(Mα𝒰)<OR\mathrm{OR}(M^{\mathcal{U}}_{\alpha})<\mathrm{OR}. Let AA be either the core of Mα𝒰M^{\mathcal{U}}_{\alpha} if ρω(Mα𝒰)>δ\rho_{\omega}(M^{\mathcal{U}}_{\alpha})>\delta, and otherwise the δ\delta-core of Mα𝒰M^{\mathcal{U}}_{\alpha}. Let BB be likewise from Mα𝒱M^{\mathcal{V}}_{\alpha}. Let π,σ\pi,\sigma be the core maps respectively. Then by the fine structural correspondence and forcing calculations,

rg(π)OR=rg(σ)OR,\mathrm{rg}(\pi)\cap\mathrm{OR}=\mathrm{rg}(\sigma)\cap\mathrm{OR},

so ORA=ORB\mathrm{OR}^{A}=\mathrm{OR}^{B}. But also, the core maps preserve the fact that the level-by-level translation works, so B=δA[M(𝒯)]B=^{*}_{\delta}A[M(\mathcal{T})] etc (with fine structural agreement up to the relevant level). But we had AMγ𝒰A\trianglelefteq M^{\mathcal{U}}_{\gamma} and BMγ𝒱B\trianglelefteq M^{\mathcal{V}}_{\gamma} for some γ\gamma, and either Eγ𝒰E^{\mathcal{U}}_{\gamma} or Eγ𝒱E^{\mathcal{V}}_{\gamma} came from 𝔼+A\mathbb{E}_{+}^{A} or 𝔼+B\mathbb{E}_{+}^{B} respectively, a contradiction. So OR(Mα𝒰)=OR\mathrm{OR}(M^{\mathcal{U}}_{\alpha})=\mathrm{OR}, so there is no dropping on main branches, and 𝒯\mathcal{T} is maximal. But now we can just replace “δ\delta-core” with the hull of δ\delta\cup\mathscr{I}, where \mathscr{I} is the class of indiscernibles of Mα𝒰M^{\mathcal{U}}_{\alpha}, or equivalently, Mα𝒱M^{\mathcal{V}}_{\alpha}, and run the analogous argument, using that Q,UQ,U are δ\delta-sound (if UMU\neq M, this is because η\eta is a strong κ0\kappa_{0}-cutpoint of UU, and hence if U=Ult(M,E)U=\mathrm{Ult}(M,E) where E𝔼ME\in\mathbb{E}^{M} with crit(E)=κ1{\rm crit}(E)=\kappa_{1}, then ν(E)η\nu(E)\leq\eta, where ν(E)\nu(E) is the natural length of EE). ∎

Now let β\beta be least such that Eβ𝒰E^{\mathcal{U}}_{\beta} or Eβ𝒱E^{\mathcal{V}}_{\beta} overlaps δ\delta. The following claim is the most central issue:

Claim 3.

Not both of Eβ𝒰,Eβ𝒱E^{\mathcal{U}}_{\beta},E^{\mathcal{V}}_{\beta} overlap δ\delta.

Proof.

Suppose F=Eβ𝒱F=E^{\mathcal{V}}_{\beta} overlaps δ\delta. Then Fκ0+MF{\upharpoonright}\kappa_{0}^{+M} is a restriction of the iteration map

Ult(M,F).\mathcal{M}_{\infty}\to\mathcal{M}_{\infty}^{\mathrm{Ult}(M,F)}.

Similarly, supposing E=Eβ𝒰E=E^{\mathcal{U}}_{\beta} overlaps δ\delta, EORE{\upharpoonright}\mathrm{OR} is a restriction of the iteration map

Mα0𝒯Ult(Mα0𝒯,E),\mathcal{M}_{\infty}^{M^{\mathcal{T}}_{\alpha_{0}}}\to\mathcal{M}_{\infty}^{\mathrm{Ult}(M^{\mathcal{T}}_{\alpha_{0}},E)},

so Ejκ0+ME\circ j{\upharpoonright}\kappa_{0}^{+M} is the restriction of the iteration map

Ult(Mα0𝒯,E).\mathcal{M}_{\infty}\to\mathcal{M}_{\infty}^{\mathrm{Ult}(M^{\mathcal{T}}_{\alpha_{0}},E)}.

So it suffices to see that

Ult(Mα0𝒯,E)=Ult(M,F),\mathcal{M}_{\infty}^{\mathrm{Ult}(M^{\mathcal{T}}_{\alpha_{0}},E)}=\mathcal{M}_{\infty}^{\mathrm{Ult}(M,F)}, (24)

as then Ejκ0+M=Fκ0+ME\circ j{\upharpoonright}\kappa_{0}^{+M}=F{\upharpoonright}\kappa_{0}^{+M}, contradicting the disagreement of extenders. But (24) holds because

(Mβ𝒰|lh(E))[M|δ]=δMβ𝒱|lh(F),(M^{\mathcal{U}}_{\beta}|{\rm lh}(E))[M|\delta]=^{*}_{\delta}M^{\mathcal{V}}_{\beta}|{\rm lh}(F),

since δ<λ(E)=λ(F)\delta<\lambda(E)=\lambda(F) and E,FE,F constitute the least disagreement. ∎

Now assume for notational simplicity that Eβ𝒰E^{\mathcal{U}}_{\beta} overlaps δ\delta; the other case is very similar. Note that:

  1. [0,β+1]𝒰[0,\beta+1]_{\mathcal{U}} does not drop in model, and

  2. 𝒰[β+1,lh(𝒰))\mathcal{U}{\upharpoonright}[\beta+1,{\rm lh}(\mathcal{U})) is above λ(Eβ𝒰)\lambda(E^{\mathcal{U}}_{\beta}).

As in the proof of Claim 2 we get:

Claim 4.

Neither (𝒯,b)^𝒰(\mathcal{T},b)\ \widehat{\ }\ \mathcal{U} nor 𝒱\mathcal{V} drops on its main branch.

It easily follows that there is γ>β\gamma>\beta such that Eγ𝒱E^{\mathcal{V}}_{\gamma} overlaps δ\delta. We have β+1b𝒰\beta+1\in b^{\mathcal{U}} and γ+1b𝒱\gamma+1\in b^{\mathcal{V}}. Let =Mα𝒰=Mα𝒱\mathscr{I}=\mathscr{I}^{M^{\mathcal{U}}_{\alpha}}=\mathscr{I}^{M^{\mathcal{V}}_{\alpha}}. Let λ=λ(Eβ𝒰)\lambda=\lambda(E^{\mathcal{U}}_{\beta}), so

κ0+M<δ<λ<λ(Eγ𝒱),\kappa_{0}^{+M}<\delta<\lambda<\lambda(E^{\mathcal{V}}_{\gamma}),

so Fλ=Eγ𝒱λF_{\lambda}=E^{\mathcal{V}}_{\gamma}{\upharpoonright}\lambda is a non-whole segment of Eγ𝒱E^{\mathcal{V}}_{\gamma}, by the ISC and smallness of MM. Let

H𝒰=cHullMα𝒰(λ) and H𝒱=cHullMα𝒱(λ),H^{\mathcal{U}}=\mathrm{cHull}^{M^{\mathcal{U}}_{\alpha}}(\lambda\cup\mathscr{I})\text{ and }H^{\mathcal{V}}=\mathrm{cHull}^{M^{\mathcal{V}}_{\alpha}}(\lambda\cup\mathscr{I}),

and π𝒰,π𝒱\pi^{\mathcal{U}},\pi^{\mathcal{V}} the uncollapses. Then κ0H𝒰=λ\kappa_{0}^{H^{\mathcal{U}}}=\lambda because H𝒰=Mβ+1𝒰H^{\mathcal{U}}=M^{\mathcal{U}}_{\beta+1} (and note iβ+1,α𝒰=π𝒰i^{\mathcal{U}}_{\beta+1,\alpha}=\pi^{\mathcal{U}}). Similarly, H𝒱=Ult(M,Fλ)H^{\mathcal{V}}=\mathrm{Ult}(M,F_{\lambda}), but λ<iFλM(κ0)=κ0H𝒱\lambda<i^{M}_{F_{\lambda}}(\kappa_{0})=\kappa_{0}^{H^{\mathcal{V}}} since FλF_{\lambda} is not whole. But since δ<λ\delta<\lambda, we also have π𝒰OR=π𝒱OR\pi^{\mathcal{U}}{\upharpoonright}\mathrm{OR}=\pi^{\mathcal{V}}{\upharpoonright}\mathrm{OR}, so π𝒱(λ)=π𝒰(λ)=κ0Mα𝒰=κ0Mα𝒱\pi^{\mathcal{V}}(\lambda)=\pi^{\mathcal{U}}(\lambda)=\kappa_{0}^{M^{\mathcal{U}}_{\alpha}}=\kappa_{0}^{M^{\mathcal{V}}_{\alpha}}, so λ=κ0H𝒱\lambda=\kappa_{0}^{H^{\mathcal{V}}}, contradiction. ∎

We now want to consider similar P-constructions internal to 𝒱1\mathscr{V}_{1}, and also iterates of 𝒱1\mathscr{V}_{1} and their generic extensions.

Definition 5.5.

Let 𝒱\mathscr{V} be a non-dropping Σ𝒱1\Sigma_{\mathscr{V}_{1}}-iterate of 𝒱1\mathscr{V}_{1}. Let 𝒯\mathcal{T} be an iteration tree on 𝒱\mathscr{V}. We say that 𝒯\mathcal{T} is dl-somewhat-relevant (dsr) iff there are 𝒯0,𝒱,𝒯1\mathcal{T}_{0},\mathscr{V}^{\prime},\mathcal{T}_{1} such that:

  1. 1.

    𝒯\mathcal{T} is short-normal,

  2. 2.

    𝒯\mathcal{T} has lower and upper components 𝒯0,𝒯1\mathcal{T}_{0},\mathcal{T}_{1} respectively, 𝒯0\mathcal{T}_{0} has successor length, b𝒯0b^{\mathcal{T}_{0}} does not drop, 𝒱=M𝒯0\mathscr{V}^{\prime}=M^{\mathcal{T}_{0}}_{\infty}, and 𝒯1\mathcal{T}_{1} (on 𝒱\mathscr{V}^{\prime}) is above γ𝒱\gamma^{\mathscr{V}^{\prime}},

  3. 3.

    for each β+1<lh(𝒯1)\beta+1<{\rm lh}(\mathcal{T}_{1}), δ0𝒱\delta_{0}^{\mathscr{V}^{\prime}} is the unique Woodin of Mβ𝒯1|lh(Eβ𝒯1)M^{\mathcal{T}_{1}}_{\beta}|{\rm lh}(E^{\mathcal{T}_{1}}_{\beta}).

Note that every dl-somewhat-relevant tree on 𝒱\mathscr{V} is based on 𝒱|δ1𝒱\mathscr{V}|\delta_{1}^{\mathscr{V}}.

Easily:

Lemma 5.5.

Let 𝒱\mathscr{V} be a non-dropping Σ𝒱1\Sigma_{\mathscr{V}_{1}}-iterate of 𝒱1\mathscr{V}_{1}. Let 𝒯\mathcal{T} on 𝒱\mathscr{V} be via Σ𝒱\Sigma_{\mathscr{V}} and δ1\delta_{1}-maximal. Then 𝒯\mathcal{T} is dsr.

Definition 5.6.

For a non-dropping Σ𝒱1\Sigma_{\mathscr{V}_{1}}-iterate 𝒱\mathscr{V} of 𝒱1\mathscr{V}_{1}, write Σ𝒱,sh\Sigma_{\mathscr{V},\mathrm{sh}} for the restriction of Σ𝒱\Sigma_{\mathscr{V}} to δ1\delta_{1}-short trees, and Σ𝒱,shdsr\Sigma^{\mathrm{dsr}}_{\mathscr{V},\mathrm{sh}} for the restriction of Σ𝒱,sh\Sigma_{\mathscr{V},\mathrm{sh}} to dsr trees.

Definition 5.7.

Let 𝒱\mathscr{V} be a non-dropping Σ𝒱1\Sigma_{\mathscr{V}_{1}}-iterate of 𝒱1\mathscr{V}_{1}. Let 𝒯\mathcal{T} be an iteration tree on 𝒱\mathscr{V}. Let 𝒱\mathbb{P}\in\mathscr{V} and gg be (𝒱,)(\mathscr{V},\mathbb{P})-generic. Say 𝒯\mathcal{T} is P-suitable for 𝒱[g]\mathscr{V}[g] iff there are 𝒯0,𝒱,𝒯1,E1,U,E0,η,δ,λ\mathcal{T}_{0},\mathscr{V}^{\prime},\mathcal{T}_{1},E_{1},U,E_{0},\eta,\delta,\lambda such that:

  1. (a)

    gg is (𝒱,)(\mathscr{V},\mathbb{P})-generic and 𝒯𝒱[g]\mathcal{T}\in\mathscr{V}[g],

  2. (b)

    𝒯\mathcal{T} is short-normal with lower and upper components 𝒯0,𝒯1\mathcal{T}_{0},\mathcal{T}_{1} respectively, 𝒱=M𝒯0\mathcal{V}^{\prime}=M^{\mathcal{T}_{0}}_{\infty} exists and b𝒯0b^{\mathcal{T}_{0}} is non-dropping, and 𝒯1\mathcal{T}_{1} is based on 𝒱|δ1𝒱\mathscr{V}^{\prime}|\delta_{1}^{\mathscr{V}^{\prime}},

  3. (c)

    𝒯\mathcal{T} is via Σ𝒱\Sigma_{\mathscr{V}},

  4. (d)

    either

    1. (i)

      E1=E_{1}=\emptyset and U=𝒱U=\mathscr{V}, or

    2. (ii)

      E1𝔼𝒱E_{1}\in\mathbb{E}^{\mathscr{V}} is short and 𝒱\mathscr{V}-total, crit(E1)=κ1𝒱{\rm crit}(E_{1})=\kappa_{1}^{\mathscr{V}} and U=Ult(𝒱,E1)U=\mathrm{Ult}(\mathscr{V},E_{1}),

  5. (e)

    U|κ1U\mathbb{P}\in U|\kappa_{1}^{U} and 𝒯(U|κ1U)[g]\mathcal{T}^{\prime}\in(U|\kappa_{1}^{U})[g] where 𝒯\mathcal{T}^{\prime} on 𝒱|δ1𝒱\mathscr{V}|\delta_{1}^{\mathscr{V}} is equivalent to 𝒯\mathcal{T},

  6. (f)

    either

    1. (i)

      E0=E_{0}=\emptyset and 𝒯0\mathcal{T}_{0} is trivial (so 𝒱=𝒱\mathscr{V}^{\prime}=\mathscr{V}), or

    2. (ii)

      E0𝔼𝒱E_{0}\in\mathbb{E}^{\mathscr{V}} is long, γ𝒱<lh(E0)\gamma^{\mathscr{V}}<{\rm lh}(E_{0}) and the lower component 𝒯0\mathcal{T}_{0} of 𝒯\mathcal{T} is just the (successor length) short-normal tree corresponding to E0E_{0} (so 𝒱=Ult(𝒱,E0)\mathscr{V}^{\prime}=\mathrm{Ult}(\mathscr{V}_{,}E_{0})),

  7. (g)

    δ0𝒱<η<κ1U\delta_{0}^{\mathscr{V}^{\prime}}<\eta<\kappa_{1}^{U} and η\eta is a strong δ0𝒱\delta_{0}^{\mathscr{V}}-cutpoint of UU, η\eta is a UU-cardinal, U|η\mathbb{P}\in U|\eta, and if E1E_{1}\neq\emptyset then κ1𝒱<η\kappa_{1}^{\mathscr{V}}<\eta,

  8. (h)

    𝒯\mathcal{T} has limit length, η<δ=δ(𝒯)<κ1U\eta<\delta=\delta(\mathcal{T})<\kappa_{1}^{U}, η\eta is the largest cardinal of U|δU|\delta, 𝒯\mathcal{T} is definable from parameters over (U|δ)[g](U|\delta)[g], and (U|δ,g)(U|\delta,g) is 𝔹δδ0𝒱M(𝒯)\mathbb{B}_{\delta\delta_{0}^{\mathscr{V}^{\prime}}}^{M(\mathcal{T})}-generic over M(𝒯)M(\mathcal{T}).

Say 𝒯\mathcal{T} is dl-relevant (for 𝒱\mathscr{V}) iff 𝒯𝒱\mathcal{T}\in\mathscr{V} is δ1\delta_{1}-maximal (hence dsr) P-suitable, as witnessed by E1=E_{1}=\emptyset.

Definition 5.8.

Let 𝒱\mathscr{V} be a non-dropping Σ𝒱1\Sigma_{\mathscr{V}_{1}}-iterate of 𝒱1\mathscr{V}_{1}. Let gg be set-generic over 𝒱\mathscr{V}. Let 𝒯𝒱[g]\mathcal{T}\in\mathscr{V}[g] be P-suitable for 𝒱[g]\mathscr{V}[g], as witnessed by U,𝒯0U,\mathcal{T}_{0}. Then 𝒫U,g(M(𝒯))\mathscr{P}^{U,g}(M(\mathcal{T})) denotes the P-construction PP of U[g]U[g] over M(𝒯)M(\mathcal{T}), using 𝔼U\mathbb{E}^{U}, computed analogously to that in Definition 5.4; so when F=FU||αF=F^{U||\alpha}\neq\emptyset and FF is long, then E=FP||αE=F^{P||\alpha} is determined by demanding Ej¯FE\circ\bar{j}\subseteq F, where j¯=i0𝒯0δ0𝒱\bar{j}=i^{\mathcal{T}_{0}}_{0\infty}{\upharpoonright}\delta_{0}^{\mathscr{V}}.

It is now straightforward to deduce a version of Lemma 5.1.1 for dsr P-suitable trees 𝒯𝒱1\mathcal{T}\in\mathscr{V}_{1} on 𝒱1\mathscr{V}_{1}, by translating them to trees on MM and applying 5.1.1. Combined with the minimal inflation method used for MM, this allows us to compute the δ1\delta_{1}-short tree strategy for 𝒱1\mathscr{V}_{1} inside 𝒱1\mathscr{V}_{1}, and also the models for forming the second direct limit system. However, before we proceed to this, we want to also consider the analogous issues for iterates 𝒱\mathscr{V} of 𝒱1\mathscr{V}_{1} (and generic extensions 𝒱[g]\mathscr{V}[g] thereof). The argument given above does not immediately adapt to such iterates 𝒱\mathscr{V} in general, because (i) 𝒱\mathscr{V} need not be as sound as 𝒱1\mathscr{V}_{1}, and (ii) 𝒱\mathscr{V} need not correspond appropriately to an iterate of MM. To deal with these possibilities, we will adjust somewhat the conclusion and argument for Lemma 5.1.1, in Lemma 5.1.2 below. Also note that it is not immediate that P-suitability and dl-relevance are first-order over 𝒱\mathscr{V} (or 𝒱1\mathscr{V}_{1}), because of the demand that 𝒯\mathcal{T} be via Σ𝒱\Sigma_{\mathscr{V}}. We will address this issue also, in a manner similar to that for MM.

5.1.2 DSR trees on iterates of 𝒱1\mathscr{V}_{1}

To deal with issue (ii) mentioned above, it turns out we can replace the use of MM (or some iterate thereof) with an MswswM_{\mathrm{swsw}}-like generic extension NN of 𝒱\mathscr{V} (together with such an extension of a related iterate 𝒱1\mathscr{V}_{1}; see below). It inherits iterability (above κ0N\kappa_{0}^{N}) from the corresponding iterate of 𝒱1\mathscr{V}_{1}:

Lemma 5.8.

Let 𝒱\mathscr{V} be a non-dropping Σ𝒱1\Sigma_{\mathscr{V}_{1}}-iterate of 𝒱1\mathscr{V}_{1}. Let gg be 𝕃𝒱\mathbb{L}^{\mathscr{V}}-generic and NN an MswswM_{\mathrm{swsw}}-like premouse such that N=𝒱[g]N=^{*}\mathscr{V}[g] and 𝒱=𝒱1N\mathscr{V}=\mathscr{V}_{1}^{N}. Let =𝒱\mathscr{I}=\mathscr{I}^{\mathscr{V}}. Then:

  1. 1.

    NN is (0,OR)(0,\mathrm{OR})-iterable with respect to trees 𝒯\mathcal{T} with lh(E0𝒯)>κ0N{\rm lh}(E^{\mathcal{T}}_{0})>\kappa_{0}^{N}.

  2. 2.

    \mathscr{I} is the class N\mathscr{I}^{N} of Silver indiscernibles for NN (with respect to the generator set κ1𝒱=κ1N\kappa_{1}^{\mathscr{V}}=\kappa_{1}^{N}). If 𝒱\mathscr{V} is η\eta-sound where δ0𝒱η\delta_{0}^{\mathscr{V}}\leq\eta then NN is η\eta-sound. If 𝒱\mathscr{V} is δ0𝒱\delta_{0}^{\mathscr{V}}-sound then NN is κ0N\kappa_{0}^{N}-sound.

Proof.

Part 1: Let PNP\triangleleft N with ρωP=κ0N\rho_{\omega}^{P}=\kappa_{0}^{N}. Then PP is (0,OR)(0,\mathrm{OR})-iterable with respect to trees 𝒯\mathcal{T} with lh(E0𝒯)>κ0N{\rm lh}(E^{\mathcal{T}}_{0})>\kappa_{0}^{N}, because κ0N\kappa_{0}^{N} is a cutpoint of PP, and letting E𝔼𝒱E\in\mathbb{E}^{\mathscr{V}} be long, EE extends to E+𝔼NE^{+}\in\mathbb{E}^{N}, and E+(P)E^{+}(P) is above-λ(E)\lambda(E)-(0,OR)(0,\mathrm{OR})-iterable, since iterating E+(P)E^{+}(P) above λ(E)\lambda(E) is equivalent to iterating 𝒱||OR(E+(P))\mathscr{V}||\mathrm{OR}(E^{+}(P)) above λ(E)\lambda(E).

So we may assume that κ0+N=δ0𝒱<lh(E0𝒯)\kappa_{0}^{+N}=\delta_{0}^{\mathscr{V}}<{\rm lh}(E^{\mathcal{T}}_{0}), and so γ𝒱<lh(E0𝒯)\gamma^{\mathscr{V}}<{\rm lh}(E^{\mathcal{T}}_{0}). Consider translatable trees 𝒯\mathcal{T} on NN. We get an iteration strategy for such trees induced by Σ𝒱\Sigma_{\mathscr{V}}, and the resulting iterates of N,𝒱N,\mathscr{V} are related according to Lemma 4.12.1. Now suppose 𝒯(α+1)\mathcal{T}{\upharpoonright}(\alpha+1) is translatable, and let 𝒰\mathcal{U} on 𝒱\mathscr{V} be its translation to 𝒱\mathscr{V}, but 𝒯(α+2)\mathcal{T}{\upharpoonright}(\alpha+2) is not translatable. Then α\alpha is a limit ordinal and a limit of stages when 𝒰\mathcal{U} uses a long extender, and lh(Eα𝒯)<δ0Mα𝒰{\rm lh}(E^{\mathcal{T}}_{\alpha})<\delta_{0}^{M^{\mathcal{U}}_{\alpha}}. But then 𝒯[α,)\mathcal{T}{\upharpoonright}[\alpha,\infty) is just a tree on some PMα𝒯P\triangleleft M^{\mathcal{T}}_{\alpha} where ρωP=κ0Mα𝒯\rho_{\omega}^{P}=\kappa_{0}^{M^{\mathcal{T}}_{\alpha}}, and κ0Mα𝒯\kappa_{0}^{M^{\mathcal{T}}_{\alpha}} is a cutpoint of PP, and this PP is also iterable above κ0Mα𝒯\kappa_{0}^{M^{\mathcal{T}}_{\alpha}}, like in the previous paragraph.

Part 2: By genericity, \mathscr{I} form indiscernibles for NN. Note that 𝒱\mathscr{V} is κ1𝒱\kappa_{1}^{\mathscr{V}}-sound. Let η[δ0𝒱,κ1𝒱]\eta\in[\delta_{0}^{\mathscr{V}},\kappa_{1}^{\mathscr{V}}] be least such that 𝒱\mathscr{V} is η\eta-sound. Note that N=Hull1N(η)N=\mathrm{Hull}^{N}_{1}(\mathscr{I}\cup\eta). So N=\mathscr{I}^{N}=\mathscr{I}. Finally suppose η=δ0𝒱\eta=\delta_{0}^{\mathscr{V}}, so N=Hull1N(κ0+N)N=\mathrm{Hull}_{1}^{N}(\kappa_{0}^{+N}\cup\mathscr{I}). But also Hull1𝒱()\mathrm{Hull}_{1}^{\mathscr{V}}(\mathscr{I}) is cofinal in δ0𝒱\delta_{0}^{\mathscr{V}} and 𝒱\mathscr{V} is definable over NN, so Hull1N(κ0N)\mathrm{Hull}_{1}^{N}(\kappa_{0}^{N}\cup\mathscr{I}) is cofinal in κ0+N\kappa_{0}^{+N} and transitive below κ0+N\kappa_{0}^{+N}, hence contains all of κ0+N\kappa_{0}^{+N}, and hence all of NN. ∎

Definition 5.9.

Under the hypotheses of Lemma 5.1.2, let ΦN𝒱\Phi_{N\supseteq\mathscr{V}} be the above-κ0N\kappa_{0}^{N}-strategy for NN induced by Σ𝒱\Sigma_{\mathscr{V}} as in the proof of the lemma. (Note that the components of this strategy which do not translate to a tree on 𝒱\mathscr{V}, i.e. on one of the projecting structures PP in the proof, are uniquely determined by PP.)

Lemma 5.9.

Let 𝒱\mathscr{V} be a Σ𝒱1\Sigma_{\mathscr{V}_{1}}-iterate of 𝒱1\mathscr{V}_{1}. Let 𝒮\mathcal{S} be the short-normal tree on 𝒱1\mathscr{V}_{1}, via Σ𝒱1\Sigma_{\mathscr{V}_{1}}, with last model 𝒱\mathscr{V}. Let 𝒱¯=cHull1𝒱(𝒱δ1𝒱)\bar{\mathscr{V}}=\mathrm{cHull}_{1}^{\mathscr{V}}(\mathscr{I}^{\mathscr{V}}\cup\delta_{1}^{\mathscr{V}}) and 𝒱¯¯=cHull1𝒱(𝒱δ0𝒱)\bar{\bar{\mathscr{V}}}=\mathrm{cHull}_{1}^{\mathscr{V}}(\mathscr{I}^{\mathscr{V}}\cup\delta_{0}^{\mathscr{V}}). Then

  1. 1.

    𝒱¯=Mα𝒮\bar{\mathscr{V}}=M^{\mathcal{S}}_{\alpha} for some αb𝒮\alpha\in b^{\mathcal{S}}, and 𝒮[α,)\mathcal{S}{\upharpoonright}[\alpha,\infty) is equivalent to a tree on 𝒱¯\bar{\mathscr{V}} via Σ𝒱¯\Sigma_{\bar{\mathscr{V}}}, 𝒱¯|δ1𝒱¯=𝒱|δ1𝒱\bar{\mathscr{V}}|\delta_{1}^{\bar{\mathscr{V}}}=\mathscr{V}|\delta_{1}^{\mathscr{V}}, and 𝒱¯\bar{\mathscr{V}} is δ1𝒱¯\delta_{1}^{\bar{\mathscr{V}}}-sound. Likewise for 𝒱¯¯\bar{\bar{\mathscr{V}}} and δ0𝒱\delta_{0}^{\mathscr{V}}.

Let 𝒱\mathbb{P}\in\mathscr{V} and gg be (𝒱,)(\mathscr{V},\mathbb{P})-generic. Let 𝒯𝒱[g]\mathcal{T}\in\mathscr{V}[g], on 𝒱\mathscr{V}, be dsr-P-suitable and b=Σ𝒱(𝒯)b=\Sigma_{\mathscr{V}}(\mathcal{T}), and U,η,δU,\eta,\delta as in Definition 5.7. Let 𝒯¯\bar{\mathcal{T}} be the tree on 𝒱¯\bar{\mathscr{V}} equivalent to 𝒯\mathcal{T}. If 𝒯\mathcal{T} is δ1\delta_{1}-short let Q¯=Q=Q(𝒯,b)\bar{Q}=Q=Q(\mathcal{T},b), and otherwise let Q=Mb𝒯Q=M^{\mathcal{T}}_{b} and

Q¯=Mb𝒯¯=cHull1Q(Qδ).\bar{Q}=M^{\bar{\mathcal{T}}}_{b}=\mathrm{cHull}_{1}^{Q}(\mathscr{I}^{Q}\cup\delta).

Let P=𝒫U,g(M(𝒯))P=\mathscr{P}^{U,g}(M(\mathcal{T})). If PP is set-sized let P¯=P\bar{P}=P and otherwise let P¯=Hull1P(Uδ)\bar{P}=\mathrm{Hull}_{1}^{P}(\mathscr{I}^{U}\cup\delta) and π:P¯P\pi:\bar{P}\to P be the uncollapse. Then:

  1. 2.

    P¯=Q¯\bar{P}=\bar{Q}

  2. 3.

    if 𝒯\mathcal{T} is δ1\delta_{1}-maximal then δ=(η+)U\delta=(\eta^{+})^{U} (and P,P¯P,\bar{P} are proper class),

  3. 4.

    if P¯P\bar{P}\neq P then PP is an above-δ\delta, ΣQ¯\Sigma_{\bar{Q}}-iterate of Q¯\bar{Q} (and hence a Σ𝒱1\Sigma_{\mathscr{V}_{1}}-iterate of 𝒱1\mathscr{V}_{1}) and π\pi is the iteration map, so πQ¯=P=𝒱\pi``\mathscr{I}^{\bar{Q}}=\mathscr{I}^{P}=\mathscr{I}^{\mathscr{V}}.

Proof (sketch).

Part 1: This is straightforward and left to the reader.

Part 2: We will prove this by considering a comparison of two phalanxes. It will take a little work to define the phalanxes and describe their relevant properties.

Let 𝒮=𝒮0^𝒮1^𝒮2\mathcal{S}=\mathcal{S}_{0}\ \widehat{\ }\ \mathcal{S}_{1}\ \widehat{\ }\ \mathcal{S}_{2} where 𝒮0\mathcal{S}_{0} is the lower component of 𝒮\mathcal{S}, 𝒮1^𝒮2\mathcal{S}_{1}\ \widehat{\ }\ \mathcal{S}_{2} the upper component, with 𝒮1\mathcal{S}_{1} based on M𝒮0|δ1M𝒮0M^{\mathcal{S}_{0}}_{\infty}|\delta_{1}^{M^{\mathcal{S}_{0}}_{\infty}} and 𝒮2\mathcal{S}_{2} above δ1M𝒮1\delta_{1}^{M^{\mathcal{S}_{1}}_{\infty}}. Then 𝒱¯¯=M𝒮0\bar{\bar{\mathcal{V}}}=M^{\mathcal{S}_{0}}_{\infty} is δ0𝒱¯¯\delta_{0}^{\bar{\bar{\mathscr{V}}}}-sound and 𝒮1\mathcal{S}_{1} is above γ𝒱¯¯\gamma^{\bar{\bar{\mathscr{V}}}}, and is via Σ𝒱¯¯\Sigma_{\bar{\bar{\mathscr{V}}}}, and 𝒱¯=M𝒮1\bar{\mathscr{V}}=M^{\mathcal{S}_{1}}_{\infty} is δ1𝒱¯\delta_{1}^{\bar{\mathscr{V}}}-sound and 𝒮2\mathcal{S}_{2} is via Σ𝒱¯\Sigma_{\bar{\mathscr{V}}}.

Let 𝒱+\mathscr{V}^{+} be an MswswM_{\mathrm{swsw}}-like generic extension of 𝒱\mathscr{V} with 𝒱=𝒱1𝒱+\mathscr{V}=\mathscr{V}_{1}^{\mathscr{V}^{+}}, and such that 𝒱+,g\mathscr{V}^{+},g are mutually 𝒱\mathscr{V}-generic. Let g𝒱+𝕃𝒱g_{\mathscr{V}^{+}}\subseteq\mathbb{L}^{\mathscr{V}} be the generic filter. Since 𝕃𝒱=𝕃𝒱¯¯\mathbb{L}^{\mathscr{V}}=\mathbb{L}^{\bar{\bar{\mathscr{V}}}} is below crit(i0𝒮1^𝒮2){\rm crit}(i^{\mathcal{S}_{1}\ \widehat{\ }\ \mathcal{S}_{2}}_{0\infty}), we have 𝕃𝒱¯¯=𝕃𝒱\mathbb{L}^{\bar{\bar{\mathscr{V}}}}=\mathbb{L}^{\mathscr{V}} and g𝒱+g_{\mathscr{V}^{+}} is also (𝒱¯¯,𝕃𝒱¯¯)(\bar{\bar{\mathscr{V}}},\mathbb{L}^{\bar{\bar{\mathscr{V}}}})-generic, and extends uniquely to an MswswM_{\mathrm{swsw}}-like generic extension 𝒱¯¯+\bar{\bar{\mathscr{V}}}^{+} of 𝒱¯¯\bar{\bar{\mathscr{V}}} with 𝒱¯¯=𝒱1𝒱¯¯+\bar{\bar{\mathscr{V}}}=\mathscr{V}_{1}^{\bar{\bar{\mathscr{V}}}^{+}}; note 𝒱¯¯+|κ0+𝒱¯¯+=𝒱+|κ0+𝒱+\bar{\bar{\mathscr{V}}}^{+}|\kappa_{0}^{+\bar{\bar{\mathscr{V}}}^{+}}=\mathscr{V}^{+}|\kappa_{0}^{+\mathscr{V}^{+}}. Lemma 5.1.2 applies to (𝒱¯¯+,𝒱¯¯)(\bar{\bar{\mathscr{V}}}^{+},\bar{\bar{\mathscr{V}}}), so 𝒮1^𝒮2\mathcal{S}_{1}\ \widehat{\ }\ \mathcal{S}_{2} translates to a tree 𝒮1+^𝒮2+\mathcal{S}_{1}^{+}\ \widehat{\ }\ \mathcal{S}_{2}^{+} on 𝒱¯¯+\bar{\bar{\mathscr{V}}}^{+}, via Φ𝒱¯¯+𝒱¯¯\Phi_{\bar{\bar{\mathscr{V}}}^{+}\supseteq\bar{\bar{\mathscr{V}}}}, and note that 𝒱+=M𝒮1+^𝒮2+\mathscr{V}^{+}=M^{\mathcal{S}_{1}^{+}\ \widehat{\ }\ \mathcal{S}_{2}^{+}}_{\infty}.

Let E0,E1𝔼𝒱E_{0},E_{1}\in\mathbb{E}^{\mathscr{V}} be as in Definition 5.7. Let Ei+𝔼𝒱+E_{i}^{+}\in\mathbb{E}^{\mathscr{V}^{+}} with lh(Ei+)=lh(Ei){\rm lh}(E_{i}^{+})={\rm lh}(E_{i}) (or Ei+==EiE_{i}^{+}=\emptyset=E_{i}). Let U¯¯0+=Ult(𝒱¯¯+,E0+)\bar{\bar{U}}_{0}^{+}=\mathrm{Ult}(\bar{\bar{\mathscr{V}}}^{+},E_{0}^{+}). Since 𝒱¯¯+\bar{\bar{\mathscr{V}}}^{+} is κ0𝒱¯¯+\kappa_{0}^{\bar{\bar{\mathscr{V}}}^{+}}-sound, U¯¯0+\bar{\bar{U}}_{0}^{+} is κ0N¯¯\kappa_{0}^{\bar{\bar{N}}^{\prime}}-sound. (Note U¯¯0+\bar{\bar{U}}_{0}^{+} need not be 𝒱+\subseteq\mathscr{V}^{+}.)

Let U+=Ult(𝒱+,E1+)U^{+}=\mathrm{Ult}(\mathscr{V}^{+},E_{1}^{+}), if E1E_{1}\neq\emptyset, and U+=𝒱+U^{+}=\mathscr{V}^{+} otherwise. Since η\eta is a δ0U\delta_{0}^{U}-strong cutpoint of UU and U|δU|\delta has largest cardinal η\eta, so is δ\delta, and δ\delta is also a κ0U+\kappa_{0}^{U^{+}}-strong cutpoint of U+U^{+}. Let U¯+=Hull1U+(U+δ)\bar{U}^{+}=\mathrm{Hull}_{1}^{U^{+}}(\mathscr{I}^{U^{+}}\cup\delta). Letting π:U¯+U+\pi:\bar{U}^{+}\to U^{+} be the uncollapse, note that δ<crit(π)\delta<{\rm crit}(\pi) (as δ(η+)U+\delta\leq(\eta^{+})^{U^{+}} and δ\delta is a strong κ0U+\kappa_{0}^{U^{+}}-cutpoint), and δ\delta is a κ0U¯+=κ0U+\kappa_{0}^{\bar{U}^{+}}=\kappa_{0}^{U^{+}}-strong cutpoint of U¯+\bar{U}^{+}, and U¯+\bar{U}^{+} is δ\delta-sound. Note that if PP is proper class then δ=δ1P=δ1P¯\delta=\delta_{1}^{P}=\delta_{1}^{\bar{P}}, PP is a ground of U+[g]U^{+}[g] via the extender algebra at δ\delta (to reach U[g]U[g]) followed by some smaller forcing (to reach U+[g]U^{+}[g]), δ=η+U\delta=\eta^{+U}, P=U=U+\mathscr{I}^{P}=\mathscr{I}^{U}=\mathscr{I}^{U^{+}},

ORrg(π)=ORHull1R(Rδ) is independent of R{P,U,U+},\mathrm{OR}\cap\mathrm{rg}(\pi)=\mathrm{OR}\cap\mathrm{Hull}_{1}^{R}(\mathscr{I}^{R}\cup\delta)\text{ is independent of }R\in\{P,U,U^{+}\},

P¯\bar{P} is δ\delta-sound, and letting U¯=cHull1U(Uδ)\bar{U}=\mathrm{cHull}_{1}^{U}(\mathscr{I}^{U}\cup\delta), then P¯U¯[g]U¯+[g]\bar{P}\subseteq\bar{U}[g]\subseteq\bar{U}^{+}[g] are related as are PU[g]U+[g]P\subseteq U[g]\subseteq U^{+}[g], so P¯=𝒫U¯(M(𝒯))\bar{P}=\mathscr{P}^{\bar{U}}(M(\mathcal{T})), etc.

Let Q+=Mb𝒯+||ORQQ^{+}=M^{\mathcal{T}^{+}}_{b}||\mathrm{OR}^{Q} where 𝒯+^b\mathcal{T}^{+}\ \widehat{\ }\ b is the translation of 𝒯^b\mathcal{T}\ \widehat{\ }\ b to a tree on 𝒱+\mathscr{V}^{+}. Let Q¯+=Q+\bar{Q}^{+}=Q^{+} if QQ has set size, and Q¯+=Hull1Q+(Qδ)\bar{Q}^{+}=\mathrm{Hull}_{1}^{Q^{+}}(\mathscr{I}^{Q}\cup\delta) otherwise. Write 𝒯=𝒯0^𝒯1\mathcal{T}=\mathcal{T}_{0}\ \widehat{\ }\ \mathcal{T}_{1} for the lower and upper components of 𝒯\mathcal{T}, and 𝒯+=𝒯0+^𝒯1+\mathcal{T}^{+}=\mathcal{T}_{0}^{+}\ \widehat{\ }\ \mathcal{T}_{1}^{+} correspondingly. Note that we can rearrange 𝒯+\mathcal{T}^{+} as a tree 𝒯¯¯+=𝒯¯¯0+^𝒯¯¯1+\bar{\bar{\mathcal{T}}}^{+}=\bar{\bar{\mathcal{T}}}^{+}_{0}\ \widehat{\ }\ \bar{\bar{\mathcal{T}}}^{+}_{1} on 𝒱¯¯+\bar{\bar{\mathscr{V}}}^{+} with 𝒯¯¯0+\bar{\bar{\mathcal{T}}}_{0}^{+} equivalent to 𝒯0+\mathcal{T}_{0}^{+} (so M𝒯¯¯0+=U¯¯0+M^{\bar{\bar{\mathcal{T}}}^{+}_{0}}_{\infty}=\bar{\bar{U}}_{0}^{+}), and 𝒯¯¯1+\bar{\bar{\mathcal{T}}}_{1}^{+} given by normalizing a stack equivalent to (j𝒮1,𝒯1+)(j``\mathcal{S}_{1},\mathcal{T}_{1}^{+}), where j:𝒱¯¯+U¯¯0+j:\bar{\bar{\mathscr{V}}}^{+}\to\bar{\bar{U}}_{0}^{+} is the iteration map and j𝒮1j``\mathcal{S}_{1} is the minimal jj-copy of 𝒮1\mathcal{S}_{1}. If QQ is set size then Q¯+=Q(𝒯¯¯+,b)\bar{Q}^{+}=Q(\bar{\bar{\mathcal{T}}}^{+},b) and otherwise Q¯+=Mb𝒯¯¯+\bar{Q}^{+}=M^{\bar{\bar{\mathcal{T}}}^{+}}_{b}. Note that Q¯+\bar{Q}^{+} is δ\delta-sound.

Now compare the phalanx ((U¯¯0+,δ),Q¯+)((\bar{\bar{U}}_{0}^{+},\delta),\bar{Q}^{+}) versus the phalanx ((𝒱¯¯+,δ),U¯+)((\bar{\bar{\mathscr{V}}}^{+},\delta),\bar{U}^{+}), “above δ\delta, modulo the generic at δ\delta and translation for overlapping extenders”, just like in the proof of Lemma 5.1.1, using Φ𝒱¯¯+𝒱¯¯\Phi_{\bar{\bar{\mathscr{V}}}^{+}\supseteq\bar{\bar{\mathscr{V}}}} to iterate the phalanxes (a little bit of normalization shows this works). Because U¯¯0+\bar{\bar{U}}_{0}^{+} is κ0U¯¯0+\kappa_{0}^{\bar{\bar{U}}_{0}^{+}}-sound and 𝒱¯¯+\bar{\bar{\mathscr{V}}}^{+} is κ0𝒱¯¯+\kappa_{0}^{\bar{\bar{\mathscr{V}}}^{+}}-sound and Q¯+,U¯+\bar{Q}^{+},\bar{U}^{+} are δ\delta-sound, essentially the same proof as before shows that the comparison is trivial, which gives P¯=Q¯\bar{P}=\bar{Q}.

We leave part 3 to the reader.

Part 4, sketch:494949We don’t really need this part of the lemma, but it is convenient to have it. Suppose P¯P\bar{P}\neq P; then PP is proper class and U¯U\bar{U}\neq U. Letting 𝒮=𝒮^E1\mathcal{S}^{\prime}=\mathcal{S}\ \widehat{\ }\ E_{1} if E1E_{1}\neq\emptyset, and 𝒮=𝒮\mathcal{S}^{\prime}=\mathcal{S} otherwise, we have U=M𝒮U=M^{\mathcal{S}^{\prime}}_{\infty}. Now it need not be that U¯\bar{U} is Mα𝒮M^{\mathcal{S}^{\prime}}_{\alpha} for some α\alpha, but this is almost the case. In fact, because δ\delta is a δ0U\delta_{0}^{U}-strong cutpoint of UU, we get the following: Let α\alpha be least such that lh(Eα𝒮)>δ{\rm lh}(E^{\mathcal{S}^{\prime}}_{\alpha})>\delta. Then there is a unique tree 𝒮\mathcal{S}^{*} extending 𝒮(α+1)\mathcal{S}^{\prime}{\upharpoonright}(\alpha+1) and such that Eα+i𝒮E^{\mathcal{S}^{*}}_{\alpha+i}\neq\emptyset iff [0,α+i]𝒮[0,\alpha+i]_{\mathcal{S}^{*}} drops, and if non-empty, Eα+i𝒮=F(Mα+i𝒮)E^{\mathcal{S}^{*}}_{\alpha+i}=F(M^{\mathcal{S}^{*}}_{\alpha+i}), and M𝒮=U¯M^{\mathcal{S}^{*}}_{\infty}=\bar{U}. Moreover, UU is a ΣU¯\Sigma_{\bar{U}}-iterate of U¯\bar{U}, via a tree 𝒮~\widetilde{\mathcal{S}} which is a straightforward translation of 𝒮[α,)\mathcal{S}{\upharpoonright}[\alpha,\infty) via a little normalization (in [14] there are similar kinds of calculations, though here it is easier). But 𝒮~\widetilde{\mathcal{S}} is above δ+1\delta+1. Therefore it translates to a tree 𝒮\mathcal{S}^{\dagger} on P¯\bar{P} whose last model is PP. We have Q¯=P¯\bar{Q}=\bar{P} is an iterate of 𝒱1\mathscr{V}_{1} and δ=δ1Q¯\delta=\delta_{1}^{\bar{Q}}. But by the smallness of MM, and since 𝒮\mathcal{S}^{\dagger} is above δ1Q¯\delta_{1}^{\bar{Q}} and does not drop on its main branch, it must be via ΣQ¯\Sigma_{\bar{Q}} (that is, PP has nothing remotely resembling a Woodin cardinal >δ1Q¯>\delta_{1}^{\bar{Q}}, so the Q-structures at limit stages are of 𝒮\mathcal{S}^{\dagger} are trivial). This completes the sketch. ∎

5.1.3 Definability of Σ𝒱,sh\Sigma_{\mathscr{V},\mathrm{sh}} and (variants of) Mb𝒯M^{\mathcal{T}}_{b}

We consider first the question of whether 𝒱1\mathscr{V}_{1} can define its own extender sequence over its universe. We don’t know whether this is the case or not, but in this direction:

Lemma 5.9.

We have:

  1. 1.

    𝒱1|δ0𝒱1\mathscr{V}_{1}|\delta_{0}^{\mathscr{V}_{1}} is definable over the universe of 𝒱1\mathscr{V}_{1}.

  2. 2.

    𝒱1\mathscr{V}_{1} is definable over its universe from the parameter |κ0\mathcal{M}_{\infty}|\kappa_{0}^{\mathcal{M}_{\infty}}.

Proof.

Part 1: Since 𝒱1|δ0𝒱1=|δ0\mathscr{V}_{1}|\delta_{0}^{\mathscr{V}_{1}}=\mathcal{M}_{\infty}|\delta_{0}^{\mathcal{M}_{\infty}} and these have the same Vδ0𝒱1V_{\delta_{0}^{\mathscr{V}_{1}}}, this is an easy corollary of Remark 3 (and its proof).

Part 2: Let UU be the universe of 𝒱1\mathscr{V}_{1}. Recall that UU is closed under Σ\Sigma_{\mathcal{M}_{\infty}} for maximal trees 𝒯\mathcal{T} via Σ,sh\Sigma_{\mathcal{M}_{\infty},\mathrm{sh}}. Since δ\delta_{\infty} is Woodin in 𝒱1\mathscr{V}_{1}, Σ(𝒯)\Sigma_{\mathcal{M}_{\infty}}(\mathcal{T}) is in fact the unique 𝒯\mathcal{T}-cofinal branch in 𝒱1\mathscr{V}_{1}, for such 𝒯\mathcal{T}. Moreover, by the (local) definability of the short tree strategy and of maximality, |κ0\mathcal{M}_{\infty}|\kappa_{0}^{\mathcal{M}_{\infty}} can define the collection of trees in |κ0\mathcal{M}_{\infty}|\kappa_{0}^{\mathcal{M}_{\infty}} which are maximal via Σ,sh\Sigma_{\mathcal{M}_{\infty},\mathrm{sh}}. Therefore working in UU, from parameter |κ0\mathcal{M}_{\infty}|\kappa_{0}^{\mathcal{M}_{\infty}}, 𝒩=|δ\mathcal{N}=\mathcal{M}_{\infty}^{\mathcal{M}_{\infty}}|\delta_{\infty}^{\mathcal{M}_{\infty}} can be computed. But then the branch through the tree from |δ\mathcal{M}_{\infty}|\delta_{\infty} to 𝒩\mathcal{N} can be computed, and hence also e𝒱1e^{\mathscr{V}_{1}} also. Therefore we can compute Ult(U,e𝒱1)\mathrm{Ult}(U,e^{\mathscr{V}_{1}}), which is the universe of Ult(𝒱1,e𝒱1)=𝒱1\mathrm{Ult}(\mathscr{V}_{1},e^{\mathscr{V}_{1}})=\mathscr{V}_{1}^{\mathcal{M}_{\infty}} (by Lemma 4.10). But 𝒱1[|κ0]=^\mathscr{V}_{1}^{\mathcal{M}_{\infty}}[\mathcal{M}_{\infty}|\kappa_{0}^{\mathcal{M}_{\infty}}]\ \widehat{=}\ \mathcal{M}_{\infty}, so we can identify the universe of \mathcal{M}_{\infty}, so by Remark 3, we can identify \mathcal{M}_{\infty} itself. But from ee, we therefore compute *, hence []\mathcal{M}_{\infty}[*], and hence 𝒱1\mathscr{V}_{1}, by Lemma 4.10. ∎

Lemma 5.9.

Let 𝒱\mathscr{V} be a non-dropping Σ𝒱1\Sigma_{\mathscr{V}_{1}}-iterate of 𝒱1\mathscr{V}_{1}. Let λOR\lambda\in\mathrm{OR} with λδ0𝒱\lambda\geq\delta_{0}^{\mathscr{V}} and 𝒱|λ+𝒱\mathbb{P}\in\mathscr{V}|\lambda^{+\mathscr{V}} and gg be (𝒱,)(\mathcal{V},\mathbb{P})-generic.505050When we deal with such generic extensions of such 𝒱\mathscr{V} (here and later), we allow gg to appear in some set-generic extension of VV, as opposed to demanding gVg\in V. Then 𝒱\mathscr{V} is definable over the universe of 𝒱[g]\mathscr{V}[g] from the parameter x=𝒱|λ+𝒱x=\mathscr{V}|\lambda^{+\mathscr{V}}.

Proof.

This is an immediate corollary of Lemma 5.1.3 and ground definability (from the parameter 𝒫()\mathcal{P}(\mathbb{P})). ∎

Lemma 5.9.

Let 𝒱\mathscr{V} be a Σ𝒱1\Sigma_{\mathscr{V}_{1}}-iterate of 𝒱1\mathscr{V}_{1}. Let λδ0𝒱\lambda\geq\delta_{0}^{\mathscr{V}}, let 𝒱|λ\mathbb{P}\in\mathscr{V}|\lambda and gg be (𝒱,)(\mathscr{V},\mathbb{P})-generic. Let x=𝒱|λ+𝒱x=\mathscr{V}|\lambda^{+\mathscr{V}}. Then:

  1. 1.

    𝒱[g]\mathscr{V}[g] is closed under Σ𝒱,shdsr\Sigma^{\mathrm{dsr}}_{\mathscr{V},\mathrm{sh}} and Σ𝒱,shdsr𝒱[g]\Sigma^{\mathrm{dsr}}_{\mathscr{V},\mathrm{sh}}{\upharpoonright}\mathscr{V}[g] is definable over the universe of 𝒱[g]\mathscr{V}[g] from the parameter xx (hence lightface 𝒱\mathscr{V}-definable if g=g=\emptyset).

  2. 2.

    The notions

    1. (a)

      dsr,

    2. (b)

      δ1\delta_{1}-short/δ1\delta_{1}-maximal dsr via Σ𝒱\Sigma_{\mathscr{V}},

    3. (c)

      dsr-P-suitable, and

    4. (d)

      dl-relevant,

    are each definable over 𝒱[g]\mathscr{V}[g] from xx (hence lightface 𝒱\mathscr{V}-definable if g=g=\emptyset).

  3. 3.

    For each δ1\delta_{1}-maximal (hence dsr) P-suitable tree 𝒯𝒱[g]\mathcal{T}\in\mathscr{V}[g], as witnessed by UU, letting 𝒯¯\bar{\mathcal{T}} be the equivalent tree on 𝒱¯=cHull1𝒱(𝒱δ1𝒱)\bar{\mathscr{V}}=\mathrm{cHull}_{1}^{\mathscr{V}}(\mathscr{I}^{\mathscr{V}}\cup\delta_{1}^{\mathscr{V}}) (which is via Σ𝒱¯\Sigma_{\bar{\mathscr{V}}}) and b=Σ𝒱¯(𝒯¯)b=\Sigma_{\bar{\mathscr{V}}}(\bar{\mathcal{T}}), we have

    Mb𝒯¯=cHull1𝒫U,g(M(𝒯))(Uδ(𝒯)).M^{\bar{\mathcal{T}}}_{b}=\mathrm{cHull}_{1}^{\mathscr{P}^{U,g}(M(\mathcal{T}))}(\mathscr{I}^{U}\cup\delta(\mathcal{T})).

    Therefore letting η\eta be least such that 𝒱\mathscr{V} is η\eta-sound (so ηκ1𝒱\eta\leq\kappa_{1}^{\mathscr{V}}), if ηδ=δ(𝒯)\eta\leq\delta=\delta(\mathcal{T}) then Mb𝒯¯=𝒫U,g(M(𝒯))M^{\bar{\mathcal{T}}}_{b}=\mathscr{P}^{U,g}(M(\mathcal{T})) and the function 𝒯Mb𝒯¯\mathcal{T}\mapsto M^{\bar{\mathcal{T}}}_{b} (with domain all such 𝒯\mathcal{T} with ηδ(𝒯)\eta\leq\delta(\mathcal{T})) is definable over the universe of 𝒱[g]\mathscr{V}[g] from the parameter (x,η)(x,\eta) (hence from η\eta over 𝒱\mathscr{V} if g=g=\emptyset).

  4. 4.

    Suppose g=g=\emptyset. Then for each δ1\delta_{1}-maximal tree 𝒯𝒱\mathcal{T}\in\mathscr{V} via Σ𝒱\Sigma_{\mathscr{V}}, with lh(𝒯)<κ1𝒱{\rm lh}(\mathcal{T})<\kappa_{1}^{\mathscr{V}}, letting 𝒯¯\bar{\mathcal{T}} be as in part 3, there is a dl-relevant tree 𝒳𝒱\mathcal{X}\in\mathscr{V}, on 𝒱\mathscr{V}, and such that, letting 𝒳¯\bar{\mathcal{X}} be likewise, then Mc𝒳¯M^{\bar{\mathcal{X}}}_{c} is a ΣMb𝒯¯\Sigma_{M^{\bar{\mathcal{T}}}_{b}}-iterate of Mb𝒯¯M^{\bar{\mathcal{T}}}_{b}, where b=Σ𝒱¯(𝒯¯)b=\Sigma_{\bar{\mathscr{V}}}(\bar{\mathcal{T}}) and c=Σ𝒱¯(𝒳¯)c=\Sigma_{\bar{\mathscr{V}}}(\bar{\mathcal{X}}).

Moreover, the definability is uniform in 𝒱,x\mathscr{V},x, and hence preserved by iteration maps.

Proof Sketch.

Part 3 is an immediate consequence of Lemma 5.1.2.

Parts 1, 2: For simplicity we assume g=g=\emptyset, but the general case is very similar. Let 𝒯𝒱\mathcal{T}\in\mathscr{V} be dsr of limit length and via Σ𝒱\Sigma_{\mathscr{V}}; we will determine whether 𝒯\mathcal{T} is δ1\delta_{1}-short or δ1\delta_{1}-maximal, and if δ1\delta_{1}-short, compute Σ𝒱(𝒯)\Sigma_{\mathscr{V}}(\mathcal{T}). Let 𝒯=𝒯0^𝒯1\mathcal{T}=\mathcal{T}_{0}\ \widehat{\ }\ \mathcal{T}_{1} with lower and upper components 𝒯0,𝒯1\mathcal{T}_{0},\mathcal{T}_{1} respectively. Let E0𝔼𝒱E_{0}\in\mathbb{E}^{\mathscr{V}} be long with γ𝒱<lh(E0)\gamma^{\mathscr{V}}<{\rm lh}(E_{0}) and 𝒯0𝒱|λ\mathcal{T}_{0}\in\mathscr{V}|\lambda^{\prime} where λ=lgcd(𝒱||lh(E0))\lambda^{\prime}=\mathrm{lgcd}(\mathscr{V}||{\rm lh}(E_{0})). Let 𝒯~=𝒯0~^𝒯1~\widetilde{\mathcal{T}}=\widetilde{\mathcal{T}_{0}}\ \widehat{\ }\ \widetilde{\mathcal{T}_{1}} where 𝒯0~\widetilde{\mathcal{T}_{0}} is the successor length tree corresponding to E0E_{0}, and letting k:M𝒯0M𝒯0~k:M^{\mathcal{T}_{0}}_{\infty}\to M^{\widetilde{\mathcal{T}_{0}}}_{\infty} be the iteration map (recall this is known to 𝒱\mathscr{V}), 𝒯1~\widetilde{\mathcal{T}_{1}} is the minimal kk-copy of 𝒯1\mathcal{T}_{1} (so 𝒯~\widetilde{\mathcal{T}} is also via Σ𝒱\Sigma_{\mathscr{V}}, by [15, ***10.3, 10.4]). It suffices to compute Σ𝒱(𝒯~)\Sigma_{\mathscr{V}}(\widetilde{\mathcal{T}}). So instead assume that 𝒯\mathcal{T} is itself in the form of 𝒯~\widetilde{\mathcal{T}}.

Let E1𝔼𝒱E_{1}\in\mathbb{E}^{\mathscr{V}} be 𝒱\mathscr{V}-total with crit(E1)=κ1𝒱{\rm crit}(E_{1})=\kappa_{1}^{\mathscr{V}} and 𝒯𝒱1|λ\mathcal{T}^{\prime}\in\mathscr{V}_{1}|\lambda where λ=λ(E1)\lambda=\lambda(E_{1}) and and 𝒯\mathcal{T}^{\prime} is the tree on 𝒱|δ1\mathscr{V}|\delta_{1} equivalent to 𝒯\mathcal{T}. Let U=Ult(𝒱,E1)U=\mathrm{Ult}(\mathscr{V},E_{1}). Let η<λ\eta<\lambda be a strong δ0𝒱\delta_{0}^{\mathscr{V}}-cutpoint and cardinal of UU with 𝒯U|η\mathcal{T}^{\prime}\in U|\eta. Now working in UU, form a minimal inflation 𝒳\mathcal{X} of 𝒯1\mathcal{T}_{1}^{\prime}, first iterating the least measurable >δ0M𝒯0>\delta_{0}^{M^{\mathcal{T}_{0}}_{\infty}} out to η\eta, and then folding in 𝔼U\mathbb{E}^{U}-genericity iteration. Now 𝒳\mathcal{X} is dsr (the issue being that we do not introduce new Woodin cardinals below the index of some Eβ𝒳E^{\mathcal{X}}_{\beta}, condition 3 in the definition of dsr (see 5.5)), because 𝒯\mathcal{T} is dsr and the inflationary extenders are only being used for genericity iteration (and the linear iteration at the start). The remaining details of the minimal inflation and overall process are as sketched in §4.2 (but the minimal variant, which is essentially the same), using that Σ𝒱\Sigma_{\mathscr{V}} has minimal inflation condensation, by Lemma 4.12.5 and [15, ***Theorem 10.2].

Part 4 follows from the proof of part 2 in the case that 𝒯\mathcal{T} is δ1\delta_{1}-maximal, since by [15], both the conversion from 𝒯\mathcal{T} to 𝒯~\widetilde{\mathcal{T}} and minimal inflation yields a correct iterate. ∎

Definition 5.10.

Let 𝒱\mathscr{V} be a non-dropping Σ𝒱1\Sigma_{\mathscr{V}_{1}}-iterate of 𝒱1\mathscr{V}_{1}, and gg be 𝒱\mathscr{V}-generic. Let 𝒱=𝒱|δ1𝒱\mathscr{V}^{-}=\mathscr{V}|\delta_{1}^{\mathscr{V}}. Then Σ𝒱\Sigma_{\mathscr{V}^{-}} denotes the strategy for 𝒱\mathscr{V}^{-} induced by Σ𝒱\Sigma_{\mathscr{V}}, and Σ𝒱,sh\Sigma_{\mathscr{V}^{-},\mathrm{sh}} denotes its restriction to δ1\delta_{1}-short trees, and Σ𝒱,shdsr\Sigma^{\mathrm{dsr}}_{\mathscr{V}^{-},\mathrm{sh}} its restriction dsr-δ1\delta_{1}-short trees.515151Note that if 𝒱,𝒱\mathscr{V},\mathscr{V}^{\prime} are both such and 𝒱=(𝒱)\mathscr{V}^{-}=(\mathscr{V}^{\prime})^{-}, then we get the same strategy for 𝒱\mathscr{V}^{-} induced by Σ𝒱\Sigma_{\mathscr{V}} and Σ𝒱\Sigma_{\mathscr{V}^{\prime}}. Also if RR is a non-dropping Σ𝒱1\Sigma_{\mathscr{V}_{1}}-iterate of 𝒱1\mathscr{V}_{1}, and R𝒱[g]R^{-}\in\mathscr{V}[g] is a Σ𝒱\Sigma_{\mathscr{V}^{-}}-iterate of 𝒱\mathscr{V}^{-}, then ΣR,sh𝒱[g]\Sigma^{\mathscr{V}[g]}_{R^{-},\mathrm{sh}} and (ΣR,shdsr)𝒱[g](\Sigma^{\mathrm{dsr}}_{R^{-},\mathrm{sh}})^{\mathscr{V}[g]} denote the restrictions of ΣR,sh\Sigma_{R^{-},\mathrm{sh}} and ΣR,shdsr\Sigma^{\mathrm{dsr}}_{R^{-},\mathrm{sh}} to trees in 𝒱[g]\mathscr{V}[g].

Let 𝒯𝒱[g]\mathcal{T}\in\mathscr{V}[g] be P-suitable for 𝒱[g]\mathscr{V}[g], as witnessed by UU. Let R=𝒫U,g(M(𝒯))R=\mathscr{P}^{U,g}(M(\mathcal{T})) (so RR is a 𝒱[g]\mathscr{V}[g]-class and is a Σ𝒱1\Sigma_{\mathscr{V}_{1}}-iterate of 𝒱1\mathscr{V}_{1}). Then ΣR,sh𝒱[g]\Sigma_{R,\mathrm{sh}}^{\mathscr{V}[g]} and (ΣR,shdsr)𝒱[g](\Sigma^{\mathrm{dsr}}_{R,\mathrm{sh}})^{\mathscr{V}[g]} denote the restriction of ΣR\Sigma_{R} to δ1\delta_{1}-short and dsr-δ1\delta_{1}-short trees in 𝒱[g]\mathscr{V}[g], respectively.525252So in the case that 𝒯\mathcal{T} is P-suitable, ΣM(𝒯),sh𝒱[g]\Sigma^{\mathscr{V}[g]}_{M(\mathcal{T}),\mathrm{sh}} and ΣR,sh𝒱[g]\Sigma^{\mathscr{V}[g]}_{R,\mathrm{sh}} are equivalent, as are (ΣM(𝒯),shdsr)𝒱[g](\Sigma^{\mathrm{dsr}}_{M(\mathcal{T}),\mathrm{sh}})^{\mathscr{V}[g]} and (ΣR,shdsr)𝒱[g](\Sigma^{\mathrm{dsr}}_{R,\mathrm{sh}})^{\mathscr{V}[g]}.

Lemma 5.10.

Let 𝒱\mathscr{V} be a Σ𝒱1\Sigma_{\mathscr{V}_{1}}-iterate of 𝒱1\mathscr{V}_{1}, λδ0𝒱\lambda\geq\delta_{0}^{\mathscr{V}}, 𝒱|λ\mathbb{P}\in\mathscr{V}|\lambda and gg be (𝒱,)(\mathscr{V},\mathbb{P})-generic. Let x=𝒱|λ+𝒱x=\mathscr{V}|\lambda^{+\mathscr{V}}. Let 𝒯𝒱[g]\mathcal{T}\in\mathscr{V}[g] be a δ1\delta_{1}-maximal tree on 𝒱\mathscr{V}^{-}, via Σ𝒱\Sigma_{\mathscr{V}^{-}}, and if 𝒯\mathcal{T} is P-suitable for 𝒱[g]\mathscr{V}[g] then let R=𝒫U,g(M(𝒯))R=\mathscr{P}^{U,g}(M(\mathcal{T})), where UU is as above. Then:

  1. 1.

    𝒱[g]\mathscr{V}[g] is closed under (ΣM(𝒯),shdsr)𝒱[g](\Sigma^{\mathrm{dsr}}_{M(\mathcal{T}),\mathrm{sh}})^{\mathscr{V}[g]} and (ΣM(𝒯),shdsr)𝒱[g](\Sigma^{\mathrm{dsr}}_{M(\mathcal{T}),\mathrm{sh}})^{\mathscr{V}[g]} is definable over 𝒱[g]\mathscr{V}[g] from (𝒯,x)(\mathcal{T},x), uniformly in 𝒯\mathcal{T}; hence likewise for (ΣR,shdsr)𝒱[g](\Sigma^{\mathrm{dsr}}_{R,\mathrm{sh}})^{\mathscr{V}[g]} for δ1\delta_{1}-maximal P-suitable trees 𝒯𝒱[g]\mathcal{T}\in\mathscr{V}[g].

  2. 2.

    The notions

    1. dsr, and

    2. δ1\delta_{1}-short/δ1\delta_{1}-maximal dsr via ΣM(𝒯)\Sigma_{M(\mathcal{T})},

    applied to trees in 𝒱[g]\mathscr{V}[g] on M(𝒯)M(\mathcal{T}), are definable over 𝒱[g]\mathscr{V}[g] from (𝒯,x)(\mathcal{T},x), uniformly in 𝒯\mathcal{T}.

  3. 3.

    Suppose 𝒯\mathcal{T} is P-suitable. Let 𝒯\mathcal{T}^{\prime} be the tree on 𝒱\mathscr{V}^{-} iterating out to M(𝒯)=RM(\mathcal{T})=R^{-}. Let 𝒰𝒱[g]\mathcal{U}^{\prime}\in\mathscr{V}[g] be on RR^{-} and via (ΣR,shdsr)𝒱[g](\Sigma^{\mathrm{dsr}}_{R^{-},\mathrm{sh}})^{\mathscr{V}[g]}. Then the stack (𝒯,𝒰)(\mathcal{T}^{\prime},\mathcal{U}^{\prime}) normalizes to a tree on 𝒱\mathscr{V}^{-} via (Σ𝒱,shdsr)𝒱[g](\Sigma^{\mathrm{dsr}}_{\mathscr{V}^{-},\mathrm{sh}})^{\mathscr{V}[g]}.

Moreover, the definability is uniform in 𝒱,x\mathscr{V},x, and so preserved by the iteration maps.

Lemma 5.1.2 suffers from a significant drawback, which is that it is restricted to dsr trees. In [13] there is a generalization of this to arbitrary trees, but this involves a further modification of the P-construction, given by merging the preceding methods with *-translation. We now summarize the key consequences of this, also proven in [13], which we will need later.

Lemma 5.10.

Lemmas 5.1.3 and 5.1.3 both remain true after striking out every instance of the term dsr.

Note that that parts parts 3 and 4 of Lemma 5.1.3 are not actually modified by striking out dsr, because all δ1\delta_{1}-maximal trees are dsr anyway.

5.2 The second direct limit system

We now define a system of uniform grounds for 𝒱1\mathscr{V}_{1}, and the associated Varsovian model 𝒱2\mathscr{V}_{2}. This is analogous to the construction of 𝒱1\mathscr{V}_{1} in §4, albeit slightly more involved. For the most part it is similar, and so we omit details and remarks which are like before. We use the results of §5.1, and in particular the modified P-construction, dsr δ1\delta_{1}-short tree strategies, etc.

5.2.1 The external direct limit system 𝒟1ext{\mathscr{D}}_{1}^{\mathrm{ext}}

Definition 5.11.

Let 𝕌1{\mathbb{U}}_{1} be the 𝒱1\mathscr{V}_{1}-class of all dl-relevant iteration trees (Definition 5.5). Define

d1={𝒱1|δ1𝒱1}{(𝒰)|𝒰𝕌1 is non-trivial}.d_{1}=\{\mathscr{V}_{1}|\delta_{1}^{\mathscr{V}_{1}}\}\cup\{\mathcal{M}(\mathcal{U})\bigm{|}\mathcal{U}\in\mathbb{U}_{1}\text{ is non-trivial}\}.

For pd1p\in d_{1}, set 𝒫p=𝒫𝒱1(p)\mathcal{P}_{p}=\mathscr{P}^{\mathscr{V}_{1}}(p) (P-construction as in Definition 5.8). Write 1={𝒫ppd1}{\mathscr{F}}_{1}=\{\mathcal{P}_{p}\mid p\in d_{1}\}. Define \preceq on d1d_{1} and on 1\mathscr{F}_{1} and maps πpq=i𝒫p𝒫q\pi_{pq}=i_{\mathcal{P}_{p}\mathcal{P}_{q}} for pqp\preceq q as in §4.

By Lemma 5.1.3, (d1,𝒫ppd1)(d_{1},\left<\mathcal{P}_{p}\right>_{p\in d_{1}}) is lightface 𝒱1\mathscr{V}_{1}-definable, as are 𝕌1\mathbb{U}_{1} and 1{\mathscr{F}}_{1}.

Lemma 5.11.

\preceq is a directed partial order, is lightface 𝒱1\mathscr{V}_{1}-definable, and the associated embeddings commute: if PQRP\preceq Q\preceq R then iQRiPQ=iPRi_{QR}\circ i_{PQ}=i_{PR}.

Proof Sketch.

For the definability, that \preceq is partial order, and the commutativity, see the proof of Lemma 4.3.1. For directedness, let 𝒯,𝒰𝕌1\mathcal{T},\mathcal{U}\in\mathbb{U}_{1}, with lower and upper components 𝒯0,𝒯1\mathcal{T}_{0},\mathcal{T}_{1} and 𝒰0,𝒰1\mathcal{U}_{0},\mathcal{U}_{1} respectively. Let E0,F0𝔼𝒱1E_{0},F_{0}\in\mathbb{E}^{\mathscr{V}_{1}} with be 𝒱1\mathscr{V}_{1}-total with crit(E0)=crit(F0)=κ0{\rm crit}(E_{0})={\rm crit}(F_{0})=\kappa_{0} and such that 𝒯0,𝒰0\mathcal{T}_{0},\mathcal{U}_{0} correspond to E0,F0E_{0},F_{0} respectively. We may assume lh(E0)lh(F0){\rm lh}(E_{0})\leq{\rm lh}(F_{0}), so if E0F0E_{0}\neq F_{0} then in fact lh(E0)<λ(F0){\rm lh}(E_{0})<\lambda(F_{0}). Therefore M𝒰0M^{\mathcal{U}_{0}}_{\infty} is a (possibly trivial) iterate of M𝒯0M^{\mathcal{T}_{0}}_{\infty}. Let j:M𝒯0M𝒰0j:M^{\mathcal{T}_{0}}_{\infty}\to M^{\mathcal{U}_{0}}_{\infty} be the iteration map. Let 𝒯1\mathcal{T}_{1}^{\prime} be the minimal jj-copy of 𝒯1\mathcal{T}_{1}. Now proceed with a pseudo-comparison of 𝒰0^𝒯0\mathcal{U}_{0}\ \widehat{\ }\ \mathcal{T}_{0}^{\prime} and 𝒰\mathcal{U} intertwined with pseudo-genericity-iteration, as in Lemma 4.3.1. ∎

Define the external direct limit system 𝒟1ext=(P,Q,iPQ:PQ1)\mathscr{D}^{\mathrm{ext}}_{1}=(P,Q,i_{PQ}\colon P\preceq Q\in{\mathscr{F}}_{1}). We have (ug1), (ug2), (ug3), (ug4), (ug5), (ug6), (ug18), and write

(1ext,(iP:P1))=dirlim𝒟1ext.\displaystyle(\mathcal{M}_{\infty 1}^{\mathrm{ext}},(i_{P\infty}\colon P\in{\mathscr{F}}_{1}))=\mathrm{dirlim}\ \mathscr{D}^{\mathrm{ext}}_{1}. (25)

Let P1P\in\mathscr{F}_{1}. Then 𝒱1|δ1P\mathscr{V}_{1}|\delta_{1}^{P} is (P,𝔹δ1Pδ0PP)(P,{\mathbb{B}}^{P}_{\delta_{1}^{P}\delta_{0}^{P}})-generic and hence P[𝒱1|δ]=δ𝒱1P[\mathscr{V}_{1}|\delta]=^{*}_{\delta}\mathscr{V}_{1}, so PP is a ground for 𝒱1\mathscr{V}_{1} via the extender algebra 𝔹δ1Pδ0P\mathbb{B}_{\delta_{1}^{P}\delta_{0}^{P}} (at δ1P\delta_{1}^{P}, using extenders with critical point δ0P\geq\delta_{0}^{P} (hence >δ0P>\delta_{0}^{P})). Thus:

Definition 5.12.

For P1P\in\mathscr{F}_{1}, let τ1P\tau_{1}^{P} be the canonical class 𝔹δ1Pδ0P\mathbb{B}_{\delta_{1}^{P}\delta_{0}^{P}}-name for 𝒱1\mathscr{V}_{1}, like in Definition 4.5, but incorporating the appropriate conversion for the overlapping extenders (note the generic filter determines 𝒱1|δ0P\mathscr{V}_{1}|\delta_{0}^{P}, which in turn determines the “key” to this conversion).

Lemma 5.12.

(ug19) holds: for each P1P\in\mathscr{F}_{1}, c1P=d1d1Pc^{P}_{1}=d_{1}\cap d^{P}_{1} is dense in (d1P,P)(d^{P}_{1},\preceq^{P}) and dense in (d1,)(d_{1},\preceq), and Pc1P=c1P{\preceq^{P}}{\upharpoonright}c^{P}_{1}={\preceq}{\upharpoonright}c^{P}_{1}.

Proof.

Let P1P\in\mathscr{F}_{1}. That Pc1P=c1P{\preceq^{P}}{\upharpoonright}c^{P}_{1}={\preceq}{\upharpoonright}c^{P}_{1} is by Lemma 5.1.3. So let Q1Q\in\mathscr{F}_{1} and R1PR\in\mathscr{F}_{1}^{P}. We must find S11PS\in\mathscr{F}_{1}\cap\mathscr{F}_{1}^{P} with Q,RSQ,R\preceq S. Let 𝒯P=𝒯P0^𝒯P1\mathcal{T}_{P}=\mathcal{T}_{P0}\ \widehat{\ }\ \mathcal{T}_{P1} be the maximal tree leading from 𝒱1\mathscr{V}_{1} to PP, with lower and upper components 𝒯P0,𝒯P1\mathcal{T}_{P0},\mathcal{T}_{P1} respectively, and likewise for RR, and let 𝒯PQ,𝒯PQ0,𝒯PQ1\mathcal{T}_{PQ},\mathcal{T}_{PQ0},\mathcal{T}_{PQ1} be likewise for QQ in PP. Let E0𝔼𝒱1E_{0}\in\mathbb{E}^{\mathscr{V}_{1}} be long with lh(E0)<κ1{\rm lh}(E_{0})<\kappa_{1} be lh(E0){\rm lh}(E_{0}) sufficiently large that P,Q,RP,Q,R are all translations of one another above some γ<λ(E0)\gamma<\lambda(E_{0}) and the various trees are in 𝒱1|λ(E0)\mathscr{V}_{1}|\lambda(E_{0}). Letting E0P𝔼PE^{P}_{0}\in\mathbb{E}^{P} and E0R𝔼RE^{R}_{0}\in\mathbb{E}^{R} with lh(E0P)=lh(E0R)=lh(E0){\rm lh}(E_{0}^{P})={\rm lh}(E_{0}^{R})={\rm lh}(E_{0}), then E0R,E0PE^{R}_{0},E^{P}_{0} are translations of E0E_{0}, so Ult(𝒱1,E0)\mathrm{Ult}(\mathscr{V}_{1},E_{0}), Ult(P,E0P)\mathrm{Ult}(P,E_{0}^{P}) and Ult(R,E0R)\mathrm{Ult}(R,E_{0}^{R}) agree through their common least Woodin lh(E0){\rm lh}(E_{0}) (but not above there if P𝒱1P\neq\mathscr{V}_{1}, as Ult(𝒱1,E0)\mathrm{Ult}(\mathscr{V}_{1},E_{0}) is δ0Ult(𝒱1,E0)\delta_{0}^{\mathrm{Ult}(\mathscr{V}_{1},E_{0})}-sound, whereas then the others are not). Let σP\sigma\in P be a 𝔹δ1Pδ0P\mathbb{B}_{\delta_{1}^{P}\delta_{0}^{P}}-name for QQ, and let p1𝔹δ1Pδ0Pp_{1}\in\mathbb{B}_{\delta_{1}^{P}\delta_{0}^{P}} be the Boolean value of the statement “τP\tau^{P} is 𝒱1\mathscr{V}_{1}-like and σ1τP\sigma\in\mathscr{F}_{1}^{\tau^{P}}”. Working in PP, we will form a Boolean-valued comparison/genericity iteration of Ult(P,E0P)\mathrm{Ult}(P,E_{0}^{P}), Ult(R,E0R)\mathrm{Ult}(R,E_{0}^{R}) and all interpretations of Ult(σ,Fσ||lh(E0))\mathrm{Ult}(\sigma,F^{\sigma||{\rm lh}(E_{0})}) below p1p_{1}, much as in the proof of Lemma 4.3.1 (in particular incorporating Boolean-valued τ1P\tau_{1}^{P}-genericity). However, because we have not yet established that 𝒱1\mathscr{V}_{1} knows its own δ1\delta_{1}-short tree strategy, we cannot quite argue as for Lemma 4.3.1. Thus, we tweak the comparison as in the following sketch (the process will be use an idea from [20, §7]; see especially [20, Corollary 7.5 and Theorem 7.3 (Claim 8)]).

We define a 𝔹δ1Pδ0P\mathbb{B}_{\delta_{1}^{P}\delta_{0}^{P}}-name for a padded tree 𝒰˙\dot{\mathcal{U}} on σ\sigma, and define padded trees 𝒯\mathcal{T} on Ult(P,E0P)\mathrm{Ult}(P,E_{0}^{P}) and 𝒱\mathcal{V} on Ult(R,E0R)\mathrm{Ult}(R,E_{0}^{R}), recursively on length in the usual manner for comparison. Given (names for) the trees up to length α+1\alpha+1, we will also have some condition qαq_{\alpha}, with qαq0=p1q_{\alpha}\leq q_{0}=p_{1}. Let qα+1q_{\alpha+1} be the Boolean value, below qαq_{\alpha}, of the statement “the least disagreement between Mα𝒰˙M^{\dot{\mathcal{U}}}_{\alpha} and Mα𝒯M^{\mathcal{T}}_{\alpha} and Mα𝒱M^{\mathcal{V}}_{\alpha}, if it exists, involves a dsr extender” (that is, satisfying condition 3 of Definition 5.5). We then take the least forced disagreement working below qα+1q_{\alpha+1}, and use this index and genericity iteration considerations to determine the next extender, etc. Given everything through some limit stage γ\gamma, which is short, the strategies Σ,shdsr\Sigma_{\cdot,\mathrm{sh}}^{\mathrm{dsr}} determine branches (as required), and set qγq_{\gamma} to be the infimum of qαα<γ\left<q_{\alpha}\right>_{\alpha<\gamma}. The rest is as usual. The conditions qαq_{\alpha} are always non-zero, and in fact qαgq_{\alpha}\in g where gg is the generic adding 𝒱1|δ0P\mathscr{V}_{1}|\delta_{0}^{P}, because 𝒰˙g,𝒯,𝒱\dot{\mathcal{U}}_{g},\mathcal{T},\mathcal{V} are then correct trees on R,P,QR,P,Q, which were themselves iterates via dsr trees, and by the analysis of comparison in [15, ***§8], the least disagreement must be an ultrapower-image of one of the extenders used in those dsr trees, and hence be itself appropriate for dsr. Because we rule out the use of non-dsr extenders, the Q-structure(s) QξQ_{\xi} used in the trees at limit stages ξ\xi do not overlap δ(𝒯ξ)\delta(\mathcal{T}{\upharpoonright}\xi) (except possibly with long extenders). They also agree with one another (in 𝒯,𝒱\mathcal{T},\mathcal{V} and all interpretations of 𝒰˙\dot{\mathcal{U}}), and no extenders in 𝔼+Qξ\mathbb{E}_{+}^{Q_{\xi}} are used later in the comparison (in particular for genericity iteration). This is because in PP and in P[g]P[g^{\prime}], the trees are P-suitable, and the Q-structures are produced by P-construction, and because of the agreement between P,𝒱1P,\mathscr{V}_{1}, they are therefore identical. ∎

5.2.2 The internal direct limit system 𝒟1\mathscr{D}_{1}

We adapt Definition 4.6 in the obvious manner, to which we refer the reader for details:

Definition 5.13.

Work in 𝒱1\mathscr{V}_{1}. Define (weak) ss-iterability for P1P\in{\mathscr{F}}_{1} and s[OR]<ω\{}s\in[\mathrm{OR}]^{<\omega}\backslash\{\emptyset\} as in 4.6. If PP is ss-iterable and sts\subseteq t and QQ is tt-iterable with PQP\preceq Q, then likewise for γsP\gamma^{P}_{s}, HsPH^{P}_{s} and πPs,Qt:HsPHtQ\pi_{Ps,Qt}:H^{P}_{s}\to H^{Q}_{t}. Define strong ss-iterability as before.

Let 1+={(P,s)|P and P is strongly s-iterable}\mathscr{F}^{+}_{1}=\{(P,s)\bigm{|}P\in\mathscr{F}\text{ and }P\text{ is strongly }s\text{-iterable}\}, and similarly let d1+={(P|δ1P,s)|(P,s)1+}d^{+}_{1}=\{(P|\delta_{1}^{P},s)\bigm{|}(P,s)\in\mathscr{F}_{1}^{+}\}. The order \preceq on d1+d^{+}_{1} is determined by (ug8). Define \preceq on +\mathscr{F}^{+} likewise. Clearly if (P,s)(Q,t)(R,u)(P,s)\preceq(Q,t)\preceq(R,u) then

πPs,Ru=πQt,RuπPs,Qt.\pi_{Ps,Ru}=\pi_{Qt,Ru}\circ\pi_{Ps,Qt}.

Define the system 𝒟1=(HsP,HtQ,πPs,Qt:(P,s)(Q,t)1+)\mathscr{D}_{1}=(H^{P}_{s},H^{Q}_{t},\pi_{Ps,Qt}\colon(P,s)\preceq(Q,t)\in\mathscr{F}_{1}^{+}).

Given P1P\in\mathscr{F}_{1} and s[OR]<ωs\in[\mathrm{OR}]^{<\omega}, recall that ss is PP-stable iff πPQ(s)=s\pi_{PQ}(s)=s for every Q1Q\in\mathscr{F}_{1} with PQP\preceq Q.

Remark 5.13.

As in Remark 4.3.2, ss-iterability actually implies strong ss-iterability.

The following lemma yields properties (ug7), (ug8), (ug9), (ug10), (ug11), (ug12), (ug13), (ug14), (ug15), (ug16):

Lemma 5.13.

We have:

  1. (a)

    if P1P\in{\mathscr{F}}_{1} and s[OR]<ω\{}s\in[\mathrm{OR}]^{<\omega}\backslash\{\emptyset\} and ss is PP-stable, then (P,s)1+(P,s)\in\mathscr{F}^{+}_{1} and (P,s)(P,s) is true (see Definition 2.1).

  2. (b)

    (1+,)(\mathscr{F}^{+}_{1},\preceq) is directed – for (P,s)(P,s), (Q,t)1+(Q,t)\in\mathscr{F}^{+}_{1} there is (R,u)1+(R,u)\in\mathscr{F}^{+}_{1} with (P,s)(R,u)(P,s)\preceq(R,u) and (Q,t)(R,u)(Q,t)\preceq(R,u) (note u=stu=s\cup t suffices).

  3. (c)

    𝒟1\mathscr{D}_{1} is lightface 𝒱1\mathscr{V}_{1}-definable.

Definition 5.14.

Noting that 𝒱1=M\mathscr{I}^{\mathscr{V}_{1}}=\mathscr{I}^{M} is a club class of generating indiscernibles for 𝒱1\mathscr{V}_{1}, define P=i𝒱1P𝒱1\mathscr{I}^{P}=i_{\mathscr{V}_{1}P}``\mathscr{I}^{\mathscr{V}_{1}} whenever PP is a non-dropping iterate of 𝒱1\mathscr{V}_{1}.

For the following, see the proof of Lemma 4.3.2:

Lemma 5.14.

For each P1P\in\mathscr{F}_{1}, PP is {α}\{\alpha\}-stable for every αM=P\alpha\in\mathscr{I}^{M}=\mathscr{I}^{P}. Therefore property (ug17) holds, as witnessed by some s[M]<ωs\in[\mathscr{I}^{M}]^{<\omega}.

We can now (working in 𝒱1\mathscr{V}_{1}) define the direct limit

(1,πPs,:(P,s)1+)=dirlim𝒟1,({\cal M}_{\infty 1},\pi_{Ps,\infty}\colon(P,s)\in\mathscr{F}_{1}^{+})=\mathrm{dirlim}\ \mathscr{D}_{1}, (26)

and the associated *-map 1*_{1}. This notation is somewhat cumbersome, so let us also write 𝒩=1\mathcal{N}_{\infty}=\mathcal{M}_{\infty 1}, and we will often write * instead of 1*_{1}, where there should be no cause for confusion. By Lemmas 2 and 2, χ:𝒩𝒩ext\chi:{\cal N}_{\infty}\to{\cal N}_{\infty}^{\mathrm{ext}} is the identity and 𝒩=𝒩ext\mathcal{N}_{\infty}=\mathcal{N}_{\infty}^{\mathrm{ext}}. Property (ug20) holds as if P1P\in\mathscr{F}_{1} and Q¯d1Pd1\bar{Q}\in d_{1}^{P}\cap d_{1} then 𝒫Q¯P=𝒫P(Q¯)=𝒫𝒱1(Q¯)\mathcal{P}_{\bar{Q}}^{P}=\mathscr{P}^{P}(\bar{Q})=\mathscr{P}^{\mathscr{V}_{1}}(\bar{Q}), because 𝔼P\mathbb{E}^{P} is a translation of 𝔼𝒱1\mathbb{E}^{\mathscr{V}_{1}} above δ1P\delta_{1}^{P}). And (ug21) again holds if ss is PP-stable.

So we have established (ug1)(ug21). For the remaining properties set δ=δ1𝒱1\delta=\delta_{1}^{\mathscr{V}_{1}} and 𝔹=𝔹δδ0𝒱1𝒱1\mathbb{B}=\mathbb{B}^{\mathscr{V}_{1}}_{\delta\delta_{0}^{\mathscr{V}_{1}}} (for the witnesses to those properties in §2). This gives (ug22). Recall we defined τP\tau^{P} in Definition 5.12. Write δ1=i𝒱1(δ1)=δ1𝒩\delta_{1\infty}=i_{\mathscr{V}_{1}\infty}(\delta_{1})=\delta_{1}^{\mathcal{N}_{\infty}} (replacing the notation δ\delta_{\infty} of §2). As for Lemma 4.3.2:

Lemma 5.14.

We have:

  1. 1.

    For each 𝒱1\mathscr{V}_{1}-stable αOR\alpha\in\mathrm{OR} and each P1P\in\mathscr{F}_{1}, letting and gg be the PP-generic filter for 𝔹δ1Pδ0PP\mathbb{B}_{\delta_{1}^{P}\delta_{0}^{P}}^{P} given by 𝒱1|δ1P\mathscr{V}_{1}|\delta_{1}^{P}, then i𝒱1P(τ𝒱1α)g=𝒱1|αi_{\mathscr{V}_{1}P}(\tau^{\mathscr{V}_{1}}{\upharpoonright}\alpha)_{g}=\mathscr{V}_{1}|\alpha. Moreover, 𝒱1=^P[g]=^P[𝒱1|δ1P]\mathscr{V}_{1}\ \widehat{=}\ P[g]\ \widehat{=}\ P[\mathscr{V}_{1}|\delta_{1}^{P}].

  2. 2.

    (ug24) holds.

  3. 3.

    κ1M=κ1𝒱1\kappa_{1}^{M}=\kappa_{1}^{\mathscr{V}_{1}} is the least measurable cardinal of 𝒩{{\cal N}_{\infty}}.

  4. 4.

    κ1+M=κ1+𝒱1=δ1\kappa_{1}^{+M}=\kappa_{1}^{+\mathscr{V}_{1}}=\delta_{1\infty}.

5.2.3 The second Varsovian model as 𝒩[]\mathcal{N}_{\infty}[*]

Definition 5.15.

Recall that 1*_{1} is the *-map associated to the preceding construction. We define the structure

𝒩[1]=(L[𝒩,1],𝒩,1);\displaystyle\mathcal{N}_{\infty}[*_{1}]=(L[\mathcal{N}_{\infty},*_{1}],\mathcal{N}_{\infty},*_{1}); (27)

that is, with universe L[𝒩,1]L[\mathcal{N}_{\infty},*_{1}] and predicates 𝒩\mathcal{N}_{\infty} and 1*_{1}. However, as mentioned above, we will often abbreviate 1*_{1} with *, hence writing 𝒩[]\mathcal{N}_{\infty}[*].

Note this structure has the universe of the abstract Varsovian model of §2. Essentially by §2, we have the elementary maps

π1:𝒩𝒩𝒩,\pi_{\infty 1}:\mathcal{N}_{\infty}\to\mathcal{N}_{\infty}^{\mathcal{N}_{\infty}},
π1+:𝒩[1]𝒩𝒩[1𝒩],\pi_{\infty 1}^{+}:\mathcal{N}_{\infty}[*_{1}]\to\mathcal{N}_{\infty}^{\mathcal{N}_{\infty}}[*_{1}^{\mathcal{N}_{\infty}}],

where 𝒩𝒩\mathcal{N}_{\infty}^{\mathcal{N}_{\infty}} is computed in 𝒩\mathcal{N}_{\infty} just as 𝒩\mathcal{N}_{\infty} is computed in 𝒱1\mathscr{V}_{1}, and 1𝒩*_{1}^{\mathcal{N}_{\infty}} is the *-map as computed in 𝒩\mathcal{N}_{\infty}. Recall 1π1π1+*_{1}\subseteq\pi_{\infty 1}\subseteq\pi_{\infty 1}^{+}, and these maps are lightface definable over 𝒱1\mathscr{V}_{1}.

We next point out that 𝒩𝒩\mathcal{N}_{\infty}^{\mathcal{N}_{\infty}} is a Σ𝒩\Sigma_{\mathcal{N}_{\infty}}-iterate of 𝒩\mathcal{N}_{\infty} and π1\pi_{\infty 1} is the correct iteration map. We also want to generalize this to other iterates of 𝒱1\mathscr{V}_{1}.

Definition 5.16.

Given a 𝒱1\mathscr{V}_{1}-like Vsp NN, let 𝒟1N\mathscr{D}^{N}_{1} and 𝒩N\mathcal{N}_{\infty}^{N} be defined over NN just as 𝒟1\mathscr{D}_{1}, 𝒩\mathcal{N}_{\infty} are defined over 𝒱1\mathscr{V}_{1}, and likewise 1N,π1N,(π1+)N*_{1}^{N},\pi_{\infty 1}^{N},(\pi_{\infty 1}^{+})^{N}. If NN is a correct iterate of 𝒱1\mathscr{V}_{1}, also define (𝒩ext)N(\mathcal{N}_{\infty}^{\mathrm{ext}})_{N} (the external direct limit) relative to NN, as for 𝒱1\mathscr{V}_{1}: given a maximal tree 𝒯𝕌1N\mathcal{T}\in\mathbb{U}^{N}_{1} (considered as a tree on NN), let b=ΣN(𝒯)b=\Sigma_{N}(\mathcal{T}) and M𝒯=Mb𝒯M_{\mathcal{T}}=M^{\mathcal{T}}_{b}, and let (𝒩ext)N(\mathcal{N}_{\infty}^{\mathrm{ext}})_{N} be the direct limit of these models M𝒯M_{\mathcal{T}} under the iteration maps. If in fact M𝒯=𝒫M(𝒯)NM_{\mathcal{T}}=\mathcal{P}^{N}_{M(\mathcal{T})} (the model indexed by M(𝒯)M(\mathcal{T}) in the covering system 𝒟1N\mathscr{D}^{N}_{1}) for each such 𝒯\mathcal{T}, then define χN:𝒩N(𝒩ext)N\chi_{N}:\mathcal{N}_{\infty}^{N}\to(\mathcal{N}_{\infty}^{\mathrm{ext}})_{N} as in §2.

Lemma 5.16.

Let NN be a δ1N\delta_{1}^{N}-sound, non-dropping Σ𝒱1\Sigma_{\mathscr{V}_{1}}-iterate of 𝒱1\mathscr{V}_{1}.

Then M𝒯=𝒫N(M(𝒯))=𝒫M(𝒯)NM_{\mathcal{T}}=\mathscr{P}^{N}(M(\mathcal{T}))=\mathcal{P}^{N}_{M(\mathcal{T})}535353Recall that the notation is 𝒫(M(𝒯))\mathscr{P}(M(\mathcal{T})) for P-construction over M(𝒯)M(\mathcal{T}), and 𝒫M(𝒯)\mathcal{P}_{M(\mathcal{T})} for the model of 𝒟1\mathscr{D}_{1} indexed at M(𝒯)M(\mathcal{T}). for each 𝒯𝕌1N\mathcal{T}\in\mathbb{U}^{N}_{1}, 𝒩N=(𝒩ext)N\mathcal{N}_{\infty}^{N}=(\mathcal{N}_{\infty}^{\mathrm{ext}})_{N} and χN=id\chi_{N}=\mathrm{id}, and 𝒩N\mathcal{N}_{\infty}^{N} is a δ1𝒩N\delta_{1}^{\mathcal{N}_{\infty}^{N}}-sound, non-dropping ΣN\Sigma_{N}-iterate of NN, and hence is a Σ𝒱1\Sigma_{\mathscr{V}_{1}}-iterate of 𝒱1\mathscr{V}_{1}. Moreover,

π1N:𝒩N𝒩𝒩N\pi_{\infty 1}^{N}:\mathcal{N}_{\infty}^{N}\to\mathcal{N}_{\infty}^{\mathcal{N}_{\infty}^{N}}

is the iteration map according to Σ𝒩N\Sigma_{\mathcal{N}_{\infty}^{N}}. This holds in particular for N=𝒱1N=\mathscr{V}_{1} and for N=𝒩N=\mathcal{N}_{\infty}, so 𝒩𝒩\mathcal{N}_{\infty}^{\mathcal{N}_{\infty}} is a correct iterate of 𝒩\mathcal{N}_{\infty}, and π1\pi_{\infty 1} is the iteration map.

Proof.

This is just Lemma 5.1.2 and a consequence thereof, and by standard arguments. ∎

Like with MM, working in 𝒩[1δ1]\mathcal{N}_{\infty}[*_{1}{\upharpoonright}\delta_{\infty 1}] we can compute π1+\pi_{\infty 1}^{+}, so 𝒩[1]\mathcal{N}_{\infty}[*_{1}] has universe

L[𝒩,1δ1]=L[𝒩,1]=L[𝒩,π1]=L[𝒩,π1+].L[\mathcal{N}_{\infty},*_{1}{\upharpoonright}\delta_{\infty 1}]=L[\mathcal{N}_{\infty},*_{1}]=L[\mathcal{N}_{\infty},\pi_{\infty 1}]=L[\mathcal{N}_{\infty},\pi_{\infty 1}^{+}].

5.2.4 Uniform grounds of 𝒱1\mathscr{V}_{1}

Lemma 5.16.

Write ε=δ1\varepsilon=\delta_{1\infty}. We have:

  1. 1.

    Vε𝒩[1]=Vε𝒩V_{\varepsilon}^{\mathcal{N}_{\infty}[*_{1}]}=V_{\varepsilon}^{{{\cal N}_{\infty}}}.

  2. 2.

    ε\varepsilon is (the second) Woodin in 𝒩[1]\mathcal{N}_{\infty}[*_{1}] (and δ0𝒩\delta_{0}^{\mathcal{N}_{\infty}} the first).

  3. 3.

    Property (ug23) of uniform grounds holds for 𝒩[1]\mathcal{N}_{\infty}[*_{1}] at ε\varepsilon; that is, 𝒩[1]\mathcal{N}_{\infty}[*_{1}]\vDashε\varepsilon is regular and 𝔹\mathbb{B}_{\infty} is ε\varepsilon-cc”. Moreover, 𝒩[1]\mathcal{N}_{\infty}[*_{1}]\vDash𝔹\mathbb{B}_{\infty} is a complete Boolean algebra”.

Proof.

Part 1: As usual we have 1η𝒩*_{1}\upharpoonright\eta\in{{\cal N}_{\infty}} for every η<ε\eta<\varepsilon. Now 𝒩𝒩[1𝒩]\mathcal{N}_{\infty}^{\mathcal{N}_{\infty}}[*_{1}^{\mathcal{N}_{\infty}}] is a class of 𝒩\mathcal{N}_{\infty} and

π1+:𝒩[1]𝒩𝒩[1𝒩]\pi_{\infty 1}^{+}:\mathcal{N}_{\infty}[*_{1}]\to\mathcal{N}_{\infty}^{\mathcal{N}_{\infty}}[*_{1}^{\mathcal{N}_{\infty}}]

is elementary. Let A𝒫(OR)𝒩[1]A\in\mathcal{P}(\mathrm{OR})\cap\mathcal{N}_{\infty}[*_{1}]. Then π1+(A)𝒩\pi_{\infty 1}^{+}(A)\in\mathcal{N}_{\infty}. So if Aη<εA\subseteq\eta<\varepsilon then 𝒩\mathcal{N}_{\infty} can compute AA from the set π1+(A)\pi_{\infty 1}^{+}(A) and the map π1+η=1η\pi_{\infty 1}^{+}{\upharpoonright}\eta=*_{1}{\upharpoonright}\eta. The remaining parts are now as in Lemma 4.6. ∎

So by Theorem 2, 𝒩[1]\mathcal{N}_{\infty}[*_{1}] is a ground of 𝒱1\mathscr{V}_{1}.

5.3 The second Varsovian model as the strategy mouse 𝒱2\mathscr{V}_{2}

Let j:|δ𝒩|δ0𝒩j:\mathcal{M}_{\infty}|\delta_{\infty}\to\mathcal{N}_{\infty}|\delta_{0}^{\mathcal{N}_{\infty}} be the restriction of the Σ\Sigma_{\mathcal{M}_{\infty}}-iteration map. Note that for each ν>κ1\nu>\kappa_{1}, if F=F𝒱1||νF=F^{\mathscr{V}_{1}||\nu}\neq\emptyset is long, then κ1<λ(F)\kappa_{1}<\lambda(F) and 𝒩|δ0𝒩\mathcal{N}_{\infty}|\delta_{0}^{\mathcal{N}_{\infty}} is definable in the codes over 𝒱1|κ1\mathscr{V}_{1}|\kappa_{1}, and hence in 𝒩|δ0𝒩𝒱1|λ\mathcal{N}_{\infty}|\delta_{0}^{\mathcal{N}_{\infty}}\in\mathscr{V}_{1}|\lambda. Moreover, letting P=Ult(𝒱1,F)0P=\mathrm{Ult}(\mathscr{V}_{1},F)\downarrow 0, we have δ0P=lh(F)\delta_{0}^{P}={\rm lh}(F) and P|δ0PP|\delta_{0}^{P} is an iterate of 𝒩|δ0𝒩\mathcal{N}_{\infty}|\delta_{0}^{\mathcal{N}_{\infty}}. In this circumstance let

kν:𝒩|δ0𝒩P|δ0Pk_{\nu}:\mathcal{N}_{\infty}|\delta_{0}^{\mathcal{N}_{\infty}}\to P|\delta_{0}^{P}

be the iteration map. Now define 𝔽>κ1𝒱1\mathbb{F}^{\mathscr{V}_{1}}_{>\kappa_{1}} as the class of all tuples (ν,α,β)OR3(\nu,\alpha,\beta)\in\mathrm{OR}^{3} such that ν>κ1\nu>\kappa_{1}, F=F𝒱1||νF=F^{\mathscr{V}_{1}||\nu}\neq\emptyset and either

  1. FF is short (so κ1crit(F)\kappa_{1}\leq{\rm crit}(F)) and F(α)=βF(\alpha)=\beta, or

  2. FF is long and kν(α)=βk_{\nu}(\alpha)=\beta.

Lemma 5.16.

𝔽>κ1𝒱1{\mathbb{F}}^{\mathscr{V}_{1}}_{>\kappa_{1}} is lightface definable over 𝒩[1]\mathcal{N}_{\infty}[*_{1}].

Proof.

Write * for 1*_{1}. Let (ν,α,β)OR3(\nu,\alpha,\beta)\in\mathrm{OR}^{3} with ν>κ1\nu>\kappa_{1}. Let F=F𝒩||νF^{\prime}=F^{\mathcal{N}_{\infty}||\nu^{*}}. We claim that (ν,α,β)𝔽>κ1𝒱1(\nu,\alpha,\beta)\in{\mathbb{F}}^{\mathscr{V}_{1}}_{>\kappa_{1}} iff either

  1. FF^{\prime}\neq\emptyset is short and F(α)=βF^{\prime}(\alpha^{*})=\beta^{*}, or

  2. FF^{\prime}\neq\emptyset is long and F(α)=βF^{\prime}(\alpha)=\beta^{*} (the argument to FF^{\prime} is α\alpha, not α\alpha^{*}!),

and moreover, if FF\neq\emptyset then FF is short iff FF^{\prime} is short. This is proved like in Lemma 4.5, but the case that FF is long is uses the modified P-construction. ∎

Lemma 5.16.

Let 𝕃=𝕃𝒩[1](κ1){\mathbb{L}}=\mathbb{L}^{\mathcal{N}_{\infty}[*_{1}]}(\kappa_{1}) (Definition 2.3, for adding a subset of κ1\kappa_{1}). Then 𝒱1|κ1\mathscr{V}_{1}|\kappa_{1} is 𝕃{\mathbb{L}}-generic over 𝒩[1]\mathcal{N}_{\infty}[*_{1}] and 𝒩[1][𝒱1|κ1]=^𝒱1\mathcal{N}_{\infty}[*_{1}][\mathscr{V}_{1}|\kappa_{1}]\ \widehat{=}\ \mathscr{V}_{1}.

Proof.

This follows from Lemma 4.5 almost like in the proof of Lemma 4.9, using the fact that 𝒩|δ0𝒩\mathcal{N}_{\infty}|\delta_{0}^{\mathcal{N}_{\infty}} and the iteration map jj used above are definable (in the codes) over 𝒱1|κ1\mathscr{V}_{1}|\kappa_{1}, and hence available to 𝒩[1][𝒱1|κ1]\mathcal{N}_{\infty}[*_{1}][\mathscr{V}_{1}|\kappa_{1}]. ∎

We now adapt Definition 4.10, presenting the second Varsovian model as a strategy mouse 𝒱2\mathscr{V}_{2} analogous to 𝒱1\mathscr{V}_{1}. The sequence 𝔼𝒱2\mathbb{E}^{\mathscr{V}_{2}} will have two kinds of long extenders, corresponding to δ0𝒩\delta_{0}^{\mathcal{N}_{\infty}} and δ1𝒩\delta_{1}^{\mathcal{N}_{\infty}}:

Definition 5.17.

Write γ0𝒱2=γ𝒩\gamma_{0}^{\mathscr{V}_{2}}=\gamma^{\mathcal{N}_{\infty}} and γ1𝒱2=(κ1𝒩)+𝒩\gamma_{1}^{\mathscr{V}_{2}}=(\kappa_{1}^{\mathcal{N}_{\infty}})^{+\mathcal{N}_{\infty}}. Note that

κ1<δ0𝒩<γ0𝒱2<κ1+𝒱1=δ1𝒩<γ1𝒱2.\kappa_{1}<\delta_{0}^{\mathcal{N}_{\infty}}<\gamma_{0}^{\mathscr{V}_{2}}<\kappa_{1}^{+\mathscr{V}_{1}}=\delta_{1}^{\mathcal{N}_{\infty}}<\gamma_{1}^{\mathscr{V}_{2}}.

Define the structure

𝒱2=(L[𝔼𝒱2];,𝔼𝒱2),\mathscr{V}_{2}=(L[{\mathbb{E}}^{\mathscr{V}_{2}}];\in,\mathbb{E}^{\mathscr{V}_{2}}),

with segments 𝒱2||ν=(𝒥ν[𝔼𝒱2ν];,𝔼𝒱2ν,𝔼ν𝒱2)\mathscr{V}_{2}||\nu=(\mathcal{J}_{\nu}[\mathbb{E}^{\mathscr{V}_{2}}{\upharpoonright}\nu];{\in},\mathbb{E}^{\mathscr{V}_{2}}{\upharpoonright}\nu,\mathbb{E}^{\mathscr{V}_{2}}_{\nu}) and their passivizations 𝒱2|ν\mathscr{V}_{2}|\nu, recursively in ν\nu as follows:

𝔼ν𝒱2={𝔼ν𝒩 if ν<γ1𝒱2π1(𝒩|δ1𝒩) if ν=γ1𝒱2𝔼ν𝒱1(𝒱2|ν) if ν>γ1𝒱2 and 𝔼ν𝒱1 is short,kν(𝒩|δ0𝒩) if ν>γ1𝒱2 and 𝔼ν𝒱1 is long,\displaystyle\mathbb{E}_{\nu}^{\mathscr{V}_{2}}=\begin{cases}\mathbb{E}_{\nu}^{{\cal N}_{\infty}}&\mbox{ if }\nu<\gamma_{1}^{\mathscr{V}_{2}}\\ \pi_{\infty 1}{\upharpoonright}({\cal N}_{\infty}|\delta_{1}^{{\cal N}_{\infty}})&\mbox{ if }\nu=\gamma_{1}^{\mathscr{V}_{2}}\\ \mathbb{E}^{\mathscr{V}_{1}}_{\nu}{\upharpoonright}(\mathscr{V}_{2}|\nu)&\mbox{ if }\nu>\gamma_{1}^{\mathscr{V}_{2}}\mbox{ and }\mathbb{E}^{\mathscr{V}_{1}}_{\nu}\text{ is short},\\ k_{\nu}{\upharpoonright}(\mathcal{N}_{\infty}|\delta_{0}^{\mathcal{N}_{\infty}})&\mbox{ if }\nu>\gamma_{1}^{\mathscr{V}_{2}}\mbox{ and }\mathbb{E}^{\mathscr{V}_{1}}_{\nu}\text{ is long},\end{cases} (28)

and with 𝔼𝒱2={(ν,x,y):𝔼ν𝒱1 and y=𝔼ν𝒱1(x)}\mathbb{E}^{\mathscr{V}_{2}}=\{(\nu,x,y)\colon\mathbb{E}_{\nu}^{\mathscr{V}_{1}}\not=\emptyset\text{ and }y=\mathbb{E}_{\nu}^{\mathscr{V}_{1}}(x)\} and 𝔼𝒱2ν\mathbb{E}^{\mathscr{V}_{2}}{\upharpoonright}\nu as usual. (We verify well-definedness in Lemma 5.3.)

Definability etc over 𝒱2\mathscr{V}_{2} has the predicate 𝔼𝒱2\mathbb{E}^{\mathscr{V}_{2}} available by default.

Write ei𝒱2=𝔼γi𝒱2𝒱1e_{i}^{\mathscr{V}_{2}}=\mathbb{E}^{\mathscr{V}_{1}}_{\gamma_{i}^{\mathscr{V}_{2}}} for i=0,1i=0,1.

The fine structural concepts for segments of 𝒱2\mathscr{V}_{2} are defined directly as for segments of 𝒱1\mathscr{V}_{1} (Definition 4.11). The next two lemmas are direct adaptations of Lemmas 4.9, 4.9 respectively:

Lemma 5.17.

Let 𝒱¯=𝒱2||γ1𝒱2\bar{\mathscr{V}}=\mathscr{V}_{2}||\gamma_{1}^{\mathscr{V}_{2}}. Then:

  1. (a)

    𝕃=𝕃𝒩[1](κ1){\mathbb{L}}=\mathbb{L}^{\mathcal{N}_{\infty}[*_{1}]}(\kappa_{1}) is Σ1\Sigma_{1}-definable over 𝒱¯\bar{\mathscr{V}}.

  2. (b)

    𝒱¯\bar{\mathscr{V}} is isomorphic to a structure which is definable without parameters over 𝒱1|κ1+𝒱1\mathscr{V}_{1}|\kappa_{1}^{+\mathscr{V}_{1}}.

  3. (c)

    𝒱¯\bar{\mathscr{V}} is sound, with ρω𝒱¯=ρ1𝒱¯=δ1\rho_{\omega}^{\bar{\mathscr{V}}}=\rho_{1}^{\bar{\mathscr{V}}}=\delta_{1\infty} and p1𝒱¯=p_{1}^{\bar{\mathscr{V}}}=\emptyset.

  4. (d)

    OR𝒱¯<ξ0\mathrm{OR}^{\bar{\mathscr{V}}}<\xi_{0}, where ξ0\xi_{0} is the least ξ>κ1+𝒱1\xi>\kappa_{1}^{+\mathscr{V}_{1}} such that 𝒱1|ξ\mathscr{V}_{1}|\xi is admissible. Therefore 𝒱2||ν\mathscr{V}_{2}||\nu is passive for every ν(γ1𝒱2,ξ0]\nu\in(\gamma_{1}^{\mathscr{V}_{2}},\xi_{0}].

Lemma 5.17.

Let g=g𝒱1|κ1g=g_{\mathscr{V}_{1}|\kappa_{1}} be the (𝒩[1],𝕃)(\mathcal{N}_{\infty}[*_{1}],{\mathbb{L}})-generic determined by 𝒱1|κ1\mathscr{V}_{1}|\kappa_{1}. For every νOR\nu\in\mathrm{OR}:

  1. 1.

    𝒱2|ν\mathscr{V}_{2}|\nu and 𝒱2||ν\mathscr{V}_{2}||\nu are in 𝒩[1]\mathcal{N}_{\infty}[*_{1}],

  2. 2.

    𝒱2|ν\mathscr{V}_{2}|\nu and 𝒱2||ν\mathscr{V}_{2}||\nu are sound,

  3. 3.

    Suppose νξ0\nu\geq\xi_{0} and let E=F𝒱2||νE=F^{\mathscr{V}_{2}||\nu} and E=F𝒱1||νE^{\prime}=F^{\mathscr{V}_{1}||\nu}.545454 Also, M|θ0MM|\theta_{0}^{M} and 𝒱1||γ𝒱1\mathscr{V}_{1}||\gamma^{\mathscr{V}_{1}} are “generically equivalent in the codes”, and letting f:(θ0M,ξ0)(γ𝒱1,ξ0)f:(\theta_{0}^{M},\xi_{0})\to(\gamma^{\mathscr{V}_{1}},\xi_{0}) be the unique surjective order-preserving map, then M|α=M||αM|\alpha=M||\alpha are likewise equivalent with 𝒱1|f(α)=𝒱1||f(α)\mathscr{V}_{1}|f(\alpha)=\mathscr{V}_{1}||f(\alpha) for all αdom(f)\alpha\in{\rm dom}(f), but we will not need this. Then

    1. (a)

      𝕃𝒱2|ν{\mathbb{L}}\in\mathscr{V}_{2}|\nu and gg is (𝒱2|ν,𝕃)(\mathscr{V}_{2}|\nu,\mathbb{L})-generic,

    2. (b)

      (𝒱2|ν)[g]=𝒱1|ν(\mathscr{V}_{2}|\nu)[g]=^{*}\mathscr{V}_{1}|\nu,555555The notation is explained in 5.3.

    3. (c)

      (𝒱2||ν)[g]=𝒱1||ν(\mathscr{V}_{2}||\nu)[g]=^{*}\mathscr{V}_{1}||\nu,

    4. (d)

      if EE^{\prime}\neq\emptyset and crit(E)>κ1{\rm crit}(E^{\prime})>\kappa_{1} then 𝒱2||ν\mathscr{V}_{2}||\nu satisfies the usual premouse axioms with respect to EE (with Jensen indexing; so EE is an extender over 𝒱2|ν\mathscr{V}_{2}|\nu which coheres 𝔼𝒱2|ν\mathbb{E}^{\mathscr{V}_{2}|\nu}, etc),

    5. (e)

      if EE^{\prime}\neq\emptyset and crit(E)=κ1{\rm crit}(E^{\prime})=\kappa_{1} then EE is a long (δ1,ν)(\delta_{1\infty},\nu)-extender over 𝒩\mathcal{N}_{\infty} and

      Ult(𝒩|δ1,E)=iE𝒱1(𝒩|δ1)=𝒩Ult(𝒱1,E)|iE𝒱1(δ1)\mathrm{Ult}(\mathcal{N}_{\infty}|\delta_{1\infty},E)=i^{\mathscr{V}_{1}}_{E^{\prime}}(\mathcal{N}_{\infty}|\delta_{1\infty})=\mathcal{N}_{\infty}^{\mathrm{Ult}(\mathscr{V}_{1},E^{\prime})}|i^{\mathscr{V}_{1}}_{E^{\prime}}(\delta_{1\infty})

      is a lightface proper class of 𝒱2|ν\mathscr{V}_{2}|\nu, uniformly in such ν\nu, and

    6. (f)

      if EE^{\prime}\neq\emptyset and EE^{\prime} is long then EE is a long (δ0𝒩,ν)(\delta_{0}^{\mathcal{N}_{\infty}},\nu)-extender over 𝒩\mathcal{N}_{\infty} and

      Ult(𝒩|δ0𝒩,E)=iE𝒱1(𝒱1|δ0𝒱1)=Ult(𝒱1,E)|iE𝒱1(δ0𝒱1)\mathrm{Ult}(\mathcal{N}_{\infty}|\delta_{0}^{\mathcal{N}_{\infty}},E)=i^{\mathscr{V}_{1}}_{E^{\prime}}(\mathscr{V}_{1}|\delta_{0}^{\mathscr{V}_{1}})=\mathcal{M}_{\infty}^{\mathrm{Ult}(\mathscr{V}_{1},E^{\prime})}|i^{\mathscr{V}_{1}}_{E^{\prime}}(\delta_{0}^{\mathscr{V}_{1}})

      is a lightface proper class of 𝒱2|ν\mathscr{V}_{2}|\nu, uniformly in such ν\nu.

Remark 5.17.

Here the notation ==^{*} is like in Remark 4.9, except that when EE^{\prime} is long, we have E=EjE^{\prime}=E\circ j, instead of EEE\subseteq E^{\prime}; recall jj is encoded into gg. An analogous consideration applies to the proof of part 4 in the next lemma; cf. Lemmas 4.9 and 4.10 and their proofs:

Lemma 5.17.
  1. 1.

    𝒩[1]\mathcal{N}_{\infty}[*_{1}] and 𝒱2\mathscr{V}_{2} have the same universe.

  2. 2.

    Ult(𝒱2,e1𝒱2)=𝒱2𝒩\mathrm{Ult}(\mathscr{V}_{2},e_{1}^{\mathscr{V}_{2}})=\mathscr{V}_{2}^{\mathcal{N}_{\infty}}.

  3. 3.

    𝒱2\mathscr{V}_{2} is a lightface class of 𝒩[1]\mathcal{N}_{\infty}[*_{1}].

  4. 4.

    𝒩[1]\mathcal{N}_{\infty}[*_{1}] is a lightface class of 𝒱2\mathscr{V}_{2}.

5.4 Iterability of 𝒩|δ1\mathcal{N}_{\infty}|\delta_{1\infty} in 𝒱1\mathscr{V}_{1} and 𝒱2\mathscr{V}_{2}

Adapting Definition 4.16:

Definition 5.18.

Let 𝒱\mathscr{V} be a non-dropping Σ𝒱1\Sigma_{\mathscr{V}_{1}}-iterate of 𝒱1\mathscr{V}_{1}. For P1𝒱P\in\mathscr{F}^{\mathscr{V}}_{1} let

HP=Hull1P(δ1P𝒱),H^{P}=\mathrm{Hull}_{1}^{P}(\delta_{1}^{P}\cup\mathscr{I}^{\mathscr{V}}),

P¯\bar{P} its transitive collapse and πP¯P:P¯P\pi_{\bar{P}P}:\bar{P}\to P the uncollapse map. Recall here that by Lemma 5.1.2, P¯\bar{P} is a δ1P¯\delta_{1}^{\bar{P}}-sound Σ𝒱1\Sigma_{\mathscr{V}_{1}}-iterate of 𝒱1\mathscr{V}_{1}. Define (𝒩ext¯)𝒱(\mathcal{N}_{\infty}^{\overline{\mathrm{ext}}})_{\mathscr{V}} as the direct limit of the iterates P¯\bar{P} such for PP.

Recall that 𝒱\mathscr{V} is automatically κ1𝒱\kappa_{1}^{\mathscr{V}}-sound. Let αOR\alpha\in\mathrm{OR} and P1𝒱P\in\mathscr{F}_{1}^{\mathscr{V}}. We say that α\alpha is (P,1𝒱)(P,\mathscr{F}_{1}^{\mathscr{V}})-stable iff whenever PQ1𝒱P\preceq Q\in\mathscr{F}_{1}^{\mathscr{V}}, we have αHQ\alpha\in H^{Q} and

πQ¯QiP¯Q¯πP¯P1(α)=α.\pi_{\bar{Q}Q}\circ i_{\bar{P}\bar{Q}}\circ\pi_{\bar{P}P}^{-1}(\alpha)=\alpha.

Adapting Lemmas 4.4, 4.4, 4.11, 4.11 and 4.11 and their proofs (and using that non-dropping Σ𝒱1\Sigma_{\mathscr{V}_{1}}-iterates of 𝒱1\mathscr{V}_{1} are always κ1𝒱\kappa^{\mathscr{V}}_{1}-sound), we have:

Lemma 5.18.

Let 𝒱\mathscr{V} be a non-dropping Σ𝒱1\Sigma_{\mathscr{V}_{1}}-iterate of 𝒱1\mathscr{V}_{1} and 𝒱¯\bar{\mathscr{V}} be the δ1𝒱\delta_{1}^{\mathscr{V}}-core of 𝒱\mathscr{V}. Let 𝒩=𝒩𝒱\mathcal{N}=\mathcal{N}_{\infty}^{\mathscr{V}}. Then:

  1. 1.

    For each PQ1𝒱P\preceq Q\in\mathscr{F}_{1}^{\mathscr{V}}, we have HPORHQORH^{P}\cap\mathrm{OR}\subseteq H^{Q}\cap\mathrm{OR}.

  2. 2.

    For each αOR\alpha\in\mathrm{OR} there is P1𝒱P\in\mathscr{F}_{1}^{\mathscr{V}} such that α\alpha is (P,1𝒱)(P,\mathscr{F}_{1}^{\mathscr{V}})-stable.

  3. 3.

    𝒩=𝒱1\mathscr{I}^{\mathcal{N}_{\infty}}=\mathscr{I}^{\mathscr{V}_{1}} and i𝒱1𝒩𝒱1=id=1𝒱1i_{\mathscr{V}_{1}\mathcal{N}_{\infty}}{\upharpoonright}\mathscr{I}^{\mathscr{V}_{1}}=\mathrm{id}=*_{1}{\upharpoonright}\mathscr{I}^{\mathscr{V}_{1}},

  4. 4.

    𝒩𝒱=𝒱\mathscr{I}^{\mathcal{N}_{\infty}^{\mathscr{V}}}=\mathscr{I}^{\mathscr{V}} and 1𝒱𝒱=id*_{1}^{\mathscr{V}}{\upharpoonright}\mathscr{I}^{\mathscr{V}}=\mathrm{id},

  5. 5.

    𝒩=𝒩𝒱=i𝒱1𝒱(𝒩)=(𝒩ext¯)𝒱\mathcal{N}=\mathcal{N}_{\infty}^{\mathscr{V}}=i_{\mathscr{V}_{1}\mathscr{V}}(\mathcal{N}_{\infty})=(\mathcal{N}_{\infty}^{\overline{\mathrm{ext}}})_{\mathscr{V}} is a δ1𝒩\delta_{1}^{\mathcal{N}}-sound Σ𝒱¯\Sigma_{\bar{\mathscr{V}}}-iterate of 𝒱¯\bar{\mathscr{V}}. Moreover, 𝒩=(𝒩ext)𝒱\mathcal{N}=(\mathcal{N}_{\infty}^{\mathrm{ext}})_{\mathscr{V}} iff 𝒱¯=𝒱\bar{\mathscr{V}}=\mathscr{V} iff 𝒩\mathcal{N} is a Σ𝒱\Sigma_{\mathscr{V}}-iterate of 𝒱\mathscr{V} iff 𝒱\mathscr{V} is δ1𝒱\delta_{1}^{\mathscr{V}}-sound.

  6. 6.

    Let 𝒱\mathscr{V}^{\prime} be a non-dropping Σ𝒱\Sigma_{\mathscr{V}}-iterate 𝒱\mathscr{V} with 𝒱|κ1𝒱𝒱\mathscr{V}|\kappa_{1}^{\mathscr{V}}\triangleleft\mathscr{V}^{\prime}. Then

    1. (a)

      𝒩𝒱\mathcal{N}_{\infty}^{\mathscr{V}^{\prime}} is a Σ𝒩𝒱\Sigma_{\mathcal{N}_{\infty}^{\mathscr{V}}}-iterate of 𝒩𝒱\mathcal{N}_{\infty}^{\mathscr{V}}, and

    2. (b)

      i𝒱𝒱𝒩𝒱i_{\mathscr{V}\mathscr{V}^{\prime}}{\upharpoonright}\mathcal{N}_{\infty}^{\mathscr{V}} is just the Σ𝒩𝒱\Sigma_{\mathcal{N}_{\infty}^{\mathscr{V}}}-iteration map 𝒩𝒱𝒩𝒱\mathcal{N}_{\infty}^{\mathscr{V}}\to\mathcal{N}_{\infty}^{\mathscr{V}^{\prime}}.

  7. 7.

    𝒩𝒩\mathcal{N}_{\infty}^{\mathcal{N}} is a δ1𝒩𝒩\delta_{1}^{\mathcal{N}_{\infty}^{\mathcal{N}}}-sound Σ𝒩\Sigma_{\mathcal{N}}-iterate of 𝒩\mathcal{N} and 1𝒱π1𝒱:𝒩𝒩𝒩*_{1}^{\mathscr{V}}\subseteq\pi_{1\infty}^{\mathscr{V}}:\mathcal{N}\to\mathcal{N}_{\infty}^{\mathcal{N}} is the Σ𝒩\Sigma_{\mathcal{N}}-iteration map.

Recall that Σ𝒱,𝒱|α\Sigma_{\mathscr{V},\mathscr{V}|\alpha} denotes the restriction of Σ𝒱\Sigma_{\mathscr{V}} to trees based on 𝒱|α\mathscr{V}|\alpha. Write (𝒩𝒱)=𝒩𝒱|δ1𝒱(\mathcal{N}_{\infty}^{\mathscr{V}})^{-}=\mathcal{N}_{\infty}^{\mathscr{V}}|\delta_{1\infty}^{\mathscr{V}}.

Lemma 5.18.

Let 𝒱\mathscr{V} be a non-dropping Σ𝒱1\Sigma_{\mathscr{V}_{1}}-iterate of 𝒱1\mathscr{V}_{1}. Then:

  1. (a)

    𝒱\mathscr{V} is closed under Σ𝒩𝒱,(𝒩𝒱)\Sigma_{{{\cal N}_{\infty}^{\mathscr{V}}},(\mathcal{N}_{\infty}^{\mathscr{V}})^{-}} and Σ𝒩𝒱,(𝒩𝒱)𝒱\Sigma_{{{\cal N}_{\infty}^{\mathscr{V}}},(\mathcal{N}_{\infty}^{\mathscr{V}})^{-}}{\upharpoonright}\mathscr{V} is lightface definable over 𝒱\mathscr{V}.

  2. (b)

    Let λδ0𝒱\lambda\geq\delta_{0}^{\mathscr{V}}, let 𝒱|λ\mathbb{P}\in\mathscr{V}|\lambda, and gg be (𝒱,)(\mathscr{V},\mathbb{P})-generic (with gg appearing in some generic extension of VV). Then 𝒱[g]\mathscr{V}[g] is closed under Σ𝒩𝒱,(𝒩𝒱)\Sigma_{\mathcal{N}_{\infty}^{\mathscr{V}},(\mathcal{N}_{\infty}^{\mathscr{V}})^{-}} and Σ𝒩𝒱,(𝒩𝒱)𝒱\Sigma_{\mathcal{N}_{\infty}^{\mathscr{V}},(\mathcal{N}_{\infty}^{\mathscr{V}})^{-}}{\upharpoonright}\mathscr{V} is definable over the universe of 𝒱[g]\mathscr{V}[g] from the parameter x=𝒱|λ+𝒱x=\mathscr{V}|\lambda^{+\mathscr{V}}, uniformly in λ\lambda.565656Regarding trees V\notin V, cf. Footnote 27.

Moreover, the definability is uniform in 𝒱,x\mathscr{V},x.

Proof.

By Lemma 5.1.3, we can define 𝒱\mathscr{V} from xx in 𝒱[g]\mathscr{V}[g], and uniformly so. To compute the δ1\delta_{1}-short tree strategy (for 𝒩𝒱\mathcal{N}_{\infty}^{\mathscr{V}}) and determine δ1\delta_{1}-maximality, use Lemma 5.1.3 (recall this involves *-translation). The computation of branches at δ1\delta_{1}-maximal stages is like in the proof of Lemma 4.3.2, using Lemmas 5.4 and 3 (or arguing as in Footnote 28 in place of Lemma 3). ∎

By Lemma 4.12.5 and [15, ***Theorem 10.2], Σ𝒩𝒱\Sigma_{\mathcal{N}^{\mathscr{V}}_{\infty}} has minimal inflation condensation. So like in Remark 4.3.2, it follows that 𝒱[g]\mathscr{V}[g] can also compute the tail strategy Γ𝒩𝒱,(𝒩𝒱)\Gamma_{\mathcal{N}_{\infty}^{\mathscr{V}},(\mathcal{N}_{\infty}^{\mathscr{V}})^{-}} for stacks on 𝒩𝒱\mathcal{N}_{\infty}^{\mathscr{V}}, based on (𝒩𝒱)(\mathcal{N}_{\infty}^{\mathscr{V}})^{-} (restricted to stacks in 𝒱[g]\mathscr{V}[g]), as in fact

Γ𝒩𝒱,(𝒩𝒱)=(Σ𝒩𝒱,(Σ𝒱))stk.\Gamma_{\mathcal{N}_{\infty}^{\mathscr{V}},(\mathcal{N}_{\infty}^{\mathscr{V}})^{-}}=(\Sigma_{\mathcal{N}_{\infty}^{\mathscr{V}},(\Sigma_{\infty}^{\mathscr{V}})^{-}})^{\mathrm{stk}}.

Similarly:

Lemma 5.18.

𝒱2\mathscr{V}_{2} is closed under Σ𝒱2,𝒱2\Sigma_{\mathscr{V}_{2},\mathscr{V}_{2}^{-}} and Σ𝒱2,𝒱2𝒱2\Sigma_{\mathscr{V}_{2},\mathscr{V}_{2}^{-}}{\upharpoonright}\mathscr{V}_{2} is lightface definable over 𝒱2\mathscr{V}_{2}.

Proof.

To compute the δ0\delta_{0}-short and δ1\delta_{1}-short tree strategies in 𝒱2\mathscr{V}_{2}, proceed much as in the proof of Lemmas 5.4 and 4.9, naturally adapted to 𝒱2\mathscr{V}_{2}. Since 𝒱2\mathscr{V}_{2} is a ground of 𝒱1\mathscr{V}_{1} via 𝕃𝒱2\mathbb{L}^{\mathscr{V}_{2}} and because of the correspondence between 𝔼𝒱2\mathbb{E}^{\mathscr{V}_{2}}, 𝔼𝒱1\mathbb{E}^{\mathscr{V}_{1}} and 𝔼M\mathbb{E}^{M}, we can perform the relevant P-constructions above γ1𝒱2\gamma_{1}^{\mathscr{V}_{2}} using 𝔼𝒱2\mathbb{E}^{\mathscr{V}_{2}} in the natural way. For δ0\delta_{0}-maximal and δ1\delta_{1}-maximal trees, we use the 0-long and 11-long extenders in 𝔼𝒱2\mathbb{E}^{\mathscr{V}_{2}} as usual. ∎

5.5 2-Varsovian strategy premice

Definition 5.19.

For a 𝒱1\mathscr{V}_{1}-like 𝒱\mathscr{V}, we define the lightface 𝒱\mathscr{V}-classes 𝒩𝒱\mathcal{N}_{\infty}^{\mathscr{V}}, 1𝒱*_{1}^{\mathscr{V}}, 𝒩[1]𝒱\mathcal{N}_{\infty}[*_{1}]^{\mathscr{V}} and 𝒱2𝒱\mathscr{V}_{2}^{\mathscr{V}} over 𝒱\mathscr{V} just as the corresponding classes are defined over 𝒱1\mathscr{V}_{1}.

Also given a 𝒱1\mathscr{V}_{1}-like 𝒱\mathscr{V} and 𝒱¯𝒱\bar{\mathscr{V}}\trianglelefteq\mathscr{V} with κ1+𝒱OR𝒱¯\kappa_{1}^{+\mathscr{V}}\leq\mathrm{OR}^{\bar{\mathscr{V}}}, we define 𝒱2𝒱¯\mathscr{V}_{2}^{\bar{\mathscr{V}}} by recursion on OR𝒱¯\mathrm{OR}^{\bar{\mathscr{V}}} by setting 𝒱2𝒱||(κ1+𝒱+α)=𝒱2𝒱||(γ+α)\mathscr{V}_{2}^{\mathscr{V}||(\kappa_{1}^{+\mathscr{V}}+\alpha)}=\mathscr{V}_{2}^{\mathscr{V}}||(\gamma+\alpha), where γ=γ1𝒱2𝒱\gamma=\gamma_{1}^{\mathscr{V}_{2}^{\mathscr{V}}}. Noting that this definition is level-by-level, we similarly define 𝒱2𝒱¯(κ)\mathscr{V}_{2}^{\bar{\mathscr{V}}}(\kappa) whenever 𝒱¯\bar{\mathscr{V}} is a 𝒱1\mathscr{V}_{1}-small Vsp such that γ0𝒱¯\gamma_{0}^{\bar{\mathscr{V}}} exists and κ\kappa is an inaccessible limit of δ0𝒱¯\delta_{0}^{\bar{\mathscr{V}}}-cutpoints of 𝒱¯\bar{\mathscr{V}} and κ<OR𝒱¯\kappa<\mathrm{OR}^{\bar{\mathscr{V}}}, level-by-level (starting by defining 𝒱2𝒱¯|κ+𝒱¯\mathscr{V}_{2}^{\bar{\mathscr{V}}|\kappa^{+\bar{\mathscr{V}}}} as 𝒱2||γ1𝒱1\mathscr{V}_{2}||\gamma_{1}^{\mathscr{V}_{1}} is defined (in the codes) over 𝒱1|κ1+𝒱1\mathscr{V}_{1}|\kappa_{1}^{+\mathscr{V}_{1}}). We will often suppress the κ\kappa from the notation, writing just 𝒱2N¯\mathscr{V}_{2}^{\bar{N}}.

We now want to axiomatize structures in the hierarchy of 𝒱2\mathscr{V}_{2} to some extent, just like for 𝒱1\mathscr{V}_{1}, adapting Definitions 4.13, 4.14 and 4.15. These are very straightforward adaptations, and the reader could fill it in him/herself, but because they are reasonably detailed, we write them out for convenience:

Definition 5.20.

A base 2-Vsp is an amenable transitive structure 𝒱=(P,F)\mathscr{V}=(P_{\infty},F) such that in some forcing extension there is PP such that:

  1. 1.

    P,PP,P_{\infty} are 1-Vsps which model ZFC\mathrm{ZFC}^{-}, γ0P<ORP\gamma_{0}^{P}<\mathrm{OR}^{P} and γ0P<ORP\gamma_{0}^{P_{\infty}}<\mathrm{OR}^{P_{\infty}}, and P,PP,P_{\infty} are 𝒱1\mathscr{V}_{1}-small (that is, PP has no active segments satisfying “There are δ1,κ1\delta_{1}^{\prime},\kappa_{1}^{\prime} such that γ0P<δ1<κ1\gamma_{0}^{P}<\delta_{1}^{\prime}<\kappa_{1}^{\prime} and δ1\delta_{1}^{\prime} is Woodin and κ1\kappa_{1}^{\prime} is strong”, and likewise for PP_{\infty}).

  2. 2.

    PP has a unique Woodin cardinal δ1P>γ0P\delta_{1}^{P}>\gamma_{0}^{P} and a largest cardinal κ1P>δ1P\kappa_{1}^{P}>\delta_{1}^{P}, and κ1P\kappa_{1}^{P} is inaccessible in PP and a limit of δ0P\delta_{0}^{P}-cutpoints of PP; likewise for PP_{\infty},

  3. 3.

    ORP=δ1P\mathrm{OR}^{P}=\delta_{1}^{P_{\infty}}, κ1P\kappa_{1}^{P} is the least measurable of PP_{\infty} and 𝒱2P=cHull1𝒱(δ1P)\mathscr{V}_{2}^{P}=\mathrm{cHull}_{1}^{\mathscr{V}}(\delta_{1}^{P_{\infty}}),

  4. 4.

    𝒩P\mathcal{N}_{\infty}^{P_{\infty}} (defined over PP_{\infty} like 𝒩|γ1𝒱2\mathcal{N}_{\infty}|\gamma_{1}^{\mathscr{V}_{2}} is defined over 𝒱1|κ1+𝒱1\mathscr{V}_{1}|\kappa_{1}^{+\mathscr{V}_{1}}) is well-defined, and has least measurable κ1P\kappa_{1}^{P_{\infty}} and second Woodin δ1𝒩P=ORP\delta_{1}^{\mathcal{N}_{\infty}^{P_{\infty}}}=\mathrm{OR}^{P_{\infty}},

  5. 5.

    𝒩P|δ1𝒩P\mathcal{N}_{\infty}^{P_{\infty}}|\delta_{1}^{\mathcal{N}_{\infty}^{P_{\infty}}} is obtained by iterating P|δ1PP_{\infty}|\delta_{1}^{P_{\infty}}, via a short-normal tree 𝒯\mathcal{T} of length δ1𝒩P\delta_{1}^{\mathcal{N}_{\infty}^{P_{\infty}}},

  6. 6.

    FF is a cofinal Σ1\Sigma_{1}-elementary (hence fully elementary) embedding

    F:P|δ1P𝒩P|δ1𝒩P,F:P_{\infty}|\delta_{1}^{P_{\infty}}\to\mathcal{N}_{\infty}^{P_{\infty}}|\delta_{1}^{\mathcal{N}_{\infty}{P_{\infty}}},

    and there is a 𝒯\mathcal{T}-cofinal branch bb such that Fib𝒯F\subseteq i^{\mathcal{T}}_{b}, and ib𝒯(δ1P)=δ1𝒩Pi^{\mathcal{T}}_{b}(\delta_{1}^{P_{\infty}})=\delta_{1}^{\mathcal{N}_{\infty}^{P_{\infty}}} (so bb is intercomputable with FF, and note that by amenability of 𝒱\mathscr{V}, FF is amenable to PP_{\infty}, and hence so is bb),

  7. 7.

    ρ1𝒱=δ1P=ORP\rho_{1}^{\mathscr{V}}=\delta_{1}^{P_{\infty}}=\mathrm{OR}^{P} and p1𝒱=p_{1}^{\mathscr{V}}=\emptyset (so 1(𝒱)=𝒱2P\mathfrak{C}_{1}(\mathscr{V})=\mathscr{V}_{2}^{P}) and δ1P\delta_{1}^{P_{\infty}} is Woodin in 𝒥(1(𝒱))\mathcal{J}(\mathfrak{C}_{1}(\mathscr{V})), as witnessed by 𝔼P\mathbb{E}^{P_{\infty}}.

  8. 8.

    PP is (𝒥(1(𝒱)),𝕃𝒱)(\mathcal{J}(\mathfrak{C}_{1}(\mathscr{V})),\mathbb{L}^{\mathscr{V}})-generic, where 𝕃𝒱\mathbb{L}^{\mathscr{V}} is defined over 𝒱\mathscr{V} as 𝕃\mathbb{L} above was defined over 𝒱2||γ1𝒱2\mathscr{V}_{2}||\gamma_{1}^{\mathscr{V}_{2}}.

Remark 4.10 carries over directly.

Definition 5.21.

A 2-Varsovian strategy premouse (2-Vsp) is a structure

𝒱=(𝒥α𝔼,𝔼,F)\mathscr{V}=(\mathcal{J}_{\alpha}^{\mathbb{E}},\mathbb{E},F)

for some sequence 𝔼\mathbb{E} of extenders, where either 𝒱\mathscr{V} is a premouse or a 1-Vsp, or:

  1. 1.

    αOR\alpha\leq\mathrm{OR} and 𝒱\mathscr{V} is an amenable acceptable J-structure,

  2. 2.

    𝒱\mathscr{V} has at least two Woodin cardinals, the least two of which are δ0𝒱<δ1𝒱\delta_{0}^{\mathscr{V}}<\delta_{1}^{\mathscr{V}}, and has an initial segment 𝒱||γ\mathscr{V}||\gamma which is a base 2-Vsp,

  3. 3.

    δ1𝒱<γ\delta_{1}^{\mathscr{V}}<\gamma, so δ1𝒱\delta_{1}^{\mathscr{V}} is the second Woodin of 𝒱||γ\mathscr{V}||\gamma,

  4. 4.

    if FF\neq\emptyset and γ<OR𝒱\gamma<\mathrm{OR}^{\mathscr{V}} then either:

    1. (a)

      𝒱\mathscr{V} satisfies the premouse axioms (for Jensen indexing) with respect to FF, and γ<crit(F)\gamma<{\rm crit}(F), or

    2. (b)

      𝒱\mathscr{V} satisfies the 1-Vsp axioms for a long extender, i.e. clause 4b of Definition 4.14, for giving an iteration map on (the premouse) 𝒱|δ0𝒱\mathscr{V}|\delta_{0}^{\mathscr{V}}, or

    3. (c)
      1. i.

        𝒱pv=(𝒥α𝔼,𝔼,)ZFC\mathscr{V}^{\mathrm{pv}}=(\mathcal{J}_{\alpha}^{\mathbb{E}},\mathbb{E},\emptyset)\vDash\mathrm{ZFC}^{-},

      2. ii.

        𝒱\mathscr{V} has largest cardinal μ\mu, which is inaccessible in 𝒱\mathscr{V} and a limit of δ0𝒱\delta_{0}^{\mathscr{V}}-cutpoints of 𝒱\mathscr{V} (where δ0𝒱\delta_{0}^{\mathscr{V}}-cutpoint applies to both short extenders and long extenders over 𝒱|δ1𝒱\mathscr{V}|\delta_{1}^{\mathscr{V}})

      3. iii.

        𝒩=𝒩𝒱pv\mathcal{N}=\mathcal{N}_{\infty}^{\mathscr{V}^{\mathrm{pv}}} is a well-defined, and satisfies the axioms of a 1-Vsp with δ1𝒩\delta_{1}^{\mathcal{N}} existing (but 𝒩\mathcal{N} is possibly illfounded), and 𝒩\mathcal{N} is (OR𝒱+1)(\mathrm{OR}^{\mathscr{V}}+1)-wellfounded, with δ1𝒩=OR𝒱\delta_{1}^{\mathcal{N}}=\mathrm{OR}^{\mathscr{V}},

      4. iv.

        𝒩|δ1𝒩\mathcal{N}|\delta_{1}^{\mathcal{N}} is a proper class of 𝒱pv\mathscr{V}^{\mathrm{pv}} has least measurable μ\mu,

      5. v.

        FF is a cofinal Σ1\Sigma_{1}-elementary embedding F:𝒱|δ1𝒱𝒩|δ1𝒩F:\mathscr{V}|\delta_{1}^{\mathscr{V}}\to\mathcal{N}|\delta_{1}^{\mathcal{N}},

      6. vi.

        𝒩|δ1𝒩\mathcal{N}|\delta_{1}^{\mathcal{N}} is pseudo-iterate of 𝒱|δ1𝒱\mathscr{V}|\delta_{1}^{\mathscr{V}}, via short-normal tree 𝒯\mathcal{T}, and there is a 𝒯\mathcal{T}-cofinal branch bb such that Fib𝒯F\subseteq i^{\mathcal{T}}_{b} (hence bb is amenable to 𝒱\mathscr{V} and inter-definable with FF over 𝒱pv\mathscr{V}^{\mathrm{pv}}),

  5. 5.

    each proper segment of 𝒱\mathscr{V} is a sound 2-Vsp (defining 2-Vsp recursively), where the fine structural language for active segments is just that with symbols for ,𝔼,F\in,\mathbb{E},F,

  6. 6.

    some p𝕃𝒱=𝕃𝒱||γp\in\mathbb{L}^{\mathscr{V}}=\mathbb{L}^{\mathscr{V}||\gamma} forces that the generic object is a 1-Vsp PP of height δ1𝒱\delta_{1}^{\mathscr{V}} with 𝒱2P=𝒱||γ\mathscr{V}_{2}^{P}=\mathscr{V}||\gamma, and there is an extension PP to a 1-Vsp P+P^{+} such that 𝒱2P+=𝒱\mathscr{V}_{2}^{P^{+}}=\mathscr{V} (so P+P^{+} is level-by-level definable over 𝒱\mathscr{V}, via inverse P-construction).

We write γ1𝒱=γ\gamma_{1}^{\mathscr{V}}=\gamma above (if 𝒱\mathscr{V} is not a 1-Vsp).

Definition 5.22.

A 2-Vsp 𝒱\mathscr{V} is 𝒱2\mathscr{V}_{2}-like iff it is proper class and in some set-generic extension, 𝒱=𝒱2N\mathscr{V}=\mathscr{V}_{2}^{N} for some MswswM_{\mathrm{swsw}}-like premouse NN. (Note this is first-order over 𝒱\mathscr{V}.)

We write 𝒱21=𝒩\mathscr{V}_{2}\downarrow 1=\mathcal{N}_{\infty} and 𝒱20=𝒩0\mathscr{V}_{2}\downarrow 0=\mathcal{N}_{\infty}\downarrow 0. Let 𝒱\mathscr{V} be 𝒱2\mathscr{V}_{2}-like. We define 𝒱1\mathscr{V}\downarrow 1 and 𝒱0\mathscr{V}\downarrow 0 analogously (first-order over 𝒱\mathscr{V} as in the proof of Lemma 5.3 part 4). In fact, let us define 𝒱i\mathscr{V}\downarrow i more generally, in the same first-order manner, but allowing 𝒱\mathscr{V} to be illfounded, but 𝒱2\mathscr{V}_{2}-like with respect to first-order properties. Also if NN is a 1-Vsp, let N1=NN\downarrow 1=N. We write 𝒱\mathscr{V}^{-} for (the 1-Vsp) 𝒱|δ1𝒱\mathscr{V}|\delta_{1}^{\mathscr{V}}. We write Λi𝒱\Lambda^{\mathscr{V}}_{i} for the putative strategy for 𝒱i\mathscr{V}\downarrow i for trees based on 𝒱|δi𝒱\mathscr{V}|\delta_{i}^{\mathscr{V}}, defined over 𝒱\mathscr{V} just as the corresponding restrictions of Σ𝒱2i\Sigma_{\mathscr{V}_{2}\downarrow i} are defined over 𝒱2\mathscr{V}_{2}, via the proof of Lemma 5.4.

We write 𝒱2=𝒱(𝒩,1)=𝒱(𝒩,1δ1)=𝒱(𝒩,e1𝒱2)\mathscr{V}_{2}=\mathscr{V}(\mathcal{N}_{\infty},*_{1})=\mathscr{V}(\mathcal{N}_{\infty},*_{1}{\upharpoonright}\delta_{1\infty})=\mathscr{V}(\mathcal{N}_{\infty},e_{1}^{\mathscr{V}_{2}}). Given a pair (N,)(N,*^{\prime}) or (N,δ)(N,*^{\prime}{\upharpoonright}\delta) or (N,e)(N,e) where NN is 𝒱1\mathscr{V}_{1}-like and the pair has similar first-order properties as does (𝒩,1)(\mathcal{N}_{\infty},*_{1}) or (𝒩,1δ1)(\mathcal{N}_{\infty},*_{1}{\upharpoonright}\delta_{1\infty}) or (𝒩,e1𝒱2)(\mathcal{N}_{\infty},e_{1}^{\mathscr{V}_{2}}) respectively, we define 𝒱(N,)\mathscr{V}(N,*^{\prime}) or 𝒱(N,δ)\mathscr{V}(N,*^{\prime}{\upharpoonright}\delta) or 𝒱(N,e)\mathscr{V}(N,e) analogously (via the proof of Lemma 5.3 part 3).

5.6 Iterability of 𝒱2\mathscr{V}_{2}

In this subsection we will define a normal iteration strategy Σ𝒱2\Sigma_{\mathscr{V}_{2}} for 𝒱2\mathscr{V}_{2} in VV.

Definition 5.23.

For i1i\leq 1, an ii-long extender is a (δi𝒱,δ)(\delta_{i}^{\mathscr{V}},\delta)-extender over 𝒱\mathscr{V}, for some premouse, 1-Vsp or 2-Vsp 𝒱\mathscr{V}, and some δ\delta.

Definition 5.24.

Let 𝒱\mathscr{V} be a 𝒱2\mathscr{V}_{2}-like 2-Vsp. A 0-maximal iteration tree 𝒯\mathcal{T} on 𝒱\mathscr{V} of length λ1\lambda\geq 1 is a system with the usual properties for 0-maximality, except that when Eα𝒯E^{\mathcal{T}}_{\alpha} is a ii-long extender, then then pred𝒯(α+1)\mathrm{pred}^{\mathcal{T}}(\alpha+1) is the least βα\beta\leq\alpha such that [0,β]𝒯[0,\beta]_{\mathcal{T}} does not drop and δiMβ𝒯<lh(Eα𝒯)\delta_{i}^{M^{\mathcal{T}}_{\beta}}<{\rm lh}(E^{\mathcal{T}}_{\alpha}).

Iteration strategies and iterability for (such trees on) 𝒱2\mathscr{V}_{2} are defined in the obvious manner (one detail here is that if [0,α+1]𝒯[0,\alpha+1]_{\mathcal{T}} does not drop then Mα+1𝒯M^{\mathcal{T}}_{\alpha+1} is a (putative) 2-Vsp, including when Eα𝒯E^{\mathcal{T}}_{\alpha} is 0-long).

Definition 5.25.

A short-normal tree on a 𝒱2\mathscr{V}_{2}-like 2-Vsp 𝒱\mathscr{V} is a 0-maximal tree that uses no long extenders. Note that a short-normal tree is of the form 𝒯0^𝒯1^𝒮\mathcal{T}_{0}\ \widehat{\ }\ \mathcal{T}_{1}\ \widehat{\ }\ \mathcal{S}, where 𝒯0\mathcal{T}_{0} is based on 𝒱|δ0𝒱\mathscr{V}|\delta_{0}^{\mathscr{V}}, either

  1. (i)

    [𝒯0\mathcal{T}_{0} has limit length or b𝒯0b^{\mathcal{T}_{0}} drops] and 𝒯1=𝒮=\mathcal{T}_{1}=\mathcal{S}=\emptyset, or

  2. (ii)

    𝒯0\mathcal{T}_{0} has successor length, b𝒯0b^{\mathcal{T}_{0}} does not drop and 𝒯1\mathcal{T}_{1} is above γ0M𝒯0\gamma_{0}^{M^{\mathcal{T}_{0}}_{\infty}} and based on M𝒯0|δ1M𝒯0M^{\mathcal{T}_{0}}_{\infty}|\delta_{1}^{M^{\mathcal{T}_{0}}_{\infty}},

and if 𝒯1\mathcal{T}_{1}\neq\emptyset then either

  1. (i)

    [𝒯1\mathcal{T}_{1} has limit length or b𝒯1b^{\mathcal{T}_{1}} drops] and 𝒮=\mathcal{S}=\emptyset, or

  2. (ii)

    𝒯1\mathcal{T}_{1} has successor length, b𝒯1b^{\mathcal{T}_{1}} does not drop and 𝒮\mathcal{S} is above γ1M𝒯1\gamma_{1}^{M^{\mathcal{T}_{1}}_{\infty}}.

Say that 𝒯0^𝒯1\mathcal{T}_{0}\ \widehat{\ }\ \mathcal{T}_{1} and 𝒮\mathcal{S} are the lower, upper components respectively, and 𝒯i\mathcal{T}_{i} the ii-lower component.

5.6.1 Condensation properties for full normalization

Definition 5.26.

We define the notions (m+1)(m+1)-relevantly condensing, (m+1)(m+1)-sub-condensing and nn-standard for 2-Vsps just as for 1-Vsps (see Definition 4.24), replacing the role of premice there with 1-Vsps, and replacing δ0𝒱,γ0𝒱\delta_{0}^{\mathscr{V}},\gamma_{0}^{\mathscr{V}} with δ1𝒱,γ1𝒱\delta_{1}^{\mathscr{V}},\gamma_{1}^{\mathscr{V}}.

By Lemma 4.12.3 and its proof we have the following, and Remark 4.12.3 carries over directly:

Lemma 5.26.

𝒱2\mathscr{V}_{2} is ω\omega-standard. (Thus, we take 𝒱2\mathscr{V}_{2}-like to include ω\omega-standard.)

5.6.2 Tree translation from 𝒱1\mathscr{V}_{1} to 𝒱2\mathscr{V}_{2}

Definition 5.27.

Let 𝒱\mathscr{V} be 𝒱1\mathscr{V}_{1}-like. We define 1-translatable trees 𝒯\mathcal{T} on 𝒱\mathscr{V} like in Definition 4.19, with 0 replaced by 11 as appropriate, but add the demand that 𝒯\mathcal{T} uses no 0-long extenders.

Let 𝒯\mathcal{T} on 𝒱\mathscr{V} be 1-translatable. The 1-translation of 𝒯\mathcal{T} is the tree on 𝒱2𝒱\mathscr{V}_{2}^{\mathscr{V}} defined just as in Definition 4.20.

Remarks 4.12.1 and 4.12.1 carry over directly, replacing 0 with 11 as appropriate. Likewise Lemma 4.12.1 and its proof:

Lemma 5.27.

Let 𝒯\mathcal{T} on 𝒱\mathscr{V} be 11-translatable, where 𝒱\mathscr{V} is 𝒱1\mathscr{V}_{1}-like. Then:

  1. 1.

    The 1-translation 𝒰\mathcal{U} of 𝒯\mathcal{T} exists and is unique.

  2. 2.

    Mα𝒰=𝒱2Mα𝒯M^{\mathcal{U}}_{\alpha}=\mathscr{V}_{2}^{M^{\mathcal{T}}_{\alpha}} and γ1Mα𝒰<OR(Mα𝒰)\gamma_{1}^{M^{\mathcal{U}}_{\alpha}}<\mathrm{OR}(M^{\mathcal{U}}_{\alpha}) for all α<lh(𝒯)\alpha<{\rm lh}(\mathcal{T}).

  3. 3.

    iαβ𝒰=iαβ𝒯Mα𝒰i^{\mathcal{U}}_{\alpha\beta}=i^{\mathcal{T}}_{\alpha\beta}{\upharpoonright}M^{\mathcal{U}}_{\alpha} for all α<𝒯β\alpha<_{\mathcal{T}}\beta such that (α,β]𝒯(\alpha,\beta]_{\mathcal{T}} does not drop.

  4. 4.

    Mα+1𝒰=𝒱2Mα+1𝒯M^{*\mathcal{U}}_{\alpha+1}=\mathscr{V}_{2}^{M^{*\mathcal{T}}_{\alpha+1}} for all α+1<lh(𝒯)\alpha+1<{\rm lh}(\mathcal{T}).

  5. 5.

    iα+1𝒰=iα+1𝒯Mα+1𝒰i^{*\mathcal{U}}_{\alpha+1}=i^{*\mathcal{T}}_{\alpha+1}{\upharpoonright}M^{*\mathcal{U}}_{\alpha+1} for all α+1<lh(𝒯)\alpha+1<{\rm lh}(\mathcal{T}).

5.6.3 Trees based on 𝒩|δ1𝒩\mathcal{N}_{\infty}|\delta_{1}^{\mathcal{N}_{\infty}}

Toward defining Σ𝒱2\Sigma_{\mathscr{V}_{2}}, we first consider trees on 𝒱2\mathscr{V}_{2} based on 𝒱2=𝒩|δ1𝒩\mathscr{V}_{2}^{-}=\mathcal{N}_{\infty}|\delta_{1}^{\mathcal{N}_{\infty}}, adapting Definition 4.21:

Definition 5.28.

Write Σ𝒩,𝒱2sn\Sigma^{\mathrm{sn}}_{\mathcal{N}_{\infty},\mathscr{V}_{2}^{-}} for the strategy for 𝒩\mathcal{N}_{\infty} for short-normal trees based on 𝒱2\mathscr{V}_{2}^{-}, induced by Σ𝒩\Sigma_{\mathcal{N}_{\infty}}. Let Ψ𝒱2,𝒱2\Psi_{\mathscr{V}_{2},\mathscr{V}_{2}^{-}} denote the putative strategy for short-normal trees on 𝒱2\mathscr{V}_{2} based on 𝒱2\mathscr{V}_{2}^{-}, induced by Σ𝒩,𝒱2sn\Sigma^{\mathrm{sn}}_{\mathcal{N}_{\infty},\mathscr{V}_{2}^{-}}. This makes sense by Lemma 5.2.4.

Remark 4.12.2 adapts routinely. We now partially adapt Lemma 4.12.2, but omit the clause “and in fact, ΛMα𝒰ΣMα𝒯\Lambda^{M^{\mathcal{U}}_{\alpha}}\subseteq\Sigma_{M^{\mathcal{T}}_{\alpha}}”, as we will prove this in more generality later, in Lemma 5.6.4. The proof of the rest is a direct adaptation:

Lemma 5.28.

Ψ𝒱2,𝒱2\Psi_{\mathscr{V}_{2},\mathscr{V}_{2}^{-}} yields wellfounded models. Moreover, let 𝒯\mathcal{T} be on 𝒩\mathcal{N}_{\infty}, via Σ𝒩,𝒱2sn\Sigma^{\mathrm{sn}}_{\mathcal{N}_{\infty},\mathscr{V}_{2}^{-}}, and let 𝒰\mathcal{U} be the corresponding tree on 𝒱2\mathscr{V}_{2} (so via Ψ𝒱2,𝒱2\Psi_{\mathscr{V}_{2},\mathscr{V}_{2}^{-}}). Let

πα:Mα𝒯Mα𝒰1Mα𝒰\pi_{\alpha}:M^{\mathcal{T}}_{\alpha}\to M^{\mathcal{U}}_{\alpha}\downarrow 1\subseteq M^{\mathcal{U}}_{\alpha}

be the natural copy map (where π0=id\pi_{0}=\mathrm{id}). Then:

  1. (i)

    [0,α]𝒯[0,\alpha]_{\mathcal{T}} drops iff [0,α]𝒰[0,\alpha]_{\mathcal{U}} drops.

  2. (ii)

    If [0,α]𝒯[0,\alpha]_{\mathcal{T}} drops then Mα𝒯=Mα𝒰=Mα𝒰1M^{\mathcal{T}}_{\alpha}=M^{\mathcal{U}}_{\alpha}=M^{\mathcal{U}}_{\alpha}\downarrow 1 (cf. Remark 4.12.2 adapted ).

  3. (iii)

    If [0,α]𝒯[0,\alpha]_{\mathcal{T}} does not drop then Mα𝒯=Mα𝒰1M^{\mathcal{T}}_{\alpha}=M^{\mathcal{U}}_{\alpha}\downarrow 1 and Mα𝒰=𝒱(Mα𝒯,)M^{\mathcal{U}}_{\alpha}=\mathscr{V}(M^{\mathcal{T}}_{\alpha},\ell) where :Mα𝒯𝒩Mα𝒯\ell:M^{\mathcal{T}}_{\alpha}\to\mathcal{N}_{\infty}^{M^{\mathcal{T}}_{\alpha}} is the correct iteration map,

  4. (iv)

    πα=id\pi_{\alpha}=\mathrm{id}; therefore, iα𝒯iα𝒰i^{\mathcal{T}}_{\alpha}\subseteq i^{\mathcal{U}}_{\alpha}.

Definition 5.29.

Given a non-dropping Ψ𝒱2,𝒱2\Psi_{\mathscr{V}_{2},\mathscr{V}_{2}^{-}}-iterate 𝒱\mathscr{V} of 𝒱2\mathscr{V}_{2}, let Ψ𝒱,𝒱\Psi_{\mathscr{V},\mathscr{V}^{-}} be induced by Σ𝒱1\Sigma_{\mathscr{V}\downarrow 1} just as Ψ𝒱2,𝒱2\Psi_{\mathscr{V}_{2},\mathscr{V}_{2}^{-}} is induced by Σ𝒩\Sigma_{\mathcal{N}_{\infty}} (this makes sense by Lemma 5.6.3).

5.6.4 Short-normal trees on 𝒱2\mathscr{V}_{2}

Definition 5.30.

Let 𝒱\mathscr{V} be a (possibly dropping, putative) iterate of 𝒱2\mathscr{V}_{2}, via a short-normal tree 𝒯^𝒮\mathcal{T}\ \widehat{\ }\ \mathcal{S} with lower and upper components 𝒯,𝒮\mathcal{T},\mathcal{S}. We say that 𝒱\mathscr{V} is good iff 𝒯\mathcal{T} is via Ψ𝒱2,𝒱2\Psi_{\mathscr{V}_{2},\mathscr{V}_{2}^{-}}, 𝒱\mathscr{V} is wellfounded and for every ii-long E𝔼+𝒱E\in\mathbb{E}_{+}^{\mathscr{V}}, i𝒱|lh(E)=P|δiP\mathcal{M}_{i\infty}^{\mathscr{V}|{\rm lh}(E)}=P|\delta_{i}^{P} for some Σ𝒱i\Sigma_{\mathscr{V}\downarrow i}-iterate PP of 𝒱i\mathscr{V}\downarrow i, and EE is the corresponding iteration map.

Say that a (partial) iteration strategy Ψ\Psi for 𝒱2\mathscr{V}_{2} is good iff all putative iterates via Ψ\Psi are good.

We now extend Ψ𝒱2,𝒱2\Psi_{\mathscr{V}_{2},\mathscr{V}_{2}^{-}} to a good short-normal 0-maximal strategy Ψsn\Psi_{\mathrm{sn}} for 𝒱2\mathscr{V}_{2}. We first deal with trees based on 𝒱||γ1𝒱\mathscr{V}||\gamma_{1}^{\mathscr{V}}:

Definition 5.31.

Write Ψ𝒱2,γ1𝒱2\Psi_{\mathscr{V}_{2},\gamma_{1}^{\mathscr{V}_{2}}} for the putative strategy Ψ\Psi for 𝒱2\mathscr{V}_{2}, for short-normal 0-maximal trees based on 𝒱2||γ1𝒱2\mathscr{V}_{2}||\gamma_{1}^{\mathscr{V}_{2}}, as follows:

  1. 1.

    Ψ𝒱2,𝒱2Ψ\Psi_{\mathscr{V}_{2},\mathscr{V}_{2}^{-}}\subseteq\Psi, and

  2. 2.

    given 𝒯\mathcal{T} via Ψ𝒱2,𝒱2\Psi_{\mathscr{V}_{2},\mathscr{V}_{2}^{-}}, of successor length α+1\alpha+1, where [0,α]𝒯[0,\alpha]_{\mathcal{T}} does not drop, and given a putative 0-maximal tree 𝒰\mathcal{U} on Mα𝒯||γ1Mα𝒯M^{\mathcal{T}}_{\alpha}||\gamma_{1}^{M^{\mathcal{T}}_{\alpha}}, which is above δ1Mα𝒯\delta_{1}^{M^{\mathcal{T}}_{\alpha}}, then 𝒯^𝒰\mathcal{T}\ \widehat{\ }\ \mathcal{U} is (equivalent to a tree) via Ψ\Psi iff there is a tree 𝒰\mathcal{U}^{\prime} on Mα𝒯1{M^{\mathcal{T}}_{\alpha}\downarrow 1}, via ΣMα𝒯1\Sigma_{M^{\mathcal{T}}_{\alpha}\downarrow 1}, with the same extenders and tree order as 𝒰\mathcal{U}.

We adapt Lemma 4.12.4:

Lemma 5.31.

Ψ𝒱2,γ1𝒱2\Psi_{\mathscr{V}_{2},\gamma_{1}^{\mathscr{V}_{2}}} is a short-normal 0-maximal strategy (hence yields wellfounded models). Moreover, let 𝒯^𝒰\mathcal{T}\ \widehat{\ }\ \mathcal{U} and 𝒰\mathcal{U}^{\prime} be as in Definition 5.31, with 𝒰\mathcal{U}\neq\emptyset. Then:

  1. 1.

    M0𝒰=Mα𝒯||γ1Mα𝒯M^{\mathcal{U}}_{0}=M^{\mathcal{T}}_{\alpha}||\gamma_{1}^{M^{\mathcal{T}}_{\alpha}} and deg0𝒰=0\deg^{\mathcal{U}}_{0}=0,

  2. 2.

    M0𝒰=Mα𝒯1M^{\mathcal{U}^{\prime}}_{0}={M^{\mathcal{T}}_{\alpha}\downarrow 1} and deg0𝒰=0\deg^{\mathcal{U}^{\prime}}_{0}=0, so (M0𝒰)pv=M0𝒰|κ1+M0𝒰(M^{\mathcal{U}}_{0})^{\mathrm{pv}}=M^{\mathcal{U}^{\prime}}_{0}|\kappa_{1}^{+M^{\mathcal{U}^{\prime}}_{0}},

  3. 3.

    for 0<β<lh(𝒰)0<\beta<{\rm lh}(\mathcal{U}), β𝒟deg𝒰β𝒟deg𝒰\beta\in\mathscr{D}_{\deg}^{\mathcal{U}}\Leftrightarrow\beta\in\mathscr{D}_{\deg}^{\mathcal{U}^{\prime}}, and degβ𝒰=degβ𝒰\deg^{\mathcal{U}}_{\beta}=\deg^{\mathcal{U}^{\prime}}_{\beta},

  4. 4.

    if 0<β<lh(𝒰)0<\beta<{\rm lh}(\mathcal{U}) and [0,β]𝒰[0,\beta]_{\mathcal{U}} drops then Mβ𝒰=Mβ𝒰M^{\mathcal{U}}_{\beta}=M^{\mathcal{U}}_{\beta^{\prime}},

  5. 5.

    if 0<β<lh(𝒰)0<\beta<{\rm lh}(\mathcal{U}) and [0,β]𝒰[0,\beta]_{\mathcal{U}} does not drop then (Mβ𝒰)pv=Mβ𝒰|κ1+Mβ𝒰(M^{\mathcal{U}}_{\beta})^{\mathrm{pv}}=M^{\mathcal{U}^{\prime}}_{\beta}|\kappa_{1}^{+M^{\mathcal{U}^{\prime}}_{\beta}},

  6. 6.

    if 0<β+1<lh(𝒰)0<\beta+1<{\rm lh}(\mathcal{U}) and [0,β+1]𝒰[0,\beta+1]_{\mathcal{U}} drops then Mβ+1𝒰=Mβ+1𝒰M^{*\mathcal{U}}_{\beta+1}=M^{*\mathcal{U}^{\prime}}_{\beta+1} and iβ+1𝒰=iβ+1𝒰i^{*\mathcal{U}}_{\beta+1}=i^{*\mathcal{U}^{\prime}}_{\beta+1},

  7. 7.

    if 0<β+1<lh(𝒰)0<\beta+1<{\rm lh}(\mathcal{U}) and [0,β+1]𝒰[0,\beta+1]_{\mathcal{U}^{\prime}} does not drop then iβ+1𝒰iβ+1𝒰i^{*\mathcal{U}}_{\beta+1}\subseteq i^{*\mathcal{U}^{\prime}}_{\beta+1},

  8. 8.

    if 0β<lh(𝒰)0\leq\beta<{\rm lh}(\mathcal{U}) and [0,β]𝒰[0,\beta]_{\mathcal{U}} does not drop then Mβ𝒰M^{\mathcal{U}^{\prime}}_{\beta} is a (κ1Mβ𝒰\kappa_{1}^{M^{\mathcal{U}^{\prime}}_{\beta}}-sound) ΣMα𝒯1\Sigma_{M^{\mathcal{T}}_{\alpha}\downarrow 1}-iterate of Mα𝒯1{M^{\mathcal{T}}_{\alpha}\downarrow 1}, 𝒩Mβ𝒰\mathcal{N}_{\infty}^{M^{\mathcal{U}^{\prime}}_{\beta}} is a δ1𝒩Mβ𝒰\delta_{1}^{\mathcal{N}_{\infty}^{M^{\mathcal{U}^{\prime}}_{\beta}}}-sound ΣMα𝒯1\Sigma_{M^{\mathcal{T}}_{\alpha}\downarrow 1}-iterate of Mα𝒯1{M^{\mathcal{T}}_{\alpha}\downarrow 1},

    Ult(Mα𝒯1,F(Mβ𝒯))=𝒩Mβ𝒰\mathrm{Ult}(M^{\mathcal{T}}_{\alpha}\downarrow 1,F(M^{\mathcal{T}}_{\beta}))=\mathcal{N}_{\infty}^{M^{\mathcal{U}^{\prime}}_{\beta}}

    and F(Mβ𝒯)F(M^{\mathcal{T}}_{\beta}) is the extender of the ΣMα𝒯1\Sigma_{M^{\mathcal{T}}_{\alpha}\downarrow 1}-iteration map.

Therefore if 𝒯,𝒰\mathcal{T},\mathcal{U} each have successor length, then M𝒯^𝒰M^{\mathcal{T}\ \widehat{\ }\ \mathcal{U}}_{\infty} is good with respect to extenders indexed γ1M𝒯^𝒰\leq\gamma_{1}^{M^{\mathcal{T}\ \widehat{\ }\ \mathcal{U}}_{\infty}} (or all extenders in 𝔼+(M𝒯^𝒰)\mathbb{E}_{+}(M^{\mathcal{T}\ \widehat{\ }\ \mathcal{U}}_{\infty}), if b𝒯^𝒰b^{\mathcal{T}\ \widehat{\ }\ \mathcal{U}} drops).

Proof.

The (last) “therefore” clause is because Σ𝒱1\Sigma_{\mathscr{V}_{1}} is good. The rest of the proof is like for Lemma 4.12.4 (although we did not yet prove that Ψ𝒱2,𝒱2\Psi_{\mathscr{V}_{2},\mathscr{V}_{2}^{-}} is good, Lemma 5.6.3(iii) does give the instance of this with respect to F𝒱||γ1𝒱F^{\mathscr{V}||\gamma_{1}^{\mathscr{V}}}, where 𝒱=Mα𝒯\mathscr{V}=M^{\mathcal{T}}_{\alpha}, which is enough to prove part 8 as in Lemma 4.12.4). ∎

We now prove a couple of variants of the branch condensation lemma 3 for trees on 𝒱1\mathscr{V}_{1}:

Lemma 5.31.

Let 𝒯,𝒰\mathcal{T},\mathcal{U} be short-normal on 𝒱1\mathscr{V}_{1}, via Σ𝒱1\Sigma_{\mathscr{V}_{1}}, based on 𝒱1|δ1𝒱1\mathscr{V}_{1}|\delta_{1}^{\mathscr{V}_{1}}, with 𝒯\mathcal{T} of limit length, 𝒰\mathcal{U} successor length with b𝒰b^{\mathcal{U}} non-dropping and δ(𝒰)=δ1M𝒰\delta(\mathcal{U})=\delta_{1}^{M^{\mathcal{U}}_{\infty}}. Let GG be VV-generic. Let b,kV[G]b,k\in V[G] where bb is a non-dropping 𝒯\mathcal{T}-cofinal branch with ib𝒯(δ1𝒱1)=δ(𝒯)i^{\mathcal{T}}_{b}(\delta_{1}^{\mathscr{V}_{1}})=\delta(\mathcal{T}) and and

k:Mb𝒯|δ1Mb𝒯M𝒰|δ1M𝒰k:M^{\mathcal{T}}_{b}|\delta_{1}^{M^{\mathcal{T}}_{b}}\to M^{\mathcal{U}}_{\infty}|\delta_{1}^{M^{\mathcal{U}}_{\infty}}

is elementary with kib𝒯=i0𝒰(𝒱1|δ1𝒱1)k\circ i^{\mathcal{T}}_{b}=i^{\mathcal{U}}_{0\infty}{\upharpoonright}(\mathscr{V}_{1}|\delta_{1}^{\mathscr{V}_{1}}). Then b=Σ𝒱1(𝒯)b=\Sigma_{\mathscr{V}_{1}}(\mathcal{T}).

Proof.

We may assume b,kVb,k\in V. Let 𝒱=Mb𝒯\mathscr{V}=M^{\mathcal{T}}_{b}. Let αb\alpha\in b be least with either α+1=lh(𝒯)\alpha+1={\rm lh}(\mathcal{T}) or δ0Mα𝒯<crit(iαb𝒯)\delta_{0}^{M^{\mathcal{T}}_{\alpha}}<{\rm crit}(i^{\mathcal{T}}_{\alpha b}). So 𝒱¯=Mα𝒯\bar{\mathscr{V}}=M^{\mathcal{T}}_{\alpha} is δ0𝒱¯\delta_{0}^{\bar{\mathscr{V}}}-sound and 𝒯[α,)\mathcal{T}{\upharpoonright}[\alpha,\infty) is on 𝒱¯\bar{\mathscr{V}}, above δ0𝒱¯\delta_{0}^{\bar{\mathscr{V}}}. Let βb𝒰\beta\in b^{\mathcal{U}} be analogous for 𝒰\mathcal{U}.

Define π:𝒱M𝒰\pi:\mathscr{V}\to M^{\mathcal{U}}_{\infty} in the natural way, extending kk, like in Lemma 3. Also define k¯:𝒱¯Mβ𝒰\bar{k}:\bar{\mathscr{V}}\to M^{\mathcal{U}}_{\beta} analogously. So k¯δ0𝒱k\bar{k}{\upharpoonright}\delta_{0}^{\mathscr{V}}\subseteq k.

The phalanx 𝔓=((𝒱¯,δ0𝒱¯),𝒱,δ(𝒯))\mathfrak{P}=((\bar{\mathscr{V}},\delta_{0}^{\bar{\mathscr{V}}}),\mathscr{V},\delta(\mathcal{T})) is iterable, via lifting trees with (k¯,k)(\bar{k},k).

Let c=Σ𝒱1(𝒯)c=\Sigma_{\mathscr{V}_{1}}(\mathcal{T}) and Qc=Q(𝒯,c)Q_{c}=Q(\mathcal{T},c) be the Q-structure, or Qc=Mc𝒯Q_{c}=M^{\mathcal{T}}_{c} if ic𝒯(δ1𝒱1)=δ(𝒯)i^{\mathcal{T}}_{c}(\delta_{1}^{\mathscr{V}_{1}})=\delta(\mathcal{T}). Let 𝔔\mathfrak{Q} be the phalanx ((𝒱¯,δ0𝒱¯),Qc,δ(𝒯))((\bar{\mathscr{V}},\delta_{0}^{\bar{\mathscr{V}}}),Q_{c},\delta(\mathcal{T})), which is also iterable.

Let 𝒱¯+\bar{\mathscr{V}}^{+} be a generic expansion of Mα𝒯M^{\mathcal{T}}_{\alpha} (so 𝒱¯+\bar{\mathscr{V}}^{+} is an MswswM_{\mathrm{swsw}}-like premouse and 𝒱¯=𝒱1𝒱¯+\bar{\mathscr{V}}=\mathscr{V}_{1}^{\bar{\mathscr{V}}^{+}}). Then 𝒯[α,)\mathcal{T}{\upharpoonright}[\alpha,\infty) can be translated to a tree 𝒯+\mathcal{T}^{+} on 𝒱¯+\bar{\mathscr{V}}^{+}, which is above κ0+𝒱¯+\kappa_{0}^{+\bar{\mathscr{V}}^{+}}. Let 𝒱+=Mb𝒯+\mathscr{V}^{+}=M^{\mathcal{T}^{+}}_{b} and Qc+=Q(𝒯+,c)Q_{c}^{+}=Q(\mathcal{T}^{+},c) or Qc+=Mc𝒯+Q_{c}^{+}=M^{\mathcal{T}^{+}}_{c} accordingly. Then the phalanxes

𝔓+=((𝒱¯+,κ0𝒱¯++1),𝒱+,δ(𝒯)) and 𝔔+=((𝒱¯+,κ0𝒱¯++1),Qc+,δ(𝒯))\mathfrak{P}^{+}=((\bar{\mathscr{V}}^{+},\kappa_{0}^{\bar{\mathscr{V}}^{+}}+1),\mathscr{V}^{+},\delta(\mathcal{T}))\text{ and }\mathfrak{Q}^{+}=((\bar{\mathscr{V}}^{+},\kappa_{0}^{\bar{\mathscr{V}}^{+}}+1),Q_{c}^{+},\delta(\mathcal{T}))

are iterable, since trees on them translate to trees on 𝔓,𝔔\mathfrak{P},\mathfrak{Q}. Note that 𝒱¯+\bar{\mathscr{V}}^{+} is κ0𝒱¯+\kappa_{0}^{\bar{\mathscr{V}}^{+}}-sound, and 𝒱+,Qc+\mathscr{V}^{+},Q^{+}_{c} are δ(𝒯)\delta(\mathcal{T})-sound. But then comparing 𝔓+\mathfrak{P}^{+} versus 𝔔+\mathfrak{Q}^{+} gives b=cb=c. ∎

Lemma 5.31.

Let 𝒯,𝒰\mathcal{T},\mathcal{U} be short-normal dsr trees on 𝒱1\mathscr{V}_{1}, via Σ𝒱1\Sigma_{\mathscr{V}_{1}}, based on 𝒱1|δ1𝒱1\mathscr{V}_{1}|\delta_{1}^{\mathscr{V}_{1}}, with 𝒯,𝒰\mathcal{T},\mathcal{U} of limit length. Suppose there is α<lh(𝒯)\alpha<{\rm lh}(\mathcal{T}) such that [0,α]𝒯[0,\alpha]_{\mathcal{T}} does not drop and 𝒯[α,)\mathcal{T}{\upharpoonright}[\alpha,\infty) is above δ0Mα𝒯\delta_{0}^{M^{\mathcal{T}}_{\alpha}}, and there is an analogous such β<lh(𝒰)\beta<{\rm lh}(\mathcal{U}); fix the least such α,β\alpha,\beta. Let c=Σ𝒱1(𝒰)c=\Sigma_{\mathscr{V}_{1}}(\mathcal{U}). Suppose that if cc is non-dropping then δ(𝒰)<δ1Mc𝒰\delta(\mathcal{U})<\delta_{1}^{M^{\mathcal{U}}_{c}}. Let GG be VV-generic. Let bV[G]b\in V[G] where bb is a 𝒯\mathcal{T}-cofinal branch such that if bb is non-dropping then δ(𝒯)<δ1Mb𝒯\delta(\mathcal{T})<\delta_{1}^{M^{\mathcal{T}}_{b}}. Let kV[G]k\in V[G] be such that

k:Q(𝒯,b)Q(𝒰,c)k:Q(\mathcal{T},b)\to Q(\mathcal{U},c)

is elementary and kib𝒯(𝒱1|δ0𝒱1)=ic𝒰(𝒱1|δ0𝒱1)k\circ i^{\mathcal{T}}_{b}{\upharpoonright}(\mathscr{V}_{1}|\delta_{0}^{\mathscr{V}_{1}})=i^{\mathcal{U}}_{c}{\upharpoonright}(\mathscr{V}_{1}|\delta_{0}^{\mathscr{V}_{1}}). Then b=Σ𝒱1(𝒯)b=\Sigma_{\mathscr{V}_{1}}(\mathcal{T}).

Proof.

This is via a straightforward variant of the proof of Lemma 5.6.4, noting that because 𝒯\mathcal{T} is dsr, Q(𝒯,b)Q(\mathcal{T},b) can only overlap δ(𝒯)\delta(\mathcal{T}) with long extenders. ∎

It turns out that the method we used to define Ψ𝒱1sn\Psi_{\mathscr{V}_{1}}^{\mathrm{sn}} is not so well suited to 𝒱2\mathscr{V}_{2}. Instead we proceed as follows:

Definition 5.32.

Ψ𝒱2sn\Psi_{\mathscr{V}_{2}}^{\mathrm{sn}} denotes the (putative) short-normal strategy Ψ\Psi for 𝒱2\mathscr{V}_{2}, defined as follows. Firstly, Ψ𝒱2,γ1𝒱2Ψ\Psi_{\mathscr{V}_{2},\gamma_{1}^{\mathscr{V}_{2}}}\subseteq\Psi. Secondly, let 𝒯\mathcal{T} be via Ψ𝒱2,𝒱2\Psi_{\mathscr{V}_{2},\mathscr{V}_{2}^{-}}, of successor length, such that b𝒯b^{\mathcal{T}} does not drop, and 𝒱=M𝒯\mathscr{V}=M^{\mathcal{T}}_{\infty}. We define the action of Ψ\Psi on above-γ1𝒱\gamma_{1}^{\mathscr{V}} trees on 𝒱\mathscr{V}.

Let 𝒫=𝒱1=i𝒱2𝒱(𝒩)\mathcal{P}=\mathscr{V}\downarrow 1=i_{\mathscr{V}_{2}\mathscr{V}}(\mathcal{N}_{\infty}), so (by Lemma 5.6.3) 𝒫\mathcal{P} is a Σ𝒩\Sigma_{\mathcal{N}_{\infty}}-iterate of 𝒩\mathcal{N}_{\infty} and 𝒫𝒱\mathcal{P}\subseteq\mathscr{V}. Let e=F𝒱||γ1𝒱e=F^{\mathscr{V}||\gamma_{1}^{\mathscr{V}}}. Let (and by Lemma 5.3)

ie𝒱:𝒱Ult(𝒱,e)=𝒱2𝒫i_{e}^{\mathscr{V}}:\mathscr{V}\to\mathrm{Ult}(\mathscr{V},e)=\mathscr{V}_{2}^{\mathcal{P}}

be the ultrapower map. Let Λ\Lambda be the above-γ1𝒱2𝒫\gamma_{1}^{\mathscr{V}_{2}^{\mathcal{P}}} strategy for 𝒱2𝒫\mathscr{V}_{2}^{\mathcal{P}} determined by translating above-κ1+𝒫\kappa_{1}^{+\mathcal{P}} (hence 1-translatable) trees on 𝒫\mathcal{P} via Σ𝒫\Sigma_{\mathcal{P}}. Then for above-γ1𝒱\gamma_{1}^{\mathscr{V}} trees 𝒰\mathcal{U} on 𝒱\mathscr{V}, 𝒯^𝒰\mathcal{T}\ \widehat{\ }\ \mathcal{U} is via Ψ\Psi iff 𝒰\mathcal{U} is via the minimal ie𝒱i^{\mathscr{V}}_{e}-pullback of Γ\Gamma.

Lemma 5.32.

Ψ𝒱2sn\Psi_{\mathscr{V}_{2}}^{\mathrm{sn}} is good.

Proof.

Clearly Ψ𝒱2sn\Psi_{\mathscr{V}_{2}}^{\mathrm{sn}} is well-defined and yields wellfounded models. So let 𝒯^𝒰\mathcal{T}\ \widehat{\ }\ \mathcal{U} be via Ψ𝒱2sn\Psi_{\mathscr{V}_{2}}^{\mathrm{sn}}, as in Definition 5.32, and 𝒱\mathscr{V}, 𝒫\mathcal{P}, ee, ie=ie𝒱i_{e}=i^{\mathscr{V}}_{e} be as there. Let ie𝒰i_{e}``\mathcal{U} be the minimal ie=ie𝒱i_{e}=i^{\mathscr{V}}_{e}-copy of 𝒰\mathcal{U} to a tree on 𝒱2𝒫\mathscr{V}_{2}^{\mathcal{P}}. Let 𝒲=M𝒯^𝒰\mathscr{W}=M^{\mathcal{T}\ \widehat{\ }\ \mathcal{U}}_{\infty} and γ1𝒲αOR𝒲\gamma_{1}^{\mathscr{W}}\leq\alpha\leq\mathrm{OR}^{\mathscr{W}} be such that 𝒲||α\mathscr{W}||\alpha is active with an ii-long extender. Let 𝒲=Ult0(𝒲||α,e)\mathscr{W}^{\prime}=\mathrm{Ult}_{0}(\mathscr{W}||\alpha,e). By Lemma 5.6.1, 𝒲Mie𝒰\mathscr{W}^{\prime}\trianglelefteq M^{i_{e}``\mathcal{U}}_{\infty}.

Now F𝒲F^{\mathscr{W}^{\prime}} is a correct iteration extender (via Σ𝒩𝒫\Sigma_{\mathcal{N}_{\infty}^{\mathcal{P}}}) based on 𝒩𝒫|δi𝒩𝒫\mathcal{N}_{\infty}^{\mathcal{P}}|\delta_{i}^{\mathcal{N}_{\infty}^{\mathcal{P}}}. For let 𝒰+{\mathcal{U}^{\prime}}^{+} be the translation of ie𝒰i_{e}``\mathcal{U} to a tree on 𝒫\mathcal{P}, and 𝒲+=M𝒰+||OR𝒲{\mathscr{W}^{\prime}}^{+}=M^{{\mathcal{U}^{\prime}}^{+}}_{\infty}||\mathrm{OR}^{\mathscr{W}^{\prime}}. If i=1i=1 (so crit(F𝒲+)=κ1𝒫{\rm crit}(F^{{\mathscr{W}^{\prime}}^{+}})=\kappa_{1}^{\mathcal{P}}) the correctness of F𝒲F^{\mathscr{W}^{\prime}} is by Lemma 5.4 part 6 applied to 𝒫\mathcal{P} and 𝒫=Ult(𝒫,F𝒲+)\mathcal{P}^{\prime}=\mathrm{Ult}(\mathcal{P},F^{{\mathscr{W}^{\prime}}^{+}}) and i𝒫𝒫i_{\mathcal{P}\mathcal{P}^{\prime}}. If i=0i=0 (so F𝒲+F^{{\mathscr{W}^{\prime}}^{+}} is long) it is because Σ𝒱1\Sigma_{\mathscr{V}_{1}} is good (so F𝒲+F^{{\mathscr{W}^{\prime}}^{+}} is correct) and how 𝒱2𝒫\mathscr{V}_{2}^{\mathcal{P}} is defined.

Let 𝒮\mathcal{S} be the limit length tree leading from 𝒫|δi𝒫\mathcal{P}|\delta_{i}^{\mathcal{P}} to i𝒲||α\mathcal{M}_{i\infty}^{\mathscr{W}||\alpha}, and 𝒮\mathcal{S}^{\prime} likewise, so 𝒮=j(𝒮)\mathcal{S}^{\prime}=j(\mathcal{S}) where j=ie𝒲||α,0j=i_{e}^{\mathscr{W}||\alpha,0} is the ultrapower map. Let \mathcal{R} be the successor length tree leading from 𝒫|δi𝒫\mathcal{P}|\delta_{i}^{\mathcal{P}} to 𝒩𝒫|δi𝒫\mathcal{N}_{\infty}^{\mathcal{P}}|\delta_{i}^{\mathcal{P}} (given by e(𝒫|δi𝒫)e{\upharpoonright}(\mathcal{P}|\delta_{i}^{\mathcal{P}})). We know that 𝒮\mathcal{S}^{\prime} is via the short tree strategy for 𝒩𝒫|δi𝒩𝒫\mathcal{N}_{\infty}^{\mathcal{P}}|\delta_{i}^{\mathcal{N}_{\infty}^{\mathcal{P}}}, and F𝒲F^{\mathscr{W}^{\prime}} yields the branch Σ𝒩𝒫(𝒮)\Sigma_{\mathcal{N}_{\infty}^{\mathcal{P}}}(\mathcal{S}^{\prime}). We claim the same holds for 𝒮\mathcal{S} and F𝒲||αF^{\mathscr{W}||\alpha}; that is, 𝒮\mathcal{S} is via the δi\delta_{i}-short tree strategy for 𝒫i\mathcal{P}\downarrow i, and F𝒲||αF^{\mathscr{W}||\alpha} yields b=Σ𝒫(𝒮)b=\Sigma_{\mathcal{P}}(\mathcal{S}).

For if i=0i=0, the Q-structure used in 𝒮\mathcal{S} for the limit stage 𝒮η\mathcal{S}{\upharpoonright}\eta does not overlap δ(𝒮η)\delta(\mathcal{S}{\upharpoonright}\eta), and is embedded by jj into an iterable Q-structure used in 𝒮\mathcal{S}^{\prime}. And if i=1i=1, it is likewise through the 0-lower component of 𝒮\mathcal{S} (until reaching δ0M(𝒮)\delta_{0}^{M(\mathcal{S})}), and above there, Lemma 5.6.4 applies to the normalizations of (𝒯,𝒮η)(\mathcal{T},\mathcal{S}{\upharpoonright}\eta) and (𝒯,,j(𝒮η))(\mathcal{T},\mathcal{R},j(\mathcal{S}{\upharpoonright}\eta)), using a restriction of jj as the map kk. (Here 𝒯\mathcal{T} and 𝒯^\mathcal{T}\ \widehat{\ }\ \mathcal{R} can be δ1\delta_{1}-maximal, but one should literally apply Lemma 5.6.4 to the short-normal trees 𝒯\mathcal{T}^{\prime} on 𝒱1\mathscr{V}_{1}, iterating to M(𝒮η)M(\mathcal{S}{\upharpoonright}\eta), and 𝒰\mathcal{U}^{\prime} on 𝒱1\mathscr{V}_{1}, iterating to M(j(𝒮η))M(j(\mathcal{S}{\upharpoonright}\eta))).

Finally let bb be the 𝒮\mathcal{S}-cofinal branch determined by F𝒲||αF^{\mathscr{W}||\alpha} and bb^{\prime} that determined by F𝒲F^{\mathscr{W}^{\prime}}. Then we can apply Lemma 5.6.4 to (𝒮,b)(\mathcal{S},b) and the stack (,(𝒮,b))(\mathcal{R},(\mathcal{S}^{\prime},b^{\prime})), using k=j(M(𝒮))k=j{\upharpoonright}(M(\mathcal{S})). Therefore bb is correct. ∎

5.6.5 Normal trees on 𝒱2\mathscr{V}_{2}

Much like in Definition 4.29, it is now easy to see:

Lemma 5.32.

There is a unique 0-maximal strategy Σ\Sigma for 𝒱2\mathscr{V}_{2} such that Ψ𝒱2snΣ\Psi_{\mathscr{V}_{2}}^{\mathrm{sn}}\subseteq\Sigma. We write Σ𝒱2=Σ\Sigma_{\mathscr{V}_{2}}=\Sigma. Every iterate of 𝒱2\mathscr{V}_{2} via Σ𝒱2\Sigma_{\mathscr{V}_{2}} is a short-normal iterate of 𝒱2\mathscr{V}_{2} via Ψ𝒱2sn\Psi_{\mathscr{V}_{2}}^{\mathrm{sn}}, and hence Σ𝒱2\Sigma_{\mathscr{V}_{2}} is good.

Remark 5.32.

Consider a 0-maximal tree 𝒯\mathcal{T} on 𝒱2\mathscr{V}_{2} and some limit λ<lh(𝒯)\lambda<{\rm lh}(\mathcal{T}) such that 𝒯\mathcal{T} uses 11-long extenders cofinally below λ\lambda. Then δ(𝒯)\delta(\mathcal{T}) is the least measurable of Mλ𝒯M^{\mathcal{T}}_{\lambda}, and in particular δ(𝒯)<δ0Mλ𝒯\delta(\mathcal{T})<\delta_{0}^{M^{\mathcal{T}}_{\lambda}}. Suppose Eλ𝒯E^{\mathcal{T}}_{\lambda} is short with crit(Eλ𝒯)<δ1Mλ𝒯{\rm crit}(E^{\mathcal{T}}_{\lambda})<\delta_{1}^{M^{\mathcal{T}}_{\lambda}} and total over Mλ𝒯M^{\mathcal{T}}_{\lambda}, or Eλ𝒯E^{\mathcal{T}}_{\lambda} is 0-long. Then pred𝒯(λ+1)=λ\mathrm{pred}^{\mathcal{T}}(\lambda+1)=\lambda and Mλ+1𝒯=Ult(Mλ𝒯,Eλ𝒯)M^{\mathcal{T}}_{\lambda+1}=\mathrm{Ult}(M^{\mathcal{T}}_{\lambda},E^{\mathcal{T}}_{\lambda}), and note that the short-normal tree 𝒰\mathcal{U} via Ψ𝒱2sn\Psi^{\mathrm{sn}}_{\mathscr{V}_{2}} has δ(𝒰)>lh(Eλ𝒯)\delta(\mathcal{U})>{\rm lh}(E^{\mathcal{T}}_{\lambda}). This could be unnatural; letting 𝒰λ\mathcal{U}_{\lambda} be the short-normal tree with last model Mλ𝒯M^{\mathcal{T}}_{\lambda}, it might be better to define 0-maximality by taking β<lh(𝒰λ)\beta<{\rm lh}(\mathcal{U}_{\lambda}) least such that Eλ𝒯𝔼+Mβ𝒰λE^{\mathcal{T}}_{\lambda}\in\mathbb{E}_{+}^{M^{\mathcal{U}_{\lambda}}_{\beta}}, and defining Mλ+1𝒯M^{\mathcal{T}}_{\lambda+1} to be the model produce by normally extending 𝒰λ(β+1)\mathcal{U}_{\lambda}{\upharpoonright}(\beta+1) with Eλ𝒯E^{\mathcal{T}}_{\lambda}. However, for our purposes here, the more naive notion of 0-maximality suffices.

Lemma 5.32.

Let 𝒱¯\bar{\mathscr{V}} be a non-dropping Ψ𝒱2,𝒱2\Psi_{\mathscr{V}_{2},\mathscr{V}_{2}^{-}}-iterate of 𝒱2\mathscr{V}_{2}, and 𝒱\mathscr{V} a non-dropping Ψ𝒱¯,𝒱¯\Psi_{\bar{\mathscr{V}},\bar{\mathscr{V}}^{-}}-iterate of 𝒱¯\bar{\mathscr{V}}^{-}. Let π:𝒱¯𝒱\pi:\bar{\mathscr{V}}\to\mathscr{V} be the iteration map. Let Ψ¯\bar{\Psi} be the above-δ1𝒱¯\delta_{1}^{\bar{\mathscr{V}}} short-normal strategy for 𝒱¯\bar{\mathscr{V}} given by Σ𝒱2\Sigma_{\mathscr{V}_{2}}, and Ψ\Psi likewise for 𝒱\mathscr{V}. Then Ψ¯\bar{\Psi} is the minimal π\pi-pullback of Ψ\Psi (see [15, ***10.3, 10.4]).

Proof.

Let 𝒯1\mathcal{T}_{1} on 𝒱¯\bar{\mathscr{V}} be via the π\pi-pullback of Ψ\Psi; we want to see that 𝒯1\mathcal{T}_{1} is via Ψ¯\bar{\Psi}. Let 𝒳1=π𝒯1\mathcal{X}_{1}=\pi``\mathcal{T}_{1}, which is via Ψ\Psi. Let π=π(𝒱¯1)\pi^{\prime}=\pi{\upharpoonright}(\bar{\mathscr{V}}\downarrow 1). So π=i𝒱¯1,𝒱1\pi^{\prime}=i_{\bar{\mathscr{V}}\downarrow 1,\mathscr{V}\downarrow 1}, also an iteration map.

If lh(E0𝒯1¯)<γ1𝒱¯{\rm lh}(E^{\bar{\mathcal{T}_{1}}}_{0})<\gamma_{1}^{\bar{\mathscr{V}}} then the desired conclusion follows from the fact that Σ𝒩\Sigma_{\mathcal{N}_{\infty}} has mic. So suppose otherwise.

Let j¯:𝒱¯Ult(𝒱¯,e1𝒱¯)\bar{j}:\bar{\mathscr{V}}\to\mathrm{Ult}(\bar{\mathscr{V}},e_{1}^{\bar{\mathscr{V}}}) and j:𝒱Ult(𝒱,e1𝒱)j:\mathscr{V}\to\mathrm{Ult}(\mathscr{V},e_{1}^{\mathscr{V}}) be the ultrapower maps, and recall Ult(𝒱,e𝒱1)=𝒱2𝒱1\mathrm{Ult}(\mathscr{V},e^{\mathscr{V}_{1}})=\mathscr{V}_{2}^{\mathscr{V}\downarrow 1} and likewise for 𝒱¯\bar{\mathscr{V}}. So the minimal jj-copy j𝒳1j``\mathcal{X}_{1} of 𝒳1\mathcal{X}_{1}, on 𝒱2𝒱1\mathscr{V}_{2}^{\mathscr{V}\downarrow 1}, translates to a tree 𝒳1\mathcal{X}_{1}^{\prime} on 𝒱1\mathscr{V}\downarrow 1 which is via Σ𝒱1\Sigma_{\mathscr{V}\downarrow 1} (and above γ1𝒱=κ1+𝒱1\gamma_{1}^{\mathscr{V}}=\kappa_{1}^{+\mathscr{V}\downarrow 1}). We need to see that the minimal j¯\bar{j}-copy of 𝒯1\mathcal{T}_{1} translates to a tree 𝒯1\mathcal{T}_{1}^{\prime} on 𝒱¯1\bar{\mathscr{V}}\downarrow 1 via Σ𝒱¯1\Sigma_{\bar{\mathscr{V}}\downarrow 1}. Since Σ𝒱¯1\Sigma_{\bar{\mathscr{V}}\downarrow 1} has mic (Lemma 4.12.5 and [15, ***Theorem 10.2]) and by [15, ***10.3, 10.4], it therefore suffices to see that that 𝒳1=π𝒯1\mathcal{X}_{1}^{\prime}=\pi^{\prime}``\mathcal{T}_{1}^{\prime}.

Let σ=π(𝒱¯|γ1𝒱¯)\sigma^{\prime}=\pi^{\prime}{\upharpoonright}(\bar{\mathscr{V}}|\gamma_{1}^{\bar{\mathscr{V}}}) and

σ=σ(𝒱2𝒱¯1|δ1𝒱2𝒱¯1)=πUlt(𝒱¯|δ1𝒱¯,e1𝒱¯).\sigma=\sigma^{\prime}{\upharpoonright}(\mathscr{V}_{2}^{\bar{\mathscr{V}}\downarrow 1}|\delta_{1}^{\mathscr{V}_{2}^{\bar{\mathscr{V}}\downarrow 1}})=\pi{\upharpoonright}\mathrm{Ult}(\bar{\mathscr{V}}|\delta_{1}^{\bar{\mathscr{V}}},e_{1}^{\bar{\mathscr{V}}}).

We have

Ult(𝒱¯1,σ)=Ult(𝒱¯1,σδ1𝒱¯)=𝒱1\mathrm{Ult}(\bar{\mathscr{V}}\downarrow 1,\sigma^{\prime})=\mathrm{Ult}(\bar{\mathscr{V}}\downarrow 1,\sigma^{\prime}{\upharpoonright}\delta_{1}^{\bar{\mathscr{V}}})=\mathscr{V}\downarrow 1

and the associated ultrapower map is just π(𝒱¯1)\pi{\upharpoonright}(\bar{\mathscr{V}}\downarrow 1). Given the fine structural correspondence between 𝒱2𝒱¯1\mathscr{V}_{2}^{\bar{\mathscr{V}}\downarrow 1} and 𝒱¯1\bar{\mathscr{V}}\downarrow 1, therefore

Ult(𝒱2𝒱¯1,σ)=𝒱2𝒱1\mathrm{Ult}(\mathscr{V}_{2}^{\bar{\mathscr{V}}\downarrow 1},\sigma)=\mathscr{V}_{2}^{\mathscr{V}\downarrow 1}

and the σ\sigma-ultrapower map 𝒱2𝒱¯1𝒱2𝒱1\mathscr{V}_{2}^{\bar{\mathscr{V}}\downarrow 1}\to\mathscr{V}_{2}^{\mathscr{V}\downarrow 1} is just π𝒱2𝒱¯1\pi{\upharpoonright}\mathscr{V}_{2}^{\bar{\mathscr{V}}\downarrow 1}. Although σ\sigma is not the restriction of an iteration map on 𝒱2𝒱¯1\mathscr{V}_{2}^{\bar{\mathscr{V}}\downarrow 1}, it is straightforward to see we still have 𝒳1~=σ𝒯1~\widetilde{\mathcal{X}_{1}}=\sigma``\widetilde{\mathcal{T}_{1}} (that is, 𝒳1~\widetilde{\mathcal{X}_{1}} is the minimal σ\sigma-copy of 𝒯1~\widetilde{\mathcal{T}_{1}}), meaning that:

  1. 𝒳1~\widetilde{\mathcal{X}_{1}} has the same tree, drop and degree structure as has 𝒯1~\widetilde{\mathcal{T}_{1}},

  2. for each α+1<lh(𝒯1~)\alpha+1<{\rm lh}(\widetilde{\mathcal{T}_{1}}), we have Mα𝒳1~||lh(Eα𝒳1~)=Ult0(Mα𝒯1~||lh(Eα𝒯1~),σ)M^{\widetilde{\mathcal{X}_{1}}}_{\alpha}||{\rm lh}(E^{\widetilde{\mathcal{X}_{1}}}_{\alpha})=\mathrm{Ult}_{0}(M^{\widetilde{\mathcal{T}_{1}}}_{\alpha}||{\rm lh}(E^{\widetilde{\mathcal{T}_{1}}}_{\alpha}),\sigma),

  3. for each α<lh(𝒯1~)\alpha<{\rm lh}(\widetilde{\mathcal{T}_{1}}), if d=degα𝒯1d=\deg^{\mathcal{T}_{1}}_{\alpha} then Mα𝒳1~=Ultd(Mα𝒯1~,σ)M^{\widetilde{\mathcal{X}_{1}}}_{\alpha}=\mathrm{Ult}_{d}(M^{\widetilde{\mathcal{T}_{1}}}_{\alpha},\sigma), and if α\alpha is a successor then Mα𝒳1~=Ultd(Mα𝒯1~,σ)M^{*\widetilde{\mathcal{X}_{1}}}_{\alpha}=\mathrm{Ult}_{d}(M^{*\widetilde{\mathcal{T}_{1}}}_{\alpha},\sigma), and

  4. the resulting ultrapower maps Mα𝒯1~Mα𝒳1~M^{\widetilde{\mathcal{T}_{1}}}_{\alpha}\to M^{\widetilde{\mathcal{X}_{1}}}_{\alpha} and Mα𝒯1~Mα𝒳1~M^{*\widetilde{\mathcal{T}_{1}}}_{\alpha}\to M^{*\widetilde{\mathcal{X}_{1}}}_{\alpha} (via σ\sigma) commute with the iteration maps of 𝒯1~\widetilde{\mathcal{T}_{1}} and 𝒳1~\widetilde{\mathcal{X}_{1}}.

These are just standard properties of minimal copying, so we already know the corresponding properties hold with respect to (π,𝒯1,𝒳1)(\pi,\mathcal{T}_{1},\mathcal{X}_{1}), (j¯,𝒯1,𝒯1~)(\bar{j},\mathcal{T}_{1},\widetilde{\mathcal{T}_{1}}), and (j,𝒳1,𝒳1~)(j,\mathcal{X}_{1},\widetilde{\mathcal{X}_{1}}). One can now deduce them for (σ,𝒯1~,𝒳1~)(\sigma,\widetilde{\mathcal{T}_{1}},\widetilde{\mathcal{X}_{1}}) with some commutativity, and in particular that

jπ(𝒱¯|δ1𝒱¯)=π(𝒱2𝒱¯1)j¯.j\circ\pi{\upharpoonright}(\bar{\mathscr{V}}|\delta_{1}^{\bar{\mathscr{V}}})=\pi{\upharpoonright}(\mathscr{V}_{2}^{\bar{\mathscr{V}}\downarrow 1})\circ\bar{j}.

But then because 𝒯1,𝒳1\mathcal{T}_{1}^{\prime},\mathcal{X}_{1}^{\prime} are translations of 𝒯1~,𝒳1~\widetilde{\mathcal{T}_{1}},\widetilde{\mathcal{X}_{1}}, and given the fine structural correspondence between 𝒱¯1\bar{\mathscr{V}}\downarrow 1 and 𝒱2𝒱¯1\mathscr{V}_{2}^{\bar{\mathscr{V}}\downarrow 1}, and likewise between 𝒱1\mathscr{V}\downarrow 1 and 𝒱2𝒱1\mathscr{V}_{2}^{\mathscr{V}\downarrow 1}, it follows that 𝒳1=π𝒯1\mathcal{X}_{1}^{\prime}=\pi^{\prime}``\mathcal{T}_{1}^{\prime}, as desired. ∎

Lemma 5.32.

Σ𝒱2\Sigma_{\mathscr{V}_{2}} has minimal inflation condensation (mic).

Proof.

We just discuss short-normal trees. Let 𝒯=𝒯0^𝒯1\mathcal{T}=\mathcal{T}_{0}\ \widehat{\ }\ \mathcal{T}_{1} and 𝒳=𝒳0^𝒳1\mathcal{X}=\mathcal{X}_{0}\ \widehat{\ }\ \mathcal{X}_{1} be as before, but with respect to 𝒱2\mathscr{V}_{2} and Σ𝒱2\Sigma_{\mathscr{V}_{2}}; in particular we have

𝒯0^𝒯1min𝒳0^(𝒳1λ),\mathcal{T}_{0}\ \widehat{\ }\ \mathcal{T}_{1}\rightsquigarrow_{\min}\mathcal{X}_{0}\ \widehat{\ }\ (\mathcal{X}_{1}{\upharpoonright}\lambda),

where λ\lambda is a limit ordinal and λ+1=lh(𝒳1)\lambda+1={\rm lh}(\mathcal{X}_{1}). We must show that 𝒳\mathcal{X} is a minimal inflation of 𝒯\mathcal{T}. Now Ψ𝒱2,𝒱2\Psi_{\mathscr{V}_{2},\mathscr{V}_{2}^{-}} has mic, since Σ𝒱1\Sigma_{\mathscr{V}_{1}} does, by Lemma 4.12.5 and [15, ***Theorem 10.2]. So we may assume 𝒯1\mathcal{T}_{1}\neq\emptyset, so we get α,β,Π0,π\alpha,\beta,\Pi_{0},\pi like before, with analogous properties (with δ1\delta_{1} replacing δ0\delta_{0}). Let η<lh(𝒯1)\eta<{\rm lh}(\mathcal{T}_{1}) be the limit ordinal and cc the 𝒯1η\mathcal{T}_{1}{\upharpoonright}\eta-cofinal branch and

Π:𝒯0^(𝒯1η)^cmin𝒳\Pi:\mathcal{T}_{0}\ \widehat{\ }\ (\mathcal{T}_{1}{\upharpoonright}\eta)\ \widehat{\ }\ c\hookrightarrow_{\min}\mathcal{X}

the minimal tree embedding determined by extending the inflation 𝒯min𝒳0^(𝒳1λ)\mathcal{T}\rightsquigarrow_{\min}\mathcal{X}_{0}\ \widehat{\ }\ (\mathcal{X}_{1}{\upharpoonright}\lambda) to 𝒳\mathcal{X} in the unique possible way. We want c=[0,η)𝒯1c=[0,\eta)_{\mathcal{T}_{1}}.

Let 𝒱¯=Mα𝒯0\bar{\mathscr{V}}=M^{\mathcal{T}_{0}}_{\alpha}, 𝒱=Mβ𝒳0\mathscr{V}=M^{\mathcal{X}_{0}}_{\beta} and j¯:𝒱¯Ult(𝒱¯,e1𝒱¯)\bar{j}:\bar{\mathscr{V}}\to\mathrm{Ult}(\bar{\mathscr{V}},e_{1}^{\bar{\mathscr{V}}}) and j:𝒱Ult(𝒱,e1𝒱)j:\mathscr{V}\to\mathrm{Ult}(\mathscr{V},e_{1}^{\mathscr{V}}) be the ultrapower maps, and recall Ult(𝒱,e𝒱1)=𝒱2𝒱1\mathrm{Ult}(\mathscr{V},e^{\mathscr{V}_{1}})=\mathscr{V}_{2}^{\mathscr{V}\downarrow 1} and likewise for 𝒱¯\bar{\mathscr{V}}. So the minimal jj-copy j𝒳1j``\mathcal{X}_{1} of 𝒳1\mathcal{X}_{1}, on 𝒱2𝒱1\mathscr{V}_{2}^{\mathscr{V}\downarrow 1}, translates to a tree 𝒳1\mathcal{X}_{1}^{\prime} on 𝒱1\mathscr{V}\downarrow 1 which is via Σ𝒱1\Sigma_{\mathscr{V}\downarrow 1} and is above κ1+(𝒱1)\kappa_{1}^{+(\mathscr{V}\downarrow 1)}. Likewise, 𝒯1\mathcal{T}_{1} translates to a tree 𝒯1\mathcal{T}_{1}^{\prime} on 𝒱¯1\bar{\mathscr{V}}\downarrow 1 via Σ𝒱¯1\Sigma_{\bar{\mathscr{V}}\downarrow 1} which is above κ1+(𝒱¯1)\kappa_{1}^{+(\bar{\mathscr{V}}\downarrow 1)}.

Let 𝒯1^=π𝒯1\widehat{\mathcal{T}_{1}}=\pi``\mathcal{T}_{1}. By Lemma 5.6.5, 𝒳0^𝒯1^\mathcal{X}_{0}\ \widehat{\ }\ \widehat{\mathcal{T}_{1}} is via Σ𝒱2\Sigma_{\mathscr{V}_{2}}. Lifting with π\pi, it is easy to see that

𝒳0^𝒯1^min𝒳0^(𝒳1λ)\mathcal{X}_{0}\ \widehat{\ }\ \widehat{\mathcal{T}_{1}}\rightsquigarrow_{\min}\mathcal{X}_{0}\ \widehat{\ }\ (\mathcal{X}_{1}{\upharpoonright}\lambda)

and that it suffices to see that

𝒳0^𝒯1^min𝒳0^𝒳1\mathcal{X}_{0}\ \widehat{\ }\ \widehat{\mathcal{T}_{1}}\rightsquigarrow_{\min}\mathcal{X}_{0}\ \widehat{\ }\ \mathcal{X}_{1}

(see [15, ***Theorem 10.7] for details; there is a straightforward correspondence between these inflations and those for 𝒯0^𝒯1\mathcal{T}_{0}\ \widehat{\ }\ \mathcal{T}_{1}).

So relabelling, we may assume 𝒯0=𝒳0\mathcal{T}_{0}=\mathcal{X}_{0} and Π𝒯0=id\Pi{\upharpoonright}\mathcal{T}_{0}=\mathrm{id}, so 𝒱¯=𝒱\bar{\mathscr{V}}=\mathscr{V} and π=id\pi=\mathrm{id} and j=j¯j=\bar{j}. Let 𝒯0~=𝒳0~\widetilde{\mathcal{T}_{0}}=\widetilde{\mathcal{X}_{0}} be the short-normal tree leading from 𝒱2\mathscr{V}_{2} to Ult(𝒱,e1𝒱)\mathrm{Ult}(\mathscr{V},e_{1}^{\mathscr{V}}). Then

𝒯0~^j¯𝒯1min𝒳0~^(j𝒳1λ),\widetilde{\mathcal{T}_{0}}\ \widehat{\ }\ \bar{j}``\mathcal{T}_{1}\rightsquigarrow_{\min}\widetilde{\mathcal{X}_{0}}\ \widehat{\ }\ (j``\mathcal{X}_{1}{\upharpoonright}\lambda),

as can be seen by lifting all relevant structures up by the extender e𝒱¯1=e𝒱1e^{\bar{\mathscr{V}}_{1}}=e^{\mathscr{V}_{1}} with the relevant degree ultrapowers. Letting 𝒯0=𝒳0\mathcal{T}_{0}^{\prime}=\mathcal{X}_{0}^{\prime} be 𝒯0=𝒳0\mathcal{T}_{0}=\mathcal{X}_{0} but as a tree on 𝒩\mathcal{N}_{\infty} (and recall 𝒯1,𝒳1\mathcal{T}_{1}^{\prime},\mathcal{X}_{1}^{\prime} were introduced above), it follows that

𝒯0^𝒯1min𝒳0^(𝒳1λ).\mathcal{T}_{0}^{\prime}\ \widehat{\ }\ \mathcal{T}_{1}^{\prime}\rightsquigarrow_{\min}\mathcal{X}_{0}^{\prime}\ \widehat{\ }\ (\mathcal{X}_{1}^{\prime}{\upharpoonright}\lambda).

Since Σ𝒩\Sigma_{\mathcal{N}_{\infty}} has mic, therefore

𝒯0^𝒯1min𝒳0^𝒳1.\mathcal{T}_{0}^{\prime}\ \widehat{\ }\ \mathcal{T}_{1}^{\prime}\rightsquigarrow_{\min}\mathcal{X}_{0}^{\prime}\ \widehat{\ }\ \mathcal{X}_{1}^{\prime}.

But the ultimate minimal tree embedding Π\Pi^{\prime} determined by this inflation is induced naturally by Π\Pi above, and in particular c=[0,η)𝒯1c=[0,\eta)_{\mathcal{T}_{1}^{\prime}}, so c=[0,η)𝒯1c=[0,\eta)_{\mathcal{T}_{1}}, as desired. ∎

5.7 Self-iterability of 𝒱2\mathscr{V}_{2}

Lemma 5.32.

𝒱2\mathscr{V}_{2} is definable over its universe from the parameter 𝒩|κ1𝒩\mathcal{N}_{\infty}|\kappa_{1}^{\mathcal{N}_{\infty}}.

Proof.

This is an essentially direct adaptation of the proof of Lemma 5.1.3, but using Lemma 5.1.3 at the point that Remark 3 was used there. ∎

Note that in Theorem 5.8, we will improve the lemma above, showing that, in fact, 𝒱2\mathscr{V}_{2} is definable without any parameters over its universe. But just using Lemma 5.7 and adapting Lemma 5.1.3, we have:

Lemma 5.32.

Let 𝒱\mathscr{V} be a non-dropping Σ𝒱2\Sigma_{\mathscr{V}_{2}}-iterate of 𝒱2\mathscr{V}_{2}. Let λOR\lambda\in\mathrm{OR} with λδ1𝒱2\lambda\geq\delta_{1}^{\mathscr{V}_{2}} and 𝒱|λ+𝒱\mathbb{P}\in\mathscr{V}|\lambda^{+\mathscr{V}} and gg be (𝒱,)(\mathcal{V},\mathbb{P})-generic. Then 𝒱\mathscr{V} is definable over the universe of 𝒱[g]\mathscr{V}[g] from the parameter x=𝒱|λ+𝒱x=\mathscr{V}|\lambda^{+\mathscr{V}}.

We will now state a key fact on the self-iterability of 𝒱2\mathscr{V}_{2} (and more). As usual, we will give the proof in a special case which illustrates the main new features, but the full proof will be handled by [13], as it involves *-translation:

Theorem 5.32.

Let GλG\subseteq\lambda be set generic over 𝒱2\mathscr{V}_{2}, where λδ1𝒱2\lambda\geq\delta_{1}^{\mathscr{V}_{2}}. Let x=𝒱2|λ+𝒱2x=\mathscr{V}_{2}|\lambda^{+\mathscr{V}_{2}}. Then:

  1. 1.

    𝒱2\mathscr{V}_{2} is closed under Σ𝒱2\Sigma_{\mathscr{V}_{2}} and Σ𝒱2𝒱2\Sigma_{\mathscr{V}_{2}}{\upharpoonright}\mathscr{V}_{2} is lightface definable over 𝒱2\mathscr{V}_{2}.

  2. 2.

    𝒱2[G]\mathscr{V}_{2}[G] is closed under Σ𝒱2\Sigma_{\mathscr{V}_{2}} and Σ𝒱2(𝒱2[G])\Sigma_{\mathscr{V}_{2}}{\upharpoonright}(\mathscr{V}_{2}[G]) is definable over the universe of 𝒱2[G]\mathscr{V}_{2}[G] from the parameter xx, uniformly in xx.

  3. 3.

    𝒱2\mathscr{V}_{2} is closed under Σ𝒩\Sigma_{\mathcal{N}_{\infty}} and Σ𝒩𝒱2\Sigma_{\mathcal{N}_{\infty}}{\upharpoonright}\mathscr{V}_{2} is lightface definable over 𝒱2\mathscr{V}_{2}. (Recall that 𝒩=𝒱21\mathcal{N}_{\infty}=\mathscr{V}_{2}\downarrow 1 is a Σ𝒱1\Sigma_{\mathscr{V}_{1}}-iterate of 𝒱1\mathscr{V}_{1}.)

  4. 4.

    𝒱2[G]\mathscr{V}_{2}[G] is closed under Σ𝒩\Sigma_{\mathcal{N}_{\infty}} and Σ𝒩(𝒱2[G])\Sigma_{\mathcal{N}_{\infty}}{\upharpoonright}(\mathscr{V}_{2}[G]) is definable over the universe of 𝒱2[G]\mathscr{V}_{2}[G] from the parameter xx, uniformly in xx.

In order to prove the theorem, we again use modified P-constructions (in general, incorporating *-translation), in the context of the following notions of P-suitability. The full proof will rely on *-translation, and so will be given in [13]. Here we will restrict our attention to dsr (defined in this context below) trees only, for illustration purposes (but the notion of P-suitability below does not have such a restriction). We restrict to trees in 𝒱2\mathscr{V}_{2} (as opposed to 𝒱2[G]\mathscr{V}_{2}[G]), as this simplifies things, and we can reduce other trees to this case.

Definition 5.33.

Let 𝒯𝒱2\mathcal{T}\in\mathscr{V}_{2} be an iteration tree on 𝒱2\mathscr{V}_{2}. Say that 𝒯\mathcal{T} is P-suitable for 𝒱2\mathscr{V}_{2} iff there are 𝒯0,𝒯1,𝒯2,E,F,𝒱,η,δ,ι\mathcal{T}_{0},\mathcal{T}_{1},\mathcal{T}_{2},E,F,\mathscr{V},\eta,\delta,\iota such that:

  1. 1.

    𝒯=𝒯0^𝒯1^𝒯2\mathcal{T}=\mathcal{T}_{0}\ \widehat{\ }\ \mathcal{T}_{1}\ \widehat{\ }\ \mathcal{T}_{2} is short-normal on 𝒱2\mathscr{V}_{2}, according to Σ𝒱2\Sigma_{\mathscr{V}_{2}}, with 0-lower and 11-lower components 𝒯0,𝒯1\mathcal{T}_{0},\mathcal{T}_{1} and upper component 𝒯2\mathcal{T}_{2}\neq\emptyset,

  2. 2.

    E,F𝔼𝒱2E,F\in\mathbb{E}^{\mathscr{V}_{2}} are 𝒱2\mathscr{V}_{2}-total and 11-long,

  3. 3.

    𝒯0^𝒯1\mathcal{T}_{0}\ \widehat{\ }\ \mathcal{T}_{1} is the successor-length tree on 𝒱2\mathscr{V}_{2} induced by EE,

  4. 4.

    𝒱=M𝒯0^𝒯1=Ult(𝒱2,E)\mathscr{V}=M^{\mathcal{T}_{0}\ \widehat{\ }\ \mathcal{T}_{1}}_{\infty}=\mathrm{Ult}(\mathscr{V}_{2},E),

  5. 5.

    δ1𝒱=lh(E)<λ++𝒱2<ι=lgcd(𝒱2|lh(F))<lh(F)\delta_{1}^{\mathscr{V}}={\rm lh}(E)<\lambda^{++\mathscr{V}_{2}}<\iota=\mathrm{lgcd}(\mathscr{V}_{2}|{\rm lh}(F))<{\rm lh}(F),

  6. 6.

    𝒯2𝒱2|ι\mathcal{T}_{2}\in\mathscr{V}_{2}|\iota; note 𝒯2\mathcal{T}_{2} is on 𝒱\mathscr{V} and is above δ1𝒱\delta_{1}^{\mathscr{V}},

  7. 7.

    η\eta is a strong {δ0𝒱2,δ1𝒱2}\{\delta_{0}^{\mathscr{V}_{2}},\delta_{1}^{\mathscr{V}_{2}}\}-cutpoint of 𝒱2\mathscr{V}_{2},

  8. 8.

    𝒯2\mathcal{T}_{2} has limit length, λ++𝒱2η<δ=δ(𝒯2)<ι\lambda^{++\mathscr{V}_{2}}\leq\eta<\delta=\delta(\mathcal{T}_{2})<\iota, η\eta is the largest cardinal of 𝒱2|δ\mathscr{V}_{2}|\delta, 𝒯2\mathcal{T}_{2} is definable from parameters over 𝒱2|δ\mathscr{V}_{2}|\delta, and 𝒱2|δ\mathscr{V}_{2}|\delta is generic over M(𝒯2)M(\mathcal{T}_{2}) for the above-ξ\xi extender algebra of M(𝒯2)M(\mathcal{T}_{2}) at δ\delta, for some ξ<δ\xi<\delta.

Now let 𝒯𝒱2\mathcal{T}\in\mathscr{V}_{2} be a tree on 𝒩=𝒱21\mathcal{N}_{\infty}=\mathscr{V}_{2}\downarrow 1. Say that 𝒯\mathcal{T} is P-suitable for 𝒱2\mathscr{V}_{2} iff the conditions above hold, except that 𝒯\mathcal{T} is short-normal on 𝒩\mathcal{N}_{\infty}, according to Σ𝒩\Sigma_{\mathcal{N}_{\infty}}, 𝒯0\mathcal{T}_{0} is the lower component of 𝒯\mathcal{T}, 𝒯1\mathcal{T}_{1} is based on M𝒯0|δ1M𝒯0M^{\mathcal{T}_{0}}_{\infty}|\delta_{1}^{M^{\mathcal{T}_{0}}_{\infty}} and is above δ0M𝒯0\delta_{0}^{M^{\mathcal{T}_{0}}_{\infty}}, 𝒯0^𝒯1\mathcal{T}_{0}\ \widehat{\ }\ \mathcal{T}_{1} has successor length and does not drop, and 𝒯2\mathcal{T}_{2} is on 𝒩=M𝒯1\mathcal{N}=M^{\mathcal{T}_{1}}_{\infty} and is above δ1𝒩\delta_{1}^{\mathcal{N}} (so 𝒩=Ult(𝒩,E)\mathcal{N}=\mathrm{Ult}(\mathcal{N}_{\infty},E), and note that 𝒯0^𝒯1\mathcal{T}_{0}\ \widehat{\ }\ \mathcal{T}_{1} can also be considered as a tree on 𝒱2\mathscr{V}_{2}, with properties as above).

The corresponding P-constructions are as follows; no proper class models show up, because we are now working up above the real Woodin cardinals. We must now restrict our attention to dsr trees (as defined immediately below).

Definition 5.34.

Let 𝒱2\mathbb{P}\in\mathscr{V}_{2} and δ1𝒱2λOR\delta_{1}^{\mathscr{V}_{2}}\leq\lambda\in\mathrm{OR} with λ\mathbb{P}\subseteq\lambda, and GG be (𝒱2,)(\mathscr{V}_{2},\mathbb{P})-generic.

Let 𝒯𝒱2\mathcal{T}\in\mathscr{V}_{2}, on either 𝒱2\mathscr{V}_{2} or 𝒩\mathcal{N}_{\infty}, be P-suitable for 𝒱2\mathscr{V}_{2}, and adopt notation as in Definition 5.33. Say that 𝒯\mathcal{T} is dsr iff M(𝒯)M(\mathcal{T}) has only 2 Woodin cardinals.

Suppose that 𝒯\mathcal{T} is dsr, but M(𝒯)M(\mathcal{T}) is not a Q-structure for itself. Then the P-construction 𝒫𝒱2|ι(M(𝒯))\mathscr{P}^{\mathscr{V}_{2}|\iota}(M(\mathcal{T})) of 𝒱2|ι\mathscr{V}_{2}|\iota over M(𝒯)M(\mathcal{T}) (recalling that ι\iota is the largest cardinal of 𝒱2|lh(F)\mathscr{V}_{2}|{\rm lh}(F)) is defined like the P-constructions used to compute the δ1\delta_{1}-short tree strategy for 𝒱1\mathscr{V}_{1}, noting that the iteration map j:𝒱2|δ0𝒱2M𝒯0|δ0M𝒯0j:\mathscr{V}_{2}|\delta_{0}^{\mathscr{V}_{2}}\to M^{\mathcal{T}_{0}}_{\infty}|\delta_{0}^{M^{\mathcal{T}_{0}}_{\infty}}, which is determined by EE, is in 𝒱2|η\mathscr{V}_{2}|\eta (and note that there are no 1-long extenders in 𝔼𝒱2[δ,ι]\mathbb{E}^{\mathscr{V}_{2}}{\upharpoonright}[\delta,\iota]).

Lemma 5.34.

Let 𝒯\mathcal{T} be dsr P-suitable for 𝒱2\mathscr{V}_{2}, on either 𝒱2\mathscr{V}_{2} or 𝒩\mathcal{N}_{\infty}. Suppose M(𝒯)M(\mathcal{T}) is not a Q-structure for itself. Then the P-construction 𝒫𝒱2|ι(M(𝒯))\mathscr{P}^{\mathscr{V}_{2}|\iota}(M(\mathcal{T})) reaches the Q-structure Q(𝒯,b)Q(\mathcal{T},b), where b=Σ𝒱2(𝒯)b=\Sigma_{\mathscr{V}_{2}}(\mathcal{T}) or b=Σ𝒩(𝒯)b=\Sigma_{\mathcal{N}_{\infty}}(\mathcal{T}).

Proof.

We first consider P-suitable trees 𝒯\mathcal{T} on 𝒩\mathcal{N}_{\infty} in 𝒱2\mathscr{V}_{2}. So adopt the notation of Definition 5.33 for this, with 𝒩=Ult(𝒩,E)\mathcal{N}=\mathrm{Ult}(\mathcal{N}_{\infty},E). Because 𝒯2\mathcal{T}_{2} is above δ1𝒩\delta_{1}^{\mathcal{N}}, the Q-structure Q=Q(𝒯2,b)Q=Q(\mathcal{T}_{2},b) exists, where b=Σ𝒩(𝒯)b=\Sigma_{\mathcal{N}_{\infty}}(\mathcal{T}). Suppose QM(𝒯2)Q\neq M(\mathcal{T}_{2}). We want to see that the P-construction reaches QQ. To verify this, we run a comparison analogous some earlier in the paper, modulo the generic at δ\delta, and after appropriate translation of long extenders. We need to specify the phalanxes we compare.

On the P-construction side, we just have MM.

On the Q-structure side, we proceed as follows. Let 𝒩¯\bar{\mathcal{N}} be the δ0𝒩\delta_{0}^{\mathcal{N}}-core of 𝒩\mathcal{N} (this is not M𝒯0M^{\mathcal{T}_{0}}_{\infty}, as 𝒩\mathcal{N}_{\infty} itself is not δ0𝒩\delta_{0}^{\mathcal{N}_{\infty}}-sound). Note that δ0𝒩¯=δ0𝒩\delta_{0}^{\bar{\mathcal{N}}}=\delta_{0}^{\mathcal{N}} and 𝒩¯\bar{\mathcal{N}} is δ0𝒩¯\delta_{0}^{\bar{\mathcal{N}}}-sound. Let 𝒩¯+\bar{\mathcal{N}}^{+} be a generic expansion of 𝒩¯\bar{\mathcal{N}} (to a premouse), via a filter which is MM-generic (for the same forcing 𝕃𝒩¯\mathbb{L}^{\bar{\mathcal{N}}}. So 𝒩¯=𝒱1𝒩¯+\bar{\mathcal{N}}=\mathscr{V}_{1}^{\bar{\mathcal{N}}^{+}}. Then 𝒯1^𝒯2\mathcal{T}_{1}\ \widehat{\ }\ \mathcal{T}_{2} translates to a tree 𝒯1+^𝒯2+\mathcal{T}_{1}^{+}\ \widehat{\ }\ \mathcal{T}_{2}^{+} on 𝒩¯+\bar{\mathcal{N}}^{+} which is above κ0+𝒩¯+=δ0𝒩¯\kappa_{0}^{+\bar{\mathcal{N}}^{+}}=\delta_{0}^{\bar{\mathcal{N}}}. Let Q+=Q(𝒯2+,b)Q^{+}=Q(\mathcal{T}_{2}^{+},b). Define the phalanx

𝔔+=((𝒩¯+,κ0N¯+1),Q+,δ).\mathfrak{Q}^{+}=((\bar{\mathcal{N}}^{+},\kappa_{0}^{\bar{N}}+1),Q^{+},\delta).

Note that 𝔔+\mathfrak{Q}^{+} is iterable, as it corresponds to iterating the phalanx

𝔔=((𝒩¯,δ0𝒩¯),Q,δ).\mathfrak{Q}=((\bar{\mathcal{N}},\delta_{0}^{\bar{\mathcal{N}}}),Q,\delta).

(Note here that the only extenders overlapping δ\delta in 𝔼+Q\mathbb{E}_{+}^{Q} are long, since 𝒯\mathcal{T} is dsr.)

We now compare 𝔔+\mathfrak{Q}^{+} with MM, above δ\delta, modulo the generic at δ\delta, translating extenders with critical point κ0𝒩¯+\kappa_{0}^{\bar{\mathcal{N}}^{+}} on the 𝔔+\mathfrak{Q}^{+} side, and those with critical point κ0M\kappa_{0}^{M} on the MM side, much as before. Much like in the proof of Lemma 5.1.2, and using the κ0𝒩¯+\kappa_{0}^{\bar{\mathcal{N}}^{+}}-soundness of 𝒩¯+\bar{\mathcal{N}}^{+} (which is by Lemma 5.1.2), the comparison is trivial, so the P-construction reaches QQ, as desired. Regarding the equivalence modulo the generic at δ\delta, although 𝒱2|δ\mathscr{V}_{2}|\delta is extender algebra generic over QQ, (for an extender algebra 𝔹\mathbb{B} at δ\delta, above some ξ\xi), it doesn’t seem immediate that it is also generic for the corresponding extender algebra of Q+Q^{+} (although the extenders correspond, it seems there might still be further axioms in Q+Q^{+} which cause problems). However, this is not a problem. Note that

𝒫(<δ)(Q[𝒱2|δ])=𝒫(<δ)(M(𝒯)[𝒱2|δ])=𝒫(<δ)(𝒱2|δ).\mathcal{P}({<\delta})\cap(Q[\mathscr{V}_{2}|\delta])=\mathcal{P}({<\delta})\cap(M(\mathcal{T})[\mathscr{V}_{2}|\delta])=\mathcal{P}({<\delta})\cap(\mathscr{V}_{2}|\delta).

We can force over Q[𝒱2|δ]Q[\mathscr{V}_{2}|\delta] with 𝕃=𝕃𝒱2𝕃𝒱1˙𝒱2|δ\mathbb{L}^{\prime}=\mathbb{L}^{\mathscr{V}_{2}}*\dot{\mathbb{L}^{\mathscr{V}_{1}}}\in\mathscr{V}_{2}|\delta, adding (𝒱1|κ1𝒱1,M|κ0M)(\mathscr{V}_{1}|\kappa_{1}^{\mathscr{V}_{1}},M|\kappa_{0}^{M}), which results in Q[M|δ]Q[M|\delta], and similarly

𝒫(<δ)(Q[M|δ])=𝒫(<δ)(M(𝒯)[M|δ])=𝒫(<δ)(M|δ).\mathcal{P}({<\delta})\cap(Q[M|\delta])=\mathcal{P}({<\delta})\cap(M(\mathcal{T})[M|\delta])=\mathcal{P}({<\delta})\cap(M|\delta).

Since 𝒩¯+|κ0𝒩¯+\bar{\mathcal{N}}^{+}|\kappa_{0}^{\bar{\mathcal{N}}^{+}} was taken MM-generic for 𝕃𝒩¯M(𝒯)\mathbb{L}^{\bar{\mathcal{N}}}\in M(\mathcal{T}), we can therefore force further with 𝕃𝒩¯\mathbb{L}^{\bar{\mathcal{N}}} to reach Q[M|δ,𝒩¯+|κ0𝒩¯+]Q[M|\delta,\bar{\mathcal{N}}^{+}|\kappa_{0}^{\bar{\mathcal{N}}^{+}}], which computes Q+Q^{+}. But the product (𝔹𝕃˙)×𝕃𝒩¯(\mathbb{B}*\dot{\mathbb{L}^{\prime}})\times\mathbb{L}^{\bar{\mathcal{N}}} can be reversed, and so M|δM|\delta is also Q+Q^{+}-generic for 𝔹𝕃˙\mathbb{B}*\dot{\mathbb{L}^{\prime}}. Moreover, 𝔹\mathbb{B} is definable from parameters over M(𝒯+)=Q+|δM(\mathcal{T}^{+})=Q^{+}|\delta. The same holds for all models that appear above 𝔔+\mathfrak{Q}^{+} in the comparison. This gives the usual fine structural correspondence between models above 𝔔+\mathfrak{Q}^{+} and their generic extensions given by adjoining M|δM|\delta. On the MM-side, the extension to M[𝒩¯+|κ0𝒩¯+]M[\bar{\mathcal{N}}^{+}|\kappa_{0}^{\bar{\mathcal{N}}^{+}}] is via 𝕃𝒩¯\mathbb{L}^{\bar{\mathcal{N}}}, which is small relative to δ\delta in MM. Likewise for all models on the MM-side of the comparison. So we also get the appropriate fine structural correspondence on the MM-side.

Now consider trees 𝒯\mathcal{T} on 𝒱2\mathscr{V}_{2}; we adopt the relevant notation from Definition 5.33. If lh(E0𝒯2)<γ1𝒱{\rm lh}(E^{\mathcal{T}_{2}}_{0})<\gamma_{1}^{\mathscr{V}}, then since ρ1𝒱||γ1𝒱=δ1𝒱\rho_{1}^{\mathscr{V}||\gamma_{1}^{\mathscr{V}}}=\delta_{1}^{\mathscr{V}}, 𝒯2\mathcal{T}_{2} immediately drops in model to 𝒱||γ1𝒱\mathscr{V}||\gamma_{1}^{\mathscr{V}}, and this cannot be undone (since 𝒯2\mathcal{T}_{2} is short-normal). Since 𝒱|γ1𝒱=𝒩||κ1+𝒩\mathscr{V}|\gamma_{1}^{\mathscr{V}}=\mathcal{N}||\kappa_{1}^{+\mathcal{N}}, where 𝒩\mathcal{N} is as in the previous case, with corresponding iteration strategy for such trees, everything in this situation is as above. So suppose γ1𝒱<lh(E0𝒯2)\gamma_{1}^{\mathscr{V}}<{\rm lh}(E^{\mathcal{T}_{2}}_{0}). Let E+𝔼ME^{+}\in\mathbb{E}^{M} with lh(E+)=lh(E){\rm lh}(E^{+})={\rm lh}(E). Let R=Ult(M,E+)R=\mathrm{Ult}(M,E^{+}). Then 𝒱=𝒱2R\mathscr{V}=\mathscr{V}_{2}^{R} and (since γ1𝒱<lh(E0𝒯2)\gamma_{1}^{\mathscr{V}}<{\rm lh}(E^{\mathcal{T}_{2}}_{0})), 𝒯2\mathcal{T}_{2} translates to a tree 𝒯2+\mathcal{T}_{2}^{+} on RR, which is above κ1+R\kappa_{1}^{+R}. Let Q+=Q(𝒯2+,b)Q^{+}=Q(\mathcal{T}_{2}^{+},b). It is straightforward to see that Q=Q(𝒯2,b)Q=Q(\mathcal{T}_{2},b) has no 11-long extenders overlapping δ\delta (recall that QM(𝒯2)Q\neq M(\mathcal{T}_{2}), and use the smallness of MM), so Q+Q^{+} can only have extenders overlapping δ\delta with critical point κ0\kappa_{0}. Define the phalanx

𝔔=((M,κ0+1),Q+,δ).\mathfrak{Q}=((M,\kappa_{0}+1),Q^{+},\delta).

Clearly 𝔔\mathfrak{Q} is iterable. We compare 𝔔\mathfrak{Q} versus MM, again above δ\delta etc, like before. This time the equivalence modulo the generic is a little different, because R|κ1+RR|\kappa_{1}^{+R} is not MM-generic, but instead is in MM. However, over QQ, we adjoin 𝒱2|δ\mathscr{V}_{2}|\delta with the extender algebra, then adjoin M|κ1+MM|\kappa_{1}^{+M}, reaching Q[M|δ]Q[M|\delta]. Like in the previous case, this two-step forcing iteration is definable from parameters over Q|δQ|\delta and the Woodinness of δ\delta ensures genericity. But R|κ1+RM|δR|\kappa_{1}^{+R}\in M|\delta, so Q+Q^{+} is (simply) definable from parameters over Q[M|δ]Q[M|\delta], and Q+Q^{+} (simply) defines QQ from parameters. This (together with exactly how these definitions are made and the parameters used) is enough for the fine structural analysis of the comparison. ∎

Without discussing *-translation, we are limited to sketching the proof of that 𝒱2\mathscr{V}_{2} can iterate itself and 𝒩\mathcal{N}_{\infty}:

Sketch of proof for Theorem 5.7.

Lemma 5.4 handles trees based on 𝒩|δ1𝒩=𝒱2|δ1𝒱2\mathcal{N}_{\infty}|\delta_{1}^{\mathcal{N}_{\infty}}=\mathscr{V}_{2}|\delta_{1}^{\mathscr{V}_{2}}.

So consider dsr trees 𝒰=𝒰0^𝒰1^𝒰2\mathcal{U}=\mathcal{U}_{0}\ \widehat{\ }\ \mathcal{U}_{1}\ \widehat{\ }\ \mathcal{U}_{2}, with lower component 𝒰0\mathcal{U}_{0}, 𝒰1\mathcal{U}_{1} on M𝒰0M^{\mathcal{U}_{0}}_{\infty}, based on M𝒰0M^{\mathcal{U}_{0}}_{\infty}, and above δ0M𝒰0\delta_{0}^{M^{\mathcal{U}_{0}}_{\infty}}, b𝒰0^𝒰1b^{\mathcal{U}_{0}\ \widehat{\ }\ \mathcal{U}_{1}} non-dropping, and 𝒰2\mathcal{U}_{2} on M𝒰0^𝒰1M^{\mathcal{U}_{0}\ \widehat{\ }\ \mathcal{U}_{1}}_{\infty}, above δ1M𝒰0^𝒰1\delta_{1}^{M^{\mathcal{U}_{0}\ \widehat{\ }\ \mathcal{U}_{1}}_{\infty}}. Let E𝔼𝒱2E\in\mathbb{E}^{\mathscr{V}_{2}} be such that EE is 11-long and λ+𝒱2<ι=lgcd(𝒱2|lh(E))\lambda^{+\mathscr{V}_{2}}<\iota=\mathrm{lgcd}(\mathscr{V}_{2}|{\rm lh}(E)) and 𝒰0^𝒰1𝒱2|ι\mathcal{U}_{0}\ \widehat{\ }\ \mathcal{U}_{1}\in\mathscr{V}_{2}|\iota. Then letting 𝒯0^𝒯1\mathcal{T}_{0}\ \widehat{\ }\ \mathcal{T}_{1} on 𝒩\mathcal{N}_{\infty} result from EE, 𝒩=M𝒯0^𝒯1=𝒱1Ult(𝒱2,E)\mathcal{N}=M^{\mathcal{T}_{0}\ \widehat{\ }\ \mathcal{T}_{1}}_{\infty}=\mathscr{V}_{1}^{\mathrm{Ult}(\mathscr{V}_{2},E)} is a correct iterate of M𝒰0^𝒰1M^{\mathcal{U}_{0}\ \widehat{\ }\ \mathcal{U}_{1}}_{\infty}, and 𝒱2\mathscr{V}_{2} knows the iteration map jj. So given that 𝒱2\mathscr{V}_{2} computes the restriction of Σ𝒩\Sigma_{\mathcal{N}} to above-δ1𝒩\delta_{1}^{\mathcal{N}} trees correctly, it can use jj to form minimal copies of trees 𝒰2\mathcal{U}_{2} (of the form above) to correct trees 𝒯2\mathcal{T}_{2}, and then 𝒰2\mathcal{U}_{2} is correct, because Σ𝒱1\Sigma_{\mathscr{V}_{1}} has minimal inflation condensation (Lemma 4.12.5), and hence so does Σ𝒩\Sigma_{\mathcal{N}_{\infty}}, by [15, ***Theorem 10.2]. (Note also that dsr-ness is preserved by the copying.) Finally, arbitrary (dsr) trees 𝒯2\mathcal{T}_{2} can be reduced to P-suitable trees by the usual minimal genericity inflation technique.

By [13], the foregoing generalizes to arbitrary (not just dsr) trees, so that Σ𝒩𝒱2\Sigma^{\mathscr{V}_{2}}_{\mathcal{N}_{\infty}} is definable over 𝒱2\mathscr{V}_{2}. Since Σ𝒩\Sigma_{\mathcal{N}_{\infty}} has minimal inflation condensation, 𝒱2\mathscr{V}_{2}\vDashΣ𝒩𝒱2\Sigma^{\mathscr{V}_{2}}_{\mathcal{N}_{\infty}} has minimal inflation condensation”.

Since the least 𝒱2\mathscr{V}_{2} indiscernible is countable in VV, and Σ𝒩\Sigma_{\mathcal{N}_{\infty}} has minimal inflation condensation in VV, by [15, ***Remark 9.2], Σ𝒩𝒱2\Sigma^{\mathscr{V}_{2}}_{\mathcal{N}_{\infty}} extends to canonically to set-generic extensions 𝒱2[G]\mathscr{V}_{2}[G] of 𝒱2\mathscr{V}_{2} (via the method in the proof of [15, ***Remark 9.2]), and letting Σ𝒩𝒱2[G]\Sigma^{\mathscr{V}_{2}[G]}_{\mathcal{N}_{\infty}} be the extension, every tree via Σ𝒩𝒱2[G]\Sigma^{\mathscr{V}_{2}[G]}_{\mathcal{N}_{\infty}} embeds via a minimal tree embedding arising from minimal inflation into some tree in 𝒱2\mathscr{V}_{2} via Σ𝒩𝒱2\Sigma^{\mathscr{V}_{2}}_{\mathcal{N}_{\infty}}, and therefore Σ𝒩𝒱2[G]\Sigma^{\mathscr{V}_{2}[G]}_{\mathcal{N}_{\infty}} also agrees with Σ𝒩V[G]\Sigma^{V[G]}_{\mathcal{N}_{\infty}} if GG is VV-generic. For the definability in 𝒱2[G]\mathscr{V}_{2}[G] from the parameter xx, use 5.7 to recover 𝒱2\mathscr{V}_{2}, from which we compute(d) the strategy.

For trees on 𝒱2\mathscr{V}_{2}, i.e. computing Σ𝒱2𝒱2\Sigma^{\mathscr{V}_{2}}_{\mathscr{V}_{2}} and Σ𝒱2𝒱2[G]\Sigma^{\mathscr{V}_{2}[G]}_{\mathscr{V}_{2}}, it is very similar, using Lemma 5.6.5. ∎

5.8 The mantle and eventual generic HOD of MM

In this section we prove the main facts regarding the eventual generic HOD\mathrm{HOD} and the mantle:

Theorem 5.34.

Let U2U_{2} be the universe of 𝒱2\mathscr{V}_{2}. Then:

  1. 1.

    U2=HODU2[G]U_{2}=\mathrm{HOD}^{U_{2}[G]} for all 𝒱2\mathscr{V}_{2}-generics GColl(ω,λ)G\subseteq\mathrm{Coll}(\omega,\lambda), for all λδ1𝒱2=κ1+M\lambda\geq\delta_{1}^{\mathscr{V}_{2}}=\kappa_{1}^{+M}, and likewise U2=HODM[H]U_{2}=\mathrm{HOD}^{M[H]} for all MM-generics HColl(ω,λ)H\subseteq\mathrm{Coll}(\omega,\lambda).

  2. 2.

    U2U_{2} has no proper ground, so U2U_{2} is the mantle and smallest ground of MM.

  3. 3.

    U2U_{2} is the mantle of all set generic extensions of MM.

  4. 4.

    𝒱2\mathscr{V}_{2} is definable without parameters over U2U_{2}, and in fact over any set-generic extension of U2U_{2}.

Proof.

Work in 𝒱2[G]\mathscr{V}_{2}[G] where GColl(ω,λ)G\subseteq\mathrm{Coll}(\omega,\lambda) is 𝒱2\mathscr{V}_{2}-generic and λδ1𝒱2\lambda\geq\delta_{1}^{\mathscr{V}_{2}}. Say that 𝒱\mathscr{V} is a λ\lambda-candidate iff 𝒱\mathscr{V} is a 𝒱2\mathscr{V}_{2}-like 2-Vsp and there is HColl(ω,λ)H\subseteq\mathrm{Coll}(\omega,\lambda) which is 𝒱\mathscr{V}-generic and 𝒱[H]=^𝒱2[G]\mathscr{V}[H]\ \widehat{=}\ \mathscr{V}_{2}[G].

Note that 𝒱\mathscr{V} is determined in 𝒱2[G]\mathscr{V}_{2}[G] by 𝒱¯=𝒱|λ+𝒱\bar{\mathscr{V}}=\mathscr{V}|\lambda^{+\mathscr{V}}, by Lemma 5.7, and moreover, by the uniformity of its proof, 𝒱¯𝒱\bar{\mathscr{V}}\mapsto\mathscr{V} is definable over (the universe of) 𝒱2[G]\mathscr{V}_{2}[G]. (We can recover the universe UU of 𝒱\mathscr{V} from 𝒱¯\bar{\mathscr{V}}, via (the proof of) Woodin-Laver, and we can recover 𝒱\mathscr{V} from 𝒱¯\bar{\mathscr{V}} and UU via (the proof of) Lemma 5.7.) So there are only set-many λ\lambda-candidates. Note that 𝒱2\mathscr{V}_{2} is a λ\lambda-candidate.

Recall here that 𝒱2\mathscr{V}_{2}-like is assumed to include whatever first-order facts satisfied by 𝒱2\mathscr{V}_{2} to make our arguments work. In particular, it should include the statement/proof of Lemma 5.7, and also the statements

  1. 𝒱\mathscr{V} is fully iterable in every set generic extension 𝒱[g]\mathscr{V}[g] of 𝒱\mathscr{V}, via the strategy Σ𝒱𝒱,g\Sigma^{\mathscr{V},g}_{\mathscr{V}} defined as in the proof of Theorem 5.7; and

  2. 𝒱1\mathscr{V}\downarrow 1 is fully iterable in every set generic extension 𝒱[g]\mathscr{V}[g] of 𝒱\mathscr{V}, via the strategy Σ𝒱1𝒱,g\Sigma^{\mathscr{V},g}_{\mathscr{V}\downarrow 1} defined as in the proof of Theorem 5.7.

Now using this iterability (which holds in 𝒱2[G]\mathscr{V}_{2}[G] with respect to each λ\lambda-candidate 𝒱\mathscr{V}), we want to define a kind of simultaneous “comparison” of all λ\lambda-candidates. For this, we will not directly attempt to compare the λ\lambda-candidates 𝒱\mathscr{V} themselves by least disagreement (due to familiar problems with showing that the comparison terminates), but, as we have done elsewhere in the paper, instead compare generic expansions of the 𝒱1\mathscr{V}\downarrow 1, and then use this to infer a comparison of the λ\lambda-candidates (and it doesn’t seem obvious that this comparison of λ\lambda-candidates is by least disagreement).

However, we only have iterability for the generic expansions NN above their κ0N\kappa_{0}^{N}, which isn’t enough to expect a standard comparison of these premice by least disagreement either (they need not agree below their κ0N\kappa_{0}^{N}, as this part is just generic). Instead, like in the proof of Lemma 4.12.4, we will first form a “mutual genericity iteration” at an appropriate Woodin cardinal, and after this converges, move to comparison “modulo a generic” above that point.

So, work in 𝒱2[G,G]\mathscr{V}_{2}[G,G^{\prime}], where GColl(ω,λ+𝒱2[G])G^{\prime}\subseteq\mathrm{Coll}(\omega,\lambda^{+\mathscr{V}_{2}[G]}) is 𝒱2[G]\mathscr{V}_{2}[G]-generic. Fix for each λ\lambda-candidate 𝒱\mathscr{V} a generic expansion P=P𝒱P=P_{\mathscr{V}} of 𝒱1\mathscr{V}\downarrow 1. So (𝒱11)P(\mathscr{V}_{1}\downarrow 1)\subseteq P and (𝒱11)=𝒱1P(\mathscr{V}_{1}\downarrow 1)=\mathscr{V}_{1}^{P}. (Moving to 𝒱2[G,G]\mathscr{V}_{2}[G,G^{\prime}] ensures these PPs exist.) Let ΣP\Sigma_{P} be the iteration strategy for PP for 0-maximal trees 𝒯\mathcal{T} with lh(E0𝒯)>κ0P{\rm lh}(E^{\mathcal{T}}_{0})>\kappa_{0}^{P} given by the proof of Lemma 4.12.4 (translating to trees via Σ𝒱𝒱2[G,G]\Sigma^{\mathscr{V}_{2}[G,G^{\prime}]}_{\mathscr{V}}, etc). Let DP𝔼PD^{P}\in\mathbb{E}^{P} be the least PP-total extender with crit(DP)=κ0P{\rm crit}(D^{P})=\kappa_{0}^{P}. Let δP\delta^{P} be the least Woodin cardinal of P|λ(DP)P|\lambda(D^{P}) such that δP>κ0P\delta^{P}>\kappa_{0}^{P} (so δP>κ0+P\delta^{P}>\kappa_{0}^{+P}).

Recall the meas-lim extender algebra (see [17]), used in the proof of Lemma 4.12.4. Write 𝔹P\mathbb{B}^{P} for the (meas-lim) extender algebra of P|lh(DP)P|{\rm lh}(D^{P}), at δP\delta^{P}, formed with extenders E𝔼PE\in\mathbb{E}^{P} such that crit(E)>κ0{\rm crit}(E)>\kappa_{0} and ν(E)\nu(E) is a limit of measurables of P|lh(DP)P|{\rm lh}(D^{P}), as witnessed by 𝔼P\mathbb{E}^{P}. We will now form a mutual genericity iteration of all PP as above, for the image of 𝔹P\mathbb{B}^{P}, producing padded trees 𝒯P\mathcal{T}_{P} on PP, above κ0+P\kappa_{0}^{+P}, based on P|δPP|\delta^{P} (and hence 𝒯P\mathcal{T}_{P} immediately drops in model to P|lh(DP)P|{\rm lh}(D^{P}), noting that ρ1P|lh(DP)=κ0+P\rho_{1}^{P|{\rm lh}(D^{P})}=\kappa_{0}^{+P}), inserting some linear iterations at successor measurables to space things conveniently. Let 𝒫\mathscr{P} be the set of all P𝒱P_{\mathscr{V}}, for λ\lambda-candidates 𝒱\mathscr{V} (where “λ\lambda-candidate” is still as computed in 𝒱[G]\mathscr{V}[G], but 𝒫𝒱[G,G]\mathscr{P}\subseteq\mathscr{V}[G,G^{\prime}]). Fix an enumeration Pββ\left<P_{\beta}\right>_{\beta} of 𝒫\mathscr{P}, and let CC be a set of ordinals coding Pβ|δPββ\left<P_{\beta}|\delta^{P_{\beta}}\right>_{\beta}. We define a sequence 𝒯αPαι\left<\mathcal{T}^{P}_{\alpha}\right>_{\alpha\leq\iota} of approximations to the final trees 𝒯P=𝒯ιP\mathcal{T}_{P}=\mathcal{T}^{P}_{\iota}. We start with 𝒯0P\mathcal{T}^{P}_{0} being the trivial tree on PP. Suppose we have defined 𝒯αP\mathcal{T}^{P}_{\alpha} for each P𝒫P\in\mathscr{P}. This will be a 0-maximal successor-length padded tree on PP, based on P|lh(DP)P|{\rm lh}(D^{P}), above κ0+P\kappa_{0}^{+P}. Let δα=supP𝒫δ(𝒯αP)\delta_{\alpha}=\sup_{P\in\mathscr{P}}\delta(\mathcal{T}^{P}_{\alpha}), where δ(𝒯)=supβ+1<lh(𝒯)lh(Eβ𝒯)\delta(\mathcal{T})=\sup_{\beta+1<{\rm lh}(\mathcal{T})}{\rm lh}(E^{\mathcal{T}}_{\beta}). If b𝒯αPb^{\mathcal{T}^{P}_{\alpha}} drops below the image of P|lh(DP)P|{\rm lh}(D^{P}) then let γαP=OR(M𝒯αP)\gamma^{P}_{\alpha}=\mathrm{OR}(M^{\mathcal{T}^{P}_{\alpha}}), and otherwise let γαP=j𝒯αP(δP)\gamma^{P}_{\alpha}=j^{\mathcal{T}^{P}_{\alpha}}(\delta^{P}), where j𝒯αP:P|lh(DP)M𝒯αPj^{\mathcal{T}^{P}_{\alpha}}:P|{\rm lh}(D^{P})\to M^{\mathcal{T}^{P}_{\alpha}}_{\infty} is the iteration map. Let KαP=M𝒯αP||γαPK^{P}_{\alpha}=M^{\mathcal{T}^{P}_{\alpha}}||\gamma^{P}_{\alpha}. Let Dα=(C,Cα)D_{\alpha}=(C,C_{\alpha}) where CαC_{\alpha} codes (KαPβ)pvβ\left<(K^{P_{\beta}}_{\alpha})^{\mathrm{pv}}\right>_{\beta} as

Cα={(β,γ)OR2|γ𝔼(KαPβ)}C_{\alpha}=\{(\beta,\gamma)\in\mathrm{OR}^{2}\bigm{|}\gamma\in\mathbb{E}(K^{P_{\beta}}_{\alpha})\}

(where 𝔼(KαPβ)\mathbb{E}(K^{P_{\beta}}_{\alpha}) is taken as a set of ordinals in a canonical fashion). Let GαPG^{P}_{\alpha} be the least E𝔼+(KαP)E\in\mathbb{E}_{+}(K^{P}_{\alpha}) such that EE is KαPK^{P}_{\alpha}-total and

  1. 1.

    E=F(KαP)E=F(K^{P}_{\alpha}), or

  2. 2.

    ν(E)\nu(E) is a limit of measurable cardinals of KαPK^{P}_{\alpha}, as witnessed by 𝔼KαP\mathbb{E}^{K^{P}_{\alpha}}, and Eν(E)E{\upharpoonright}\nu(E) induces an extender algebra axiom false of DαD_{\alpha}, or

  3. 3.

    crit(E)<sup(C){\rm crit}(E)<\sup(C), or crit(E){\rm crit}(E) is not a cardinal in 𝒱2[G,G]\mathscr{V}_{2}[G,G^{\prime}],

if there is such an EE, and GαP=G^{P}_{\alpha}=\emptyset otherwise. If there is P𝒫P\in\mathscr{P} such that GαP=G^{P}_{\alpha}=\emptyset and b𝒯αPb^{\mathcal{T}^{P}_{\alpha}} does not drop below the image of P|lh(DP)P|{\rm lh}(D^{P}) and γαPlh(GαP)\gamma^{P}_{\alpha}\leq{\rm lh}(G^{P^{\prime}}_{\alpha}) for all PP^{\prime} such that GαPG^{P^{\prime}}_{\alpha}\neq\emptyset, then we stop the construction, and set ι=α\iota=\alpha, and 𝒯P=𝒯αP\mathcal{T}^{P}=\mathcal{T}^{P}_{\alpha} for all PP. Otherwise, let ξα=minP𝒫lh(GαP)\xi_{\alpha}=\min_{P\in\mathscr{P}}{\rm lh}(G^{P}_{\alpha}), and set EαP=GαPE^{P}_{\alpha}=G^{P}_{\alpha} if lh(GαP)=ξα{\rm lh}(G^{P}_{\alpha})=\xi_{\alpha}, and EαP=E^{P}_{\alpha}=\emptyset otherwise. Let γ\gamma be least such that either γ+1=lh(𝒯αP)\gamma+1={\rm lh}(\mathcal{T}^{P}_{\alpha}) or ξα<lh(Eγ𝒯αP)\xi_{\alpha}<{\rm lh}(E^{\mathcal{T}^{P}_{\alpha}}_{\gamma}), and set 𝒯α+1P=𝒯αP(γ+1)^EαP\mathcal{T}^{P}_{\alpha+1}=\mathcal{T}^{P}_{\alpha}{\upharpoonright}(\gamma+1)\ \widehat{\ }\ \left<E^{P}_{\alpha}\right> (as a 0-maximal tree, with last extender used being EαPE^{P}_{\alpha}, which might be empty).

Now suppose we have defined 𝒯αP\mathcal{T}^{P}_{\alpha} for all α<η\alpha<\eta and P𝒫P\in\mathscr{P}, where η\eta is a limit. Let ξ=lim infα<ηξα\xi=\liminf_{\alpha<\eta}\xi_{\alpha}. Then 𝒯ηP\mathcal{T}^{P}_{\eta} is the natural lim inf of the sequence 𝒯αPα<η\left<\mathcal{T}^{P}_{\alpha}\right>_{\alpha<\eta}. That is, Eγ𝒯ηP=EE^{\mathcal{T}^{P}_{\eta}}_{\gamma}=E iff lh(E)<ξ{\rm lh}(E)<\xi and eventually all α<η\alpha<\eta have Eγ𝒯αP=EE^{\mathcal{T}^{P}_{\alpha}}_{\gamma}=E, and 𝒯ηP\mathcal{T}^{P}_{\eta} is via ΣP\Sigma_{P}, and has successor length. This determines 𝒯ηP\mathcal{T}^{P}_{\eta}.

This determines the entire construction. The first claim is very much like in the proof of Lemma 4.12.4:

Claim 1.

We have:

  1. 1.

    Each 𝒯αP\mathcal{T}^{P}_{\alpha} is 0-maximal on PP, and if b𝒯αPb^{\mathcal{T}^{P}_{\alpha}} drops below the image of P|lh(DP)P|{\rm lh}(D^{P}) then KαPK^{P}_{\alpha} is active, so GαPG^{P}_{\alpha}\neq\emptyset.

  2. 2.

    ι<\iota<\infty.

  3. 3.

    Therefore there is P𝒫P^{\prime}\in\mathscr{P} such that b𝒯ιPb^{\mathcal{T}^{P^{\prime}}_{\iota}} does not drop below the image of P|lh(DP)P^{\prime}|{\rm lh}(D^{P^{\prime}}).

Claim 2.

For every P𝒫P\in\mathscr{P}, b𝒯Pb^{\mathcal{T}^{P}} does not drop below the image of P|lh(DP)P|{\rm lh}(D^{P}), and j𝒯P(δP)=j𝒯P(δP)j^{\mathcal{T}^{P}}(\delta^{P})=j^{\mathcal{T}^{P^{\prime}}}(\delta^{P^{\prime}}).

Proof.

Because b𝒯ιPb^{\mathcal{T}^{P^{\prime}}_{\iota}} does not drop below the image of P|lh(DP)P^{\prime}|{\rm lh}(D^{P^{\prime}}), and j𝒯P(δP)j^{\mathcal{T}^{P^{\prime}}}(\delta^{P^{\prime}}) is a limit of measurables of KιPK^{P^{\prime}}_{\iota}, and GιP=G^{P^{\prime}}_{\iota}=\emptyset, j𝒯P(δP)j^{\mathcal{T}^{P^{\prime}}}(\delta^{P^{\prime}}) must be a limit cardinal of 𝒱2[G,G]\mathscr{V}_{2}[G,G^{\prime}]. Therefore every 𝒯P\mathcal{T}^{P} uses cofinally many non-empty extenders indexed below j𝒯P(δP)=ξ=lim infα<ιξαj^{\mathcal{T}^{P^{\prime}}}(\delta^{P^{\prime}})=\xi=\liminf_{\alpha<\iota}\xi_{\alpha}, ξ\xi is a limit cardinal of M𝒯PM^{\mathcal{T}^{P}}_{\infty}, and note that (C,Cι)(C,C_{\iota}) is generic over M(𝒯P)M(\mathcal{T}^{P}) for its extender algebra at ξ\xi, since ξlh(GιP)\xi\leq{\rm lh}(G^{P}_{\iota}) if GιPG^{P}_{\iota}\neq\emptyset.

Now suppose that b𝒯Pb^{\mathcal{T}^{P}} drops below the image of P|lh(DP)P|{\rm lh}(D^{P}), or j𝒯P(δP)>ξj^{\mathcal{T}^{P}}(\delta^{P})>\xi. Let QM𝒯PQ\trianglelefteq M^{\mathcal{T}^{P}}_{\infty} be the Q-structure for ξ\xi. It is straightforward to see that QQ does not overlap ξ\xi, and note that we can compare QQ versus U=Ult(P,F(M𝒯P))U=\mathrm{Ult}(P^{\prime},F(M^{\mathcal{T}^{P^{\prime}}}_{\infty})) as premice Q+Q^{+} and U+U^{+} over (M(𝒯P),M(𝒯P))(M(\mathcal{T}^{P}),M(\mathcal{T}^{P^{\prime}})), so by MswswM_{\mathrm{swsw}}-likeness, it follows that Q+U+Q^{+}\triangleleft U^{+}. Expanding U+U^{+} to U+[C,Cι]U^{+}[C,C_{\iota}], where ξ\xi is still regular, we can now argue like in the proof of Claim 1 of the proof of Lemma 4.12.4 for a contradiction. (Although 𝒯PU+[P|δP]\mathcal{T}^{P}\in U^{+}[P|\delta^{P}], we work in U+[C,Cι]U^{+}[C,C_{\iota}] because the reasons for the extenders used in 𝒯P\mathcal{T}^{P} are encoded into (C,Cι)(C,C_{\iota}), and we need this to obtain the contradiction.) ∎

So M𝒯PM^{\mathcal{T}^{P}}_{\infty} is active with an image EPE^{P} of DPD^{P}, and EPE^{P} is PP-total with crit(EP)=κ0P{\rm crit}(E^{P})=\kappa_{0}^{P}. Let UP=Ult(P,EP)U_{P}=\mathrm{Ult}(P,E^{P}). Then ξ\xi is a strong cutpoint of UP,UPU_{P},U_{P^{\prime}}, and both extend to premice over (UP|ξ,UP|ξ)(U_{P}|\xi,U_{P^{\prime}}|\xi). So we can simultaneously compare all UPU_{P} above ξ\xi, modulo this generic equivalence. (With a simple instance of normalization, the resulting trees can easily be rearranged as trees on the phalanxes Φ(𝒯P)\Phi(\mathcal{T}^{P}).) This produces a final iterate WPW_{P} of PP, with WP=ξWPW_{P}=^{*}_{\xi}W_{P^{\prime}}, ξ\xi is Woodin in WPW_{P} and ξ<κ0WP\xi<\kappa_{0}^{W_{P}}.

Claim 3.

𝒱1WP=𝒱1WP\mathscr{V}_{1}^{W_{P}}=\mathscr{V}_{1}^{W_{P^{\prime}}} for all P,P𝒫P,P^{\prime}\in\mathscr{P}.

Proof.

By §4.5, 𝒱1=𝒱1M\mathscr{V}_{1}=\mathscr{V}_{1}^{M} depends only on the equivalence class \mathscr{E}. So the corresponding fact holds for WPW_{P}. But we can take G,GColl(ω,<κ0)G,G^{\prime}\subseteq\mathrm{Coll}(\omega,{<\kappa_{0}}) which are WP,WPW_{P},W_{P^{\prime}}-generic respectively with WP[G]=^WP[G]W_{P}[G]\ \widehat{=}\ W_{P^{\prime}}[G^{\prime}], and then WP=WP\mathscr{E}^{W_{P}}=\mathscr{E}^{W_{P^{\prime}}}, which suffices. ∎

Now let 𝒱\mathscr{V} be a λ\lambda-candidate and P=P𝒱P=P_{\mathscr{V}}, so 𝒱1=𝒱1P\mathscr{V}\downarrow 1=\mathscr{V}_{1}^{P}. Note that 𝒯P^EP^𝒰P\mathcal{T}_{P}\ \widehat{\ }\ \left<E_{P}\right>\ \widehat{\ }\ \mathcal{U}_{P}, after normalization, is translatable, where 𝒰P\mathcal{U}_{P} is the tree leading from UPU_{P} to WPW_{P}. Let 𝒯𝒱1\mathcal{T}_{\mathscr{V}\downarrow 1} on 𝒱1=𝒱1P{\mathscr{V}\downarrow 1}=\mathscr{V}_{1}^{P} be its (short-normal) translation on 𝒱1{\mathscr{V}\downarrow 1}. Then M𝒯𝒱=𝒱1WPM^{\mathcal{T}_{\mathscr{V}}}_{\infty}=\mathscr{V}_{1}^{W_{P}}, which by the previous claim is independent of 𝒱\mathscr{V}. So the trees 𝒯𝒱1\mathcal{T}_{\mathscr{V}\downarrow 1} iterate the various 𝒱1\mathscr{V}\downarrow 1 to a common model 𝒱1\mathscr{V}_{1}^{*}.

Let 𝒯𝒱1=𝒯0^𝒯1\mathcal{T}_{\mathscr{V}\downarrow 1}=\mathcal{T}_{0}\ \widehat{\ }\ \mathcal{T}_{1} where 𝒯0\mathcal{T}_{0} is based on 𝒱|δ1𝒱=(𝒱1)|δ1𝒱1\mathscr{V}|\delta_{1}^{\mathscr{V}}=(\mathscr{V}\downarrow 1)|\delta_{1}^{\mathscr{V}\downarrow 1}, and 𝒯1\mathcal{T}_{1} is on M𝒯0M^{\mathcal{T}_{0}}_{\infty}, and is above δ1M𝒯0=δ1𝒱1\delta_{1}^{M^{\mathcal{T}_{0}}_{\infty}}=\delta_{1}^{\mathscr{V}_{1}^{*}}. Then 𝒯0\mathcal{T}_{0} translates to a tree 𝒰0\mathcal{U}_{0} on 𝒱\mathscr{V}, and M𝒯0=M𝒰01M^{\mathcal{T}_{0}}_{\infty}={M^{\mathcal{U}_{0}}_{\infty}\downarrow 1}. Now 𝒯1\mathcal{T}_{1} essentially translates to a tree 𝒰1\mathcal{U}_{1} on M𝒰0M^{\mathcal{U}_{0}}_{\infty}. The extenders used in 𝒰1\mathcal{U}_{1} are just those with indices those used in 𝒯1\mathcal{T}_{1}, together with 1 further 11-long extender, which is an image of e1(M𝒰0)e_{1}(M^{\mathcal{U}_{0}}_{\infty}). That is, let α0=0\alpha_{0}=0, and let α1\alpha_{1} be least such that [0,α1]𝒯0[0,\alpha_{1}]_{\mathcal{T}_{0}} is non-dropping and κ1+Mα1𝒯0<lh(Eα1𝒯0)\kappa_{1}^{+M^{\mathcal{T}_{0}}_{\alpha_{1}}}<{\rm lh}(E^{\mathcal{T}_{0}}_{\alpha_{1}}). Then 𝒰1(α1+1)\mathcal{U}_{1}{\upharpoonright}(\alpha_{1}+1) is a direct translation of 𝒯1\mathcal{T}_{1}, though note that if it is non-trivial, it drops in model immediately to M𝒰0||γ1M𝒰0M^{\mathcal{U}_{0}}_{\infty}||\gamma_{1}^{M^{\mathcal{U}_{0}}_{\infty}}, or some segment thereof. Then, 𝒰1\mathcal{U}_{1} uses an extra extender; if α1=0\alpha_{1}=0 then Eα1𝒰1=e1(M𝒰0)E^{\mathcal{U}_{1}}_{\alpha_{1}}=e_{1}(M^{\mathcal{U}_{0}}_{\infty}), and otherwise Eα1𝒰1=F(M𝒰0)E^{\mathcal{U}_{1}}_{\alpha_{1}}=F(M^{\mathcal{U}_{0}}_{\infty}) (which is an image of e1(M𝒰0)e_{1}(M^{\mathcal{U}_{0}}_{\infty})). This results in Mα1+1𝒰1=𝒱2(Mα1𝒯1)M^{\mathcal{U}_{1}}_{\alpha_{1}+1}=\mathscr{V}_{2}(M^{\mathcal{T}_{1}}_{\alpha_{1}}). After this, noting that 𝒯1[α1,)\mathcal{T}_{1}{\upharpoonright}[\alpha_{1},\infty) is 1-translatable on Mα1𝒯1M^{\mathcal{T}_{1}}_{\alpha_{1}} (in particular, uses no 0-long extenders), we set 𝒰1[α+1,)\mathcal{U}_{1}{\upharpoonright}[\alpha+1,\infty) to be its 1-translation. Write 𝒰𝒱=𝒰0^𝒰1\mathcal{U}_{\mathscr{V}}=\mathcal{U}_{0}\ \widehat{\ }\ \mathcal{U}_{1}.

So we end up with M𝒰𝒱=𝒱2(M𝒯𝒱)M^{\mathcal{U}_{\mathscr{V}}}_{\infty}=\mathscr{V}_{2}(M^{\mathcal{T}_{\mathscr{V}}}_{\infty}), but M𝒯𝒱M^{\mathcal{T}_{\mathscr{V}}}_{\infty} was independent of 𝒱\mathscr{V}. So write 𝒱2\mathscr{V}_{2}^{*} for this common iterate of the λ\lambda-candidates 𝒱\mathscr{V}.

Using the strategies ΣP\Sigma_{P}, we can define 𝒰𝒱\mathcal{U}_{\mathscr{V}} uniformly in 𝒱\mathscr{V}. So let Γ\Gamma be the proper class of all ordinals fixed by all the iteration maps i𝒰𝒱i^{\mathcal{U}_{\mathscr{V}}}. Let 𝒱¯2=cHull1𝒱2(Γ)\bar{\mathscr{V}}_{2}=\mathrm{cHull}_{1}^{\mathscr{V}_{2}^{*}}(\Gamma) and π:𝒱¯2𝒱2\pi:\bar{\mathscr{V}}_{2}\to\mathscr{V}_{2}^{*} the uncollapse map. Since rg(i𝒰𝒱2)rg(π)\mathrm{rg}(i_{\mathcal{U}_{\mathscr{V}_{2}}})\subseteq\mathrm{rg}(\pi), this determines an elementary π:𝒱¯2𝒱2\pi:\bar{\mathscr{V}}_{2}\to\mathscr{V}_{2} by factoring. But 𝒱2\mathscr{V}_{2} is a set-ground of 𝒱2[G,G]\mathscr{V}_{2}[G,G^{\prime}], so by [5], 𝒱¯2=𝒱2\bar{\mathscr{V}}_{2}=\mathscr{V}_{2} and π=id\pi=\mathrm{id}.

So we have defined 𝒱2\mathscr{V}_{2} over the universe of 𝒱2[G,G]\mathscr{V}_{2}[G,G^{\prime}] from the parameter λ\lambda, and so by homogeneity, in fact over the universe of 𝒱2[G]\mathscr{V}_{2}[G] from λ\lambda. The uniformity then gives that we can define 𝒱2\mathscr{V}_{2} over the universe of any set-generic extension of 𝒱2\mathscr{V}_{2}, from no parameter.

We can now easily complete the proof of the theorem. Part 4 was just established above. Part 1: Let U2U_{2} be the universe of 𝒱2\mathscr{V}_{2} and GColl(ω,λ)G\subseteq\mathrm{Coll}(\omega,\lambda) be 𝒱2\mathscr{V}_{2}-generic, where λδ1𝒱2\lambda\geq\delta_{1}^{\mathscr{V}_{2}}. It now easily follows that U2HODU2[G]U_{2}\subseteq\mathrm{HOD}^{U_{2}[G]}, so actually U2=HODU2[G]U_{2}=\mathrm{HOD}^{U_{2}[G]}. And if HH is Coll(ω,λ)\mathrm{Coll}(\omega,\lambda)-generic over MM, then since MM is an 𝕃𝒱2\mathbb{L}^{\mathscr{V}_{2}}-extension of 𝒱2\mathscr{V}_{2}, it follows that U2=HODM[H]U_{2}=\mathrm{HOD}^{M[H]}. Part 2: If WU2W\subseteq U_{2} is a ground of U2U_{2}, then we get HODU2[G]W2\mathrm{HOD}^{U_{2}[G]}\subseteq W_{2} if λ\lambda is sufficiently large, so U2WU_{2}\subseteq W, so U2=WU_{2}=W. Part 3: The fact that U2U_{2} is the mantle of all set-generic extensions of U2U_{2} now follows from the set-directedness of set-grounds. ∎

Corollary 5.34.

We have:

  1. 1.

    The κ1\kappa_{1}-mantle κ1M\mathscr{M}^{M}_{\kappa_{1}} of MM is the universe of 𝒱2\mathscr{V}_{2}, so κ1\kappa_{1} is the least ordinal with this property.

  2. 2.

    If GColl(ω,<κ1)G\subseteq\mathrm{Coll}(\omega,{<\kappa_{1}}) is MM-generic then HODM[G]\mathrm{HOD}^{M[G]} is the universe of 𝒱2\mathscr{V}_{2}.

Proof.

Note that 𝒱2HODM[G]κ1M\mathscr{V}_{2}\subseteq\mathrm{HOD}^{M[G]}\subseteq\mathscr{M}^{M}_{\kappa_{1}}, using Theorem 5.8. So we just need to see that κ1M𝒱2\mathscr{M}^{M}_{\kappa_{1}}\subseteq\mathscr{V}_{2}. Let XX be a set of ordinals in κ1M\mathscr{M}^{M}_{\kappa_{1}}. Let E𝔼ME\in\mathbb{E}^{M} be MM-total with crit(E)=κ1{\rm crit}(E)=\kappa_{1}, and U=Ult(M,E)U=\mathrm{Ult}(M,E). Then j(X)j(κ1)Uj(X)\in\mathscr{M}^{U}_{j(\kappa_{1})} and jsupX𝒱2j{\upharpoonright}\sup X\in\mathscr{V}_{2}, so it suffices to find a <j(κ1){<j(\kappa_{1})}-ground WW of UU with W𝒱2W\subseteq\mathscr{V}_{2}. But this can be done like in the proof of Theorem 4.8, or as follows:575757The method used here was actually the method used in the original proof of Theorem 4.8. Let WW be the result of the P-construction of UU over 𝒱2|γ1𝒱2\mathscr{V}_{2}|\gamma_{1}^{\mathscr{V}_{2}} (in the style of that used to construct 𝒱2\mathscr{V}_{2}). Note that (𝒱1|κ1,M|κ0)(\mathscr{V}_{1}|\kappa_{1},M|\kappa_{0}) is generic over WW for the two-step forcing iteration given by 𝕃𝒱2\mathbb{L}^{\mathscr{V}_{2}} followed by 𝕃𝒱1\mathbb{L}^{\mathscr{V}_{1}}, and W[𝒱1|κ1,M|κ0]=^UW[\mathscr{V}_{1}|\kappa_{1},M|\kappa_{0}]\ \widehat{=}\ U. So WW is a <j(κ1){<j(\kappa_{1})}-ground of UU. But W𝒱2W\subseteq\mathscr{V}_{2}, since W||lh(E)=𝒱2|lh(E)W||{\rm lh}(E)=\mathscr{V}_{2}|{\rm lh}(E), and we can inductively compute the extender sequence of WW above lh(E){\rm lh}(E) using E𝒱2E{\upharpoonright}\mathscr{V}_{2} and Ult(𝒱2,E𝒱2)=𝒱2U\mathrm{Ult}(\mathscr{V}_{2},E{\upharpoonright}\mathscr{V}_{2})=\mathscr{V}_{2}^{U}. ∎

Acknowledgements

Schindler gratefully acknowledges support by the DFG grant SCHI 484/8-1, “Die Geologie Innerer Modelle.” Schindler and Schlutzenberg gratefully acknowledge partial support by the Deutsche Forschungsgemeinschaft (DFG, German Research Foundation) under Germany’s Excellence Strategy EXC 2044390685587, Mathematics Münster: Dynamics–Geometry–Structure. Schlutzenberg teilweise gefördert durch die Deutsche Forschungsgemeinschaft (DFG) – Projektnummer 445387776. Schlutzenberg partly supported by the Deutsche Forschungsgemeinschaft (DFG, German Research Foundation) – project number 445387776.

References

  • [1] E. Closson. The Solovay Sequence in Derived Models Associated to Mice. PhD thesis, University of California, Berkeley, 2008.
  • [2] Gunter Fuchs, Joel David Hamkins, and Jonas Reitz. Set theoretic geology. Annals of Pure and Applied Logic, 166(4):464–501, 2015.
  • [3] Gunter Fuchs and Ralf Schindler. Inner model theoretic geology. Journal of Symbolic Logic, 81(3):972–996, 2016.
  • [4] Haim Gaifman. Elementary embeddings of models of set-theory and certain subtheories. In Axiomatic set theory (Proc. Sympos. Pure Math., Vol. XIII, Part II, Univ. California, Los Angeles, Calif., 1967), pages 33–102. Amer. Math. Soc., Providence, R. I., 1974.
  • [5] Joel David Hamkins, Greg Kirmayer, and Norman Lewis Perlmutter. Generalizations of the kunen inconsistency. Annals of Pure and Applied Logic, 163(12), 2012.
  • [6] Richard Laver. Certain very large cardinals are not created in small forcing extensions. Annals of Pure and Applied Logic, 149(1–3):1–6, 2007.
  • [7] G. Sargsyan. Hod Mice and the Mouse Set Conjecture, volume 236 of Memoirs of the American Mathematical Society. American Mathematical Society, 2015.
  • [8] Grigor Sargsyan and Ralf Schindler. Varsovian models I. Journal of Symbolic Logic, 83(2):496–528, 2018.
  • [9] Ralf Schindler. A note on the <κ{<\kappa} mantle. Handwritten, https://ivv5hpp.uni-muenster.de/u/rds/kappa_mantle.pdf.
  • [10] Ralf Schindler. Varsovian models II (parts 1–6). Handwritten, https://ivv5hpp.uni-muenster.de/u/rds/VM2.pdf, https://ivv5hpp.uni-muenster.de/u/rds/VM2_2.pdf, https://ivv5hpp.uni-muenster.de/u/rds/VM2_5.pdf, https://ivv5hpp.uni-muenster.de/u/rds/VM2_6.pdf, https://ivv5hpp.uni-muenster.de/u/rds/VM2_7.pdf, https://ivv5hpp.uni-muenster.de/u/rds/VM2_8.pdf.
  • [11] Ralf Schindler. The long extender algebra. Archive for Mathematical Logic, 57:73–82, 2018.
  • [12] Ralf Schindler and John Steel. The self-iterability of L[E]L[E]. Journal of Symbolic Logic, 74(3):751–779, 2009.
  • [13] Farmer Schlutzenberg. *-translation and Varsovian models. To appear.
  • [14] Farmer Schlutzenberg. Background construction for λ\lambda-indexed mice. arXiv:2101.00889v2.
  • [15] Farmer Schlutzenberg. Full normalization for transfinite stacks. arXiv:2102.03359v3.
  • [16] Farmer Schlutzenberg. Local mantles of L[x]L[x]. arXiv:2103.12925v2.
  • [17] Farmer Schlutzenberg. Ordinal definability in L[𝔼]L[\mathbb{E}]. arXiv:2012.07185v2.
  • [18] Farmer Schlutzenberg. Measures in mice. PhD thesis, University of California, Berkeley, 2007. arXiv:1301.4702v1.
  • [19] Farmer Schlutzenberg. Θ\Theta is woodin in HOD” directly from mice. Available at https://www.math.uci.edu/~mzeman/CMI/talk-schlutzenberg-4.pdf, 2016.
  • [20] Farmer Schlutzenberg. Iterability for (transfinite) stacks. Journal of Mathematical Logic, 21(2), 2021.
  • [21] Farmer Schlutzenberg. Choice principles in local mantles. Mathematical Logic Quarterly, 68(3):264–278, 2022.
  • [22] Farmer Schlutzenberg. The definability of the extender sequence 𝔼\mathbb{E} from 𝔼1\mathbb{E}\upharpoonright\aleph_{1} in L[𝔼]L[\mathbb{E}]. The Journal of Symbolic Logic, 89(2):427–459, 2024.
  • [23] John R. Steel. Local HOD computation. 2016. Handwritten notes, available at https://math.berkeley.edu/~steel.
  • [24] John R. Steel. A Comparison Process for Mouse Pairs. Cambridge University Press, 2022.
  • [25] Toshimichi Usuba. The downward directed grounds hypothesis and very large cardinals. Journal of Mathematical Logic, 17(2), 2017.
  • [26] Toshimichi Usuba. Extendible cardinals and the mantle. Archive for Mathematical Logic, 58:71–75, 2019.
  • [27] W. Hugh Woodin. Email to the second author. Personal communication, dated February 1, 2016.
  • [28] W. Hugh Woodin. The continuum hypothesis, the generic-multiverse of sets, and the ω\omega-conjecture. In Set theory, arithmetic, and foundations of mathematics: theorems, philosophies, volume 36 of Lecture Notes in Logic, pages 13–42. Cambridge University Press, 2011.